Skip to main content

Risk, Uncertainty, and the Dimensions of Technological Rationality

  • Chapter
New Perspectives on Technology, Values, and Ethics

Part of the book series: Boston Studies in the Philosophy and History of Science ((BSPS,volume 315))

Abstract

This paper show that risk and uncertainty are closely related to technological rationality due to importance of the time horizon over which the consequences of technology are felt, the collateral effects of actions result of technological rationality, and the irreversibility of the consequences of many of these actions. Rationality is no longer merely a question of efficacy and effectiveness, rational procedure in technology has to consider all the variables in play including those related to the dangerous effects of technology and the risks and uncertainty they generate.

Accordingly, it is argued that risk and uncertainty consequences place technology in the realm of public and social life, and hence in the field of politics and moral. Technological rationality cannot be merely reduced to a question of efficacy or effectiveness since its consequences insert technology in the sphere of responsibility. Therefore, technological rationality is not just a question of means: it is also a question of ends. Evaluative rationality and means-ends (instrumental) rationality are two dimensions of technological rationality.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

eBook
USD 16.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 54.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 54.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. 1.

    According to Quintanilla, his strategy is to measure technical efficiency–on the basis more than economic efficiency, the thermodynamic efficiency–as: “a function of the level of adjustment between results and objectives of an action.” Quintanilla (2005), p. 220.

  2. 2.

    As is well known different theoreticians have characterized technological rationality in terms that go far beyond this conception taking into account external rationality and rationality of ends, see for instance, Gonzalez (1998); Mitcham (2005), p. 788; Rescher (1988); and Agazzi (2004).

  3. 3.

    This has been pointed out by Herbert Simon characterization of substantive rationality. He considers that this is the case because in conditions of certainty, one of the options always emerges as objectively preferable to the others, and this occurs almost deterministically; Simon (1976). See also Simon (1978).

  4. 4.

    Gonzalez (1998), p. 113. For an analysis of economic rationality in technology, see Gonzalez (1998), pp. 95–115. In this work, he states that “economic rationality may serve as a link between scientific rationality and technological rationality,” Gonzalez (1998), p. 97.

  5. 5.

    To technological determinism see Gonzalez (2005), p. 30. As argued Gonzalez (2005), pp. 31–32, Niiniluoto holds an interesting middle position between determinism and voluntarism. Also, see Niiniluoto (1994, 1997).

  6. 6.

    For moral judgement of science and technology, see Agazzi (2004), pp. 127–139.

  7. 7.

    Nuclear waste continues to be hazardous for a long time; the plutonium in nuclear power plants will always enable the construction of nuclear weapons; genetic defects and alterations may last until the end of time; the heating of the atmosphere seems to be irreversible, etc. For an analysis of scientific progress and technological innovation, see Gonzalez (1997).

  8. 8.

    The basic idea is that many events occur unintentionally, they are the by-products of actions. They may be positive (A. Smith’s invisible hand) or negative (perverse effects). For more on this subject, see Elster (1988). Also see, Gómez (2002).

  9. 9.

    See the interesting proposal for public risk assessment and its legal regulation by Jasanoff (2001). See also Agazzi (2004), pp. 204–205.

  10. 10.

    Mayo (1997), p. 227. Given that there is more than one scientifically acceptable response to these questions, there is more than one plausible choice.

  11. 11.

    In experiments with animals have been shown that formaldehyde causes cancer in concentrations greater than 6 ppm in the air breathed.

  12. 12.

    That is what Beck terms the “the hazardousness of a risk” the risk of the risk. See Beck (1992), p. 29.

  13. 13.

    Only USA, Japan and UK maintain preventive regulations.

  14. 14.

    According to Bradbury, risk management requires the development of institutional procedures for structuring between two different perspectives on risk, the scientific and the social views. Cf. Bradbury (1989), p. 394.

  15. 15.

    These points have been developed by Beck (1992, 1998).

  16. 16.

    Beck (1992); the author has developed these issues extensively.

  17. 17.

    See the interesting Gonzalez work on the role of values in the configuration of technology: Gonzalez (2008, 2016).

  18. 18.

    For these questions see Balmer (2013).

  19. 19.

    Rescher distinguishes between the two forms of rationality in relation to science; see Rescher (1988), pp. 2–3.

  20. 20.

    For the relationship between science, technology and politics see Gómez and Balmer (2013). Also at the cultural sphere, see Mitcham (1980).

  21. 21.

    According to Beck. See Beck (1992), pp. 36, 48–49, 52 (among others). See also Beck (1998).

  22. 22.

    This is a key idea in Beck’s analysis of risk society; see Beck (1992), passim, and Beck (1998).

  23. 23.

    According to Rescher, the three spheres of the technological rationality are: The cognitive, the practical and the evaluative ones. See Rescher (1988).

  24. 24.

    Both are forms of rational choice in contexts of uncertainty.

  25. 25.

    Elster (1983), p. 203. This author points out that an infinite number multiplied by any positive quantity (no matter how small), is still infinite.

  26. 26.

    Prudential recommendations are located within the framework of consequentialist ethics based on the principle of responsibility that is today fairly popular; for more on this subject, see Agazzi (1999).

  27. 27.

    In the US in the 1980s.

  28. 28.

    In relation to the precautionary principle, see Foster et al. (2000). See also Gómez (2003).

  29. 29.

    The solutions to these situations are of two types: Strengthening compliance of the international agreements with sanctions and/or rewards–which is not very feasible at certain levels since it would be required strong transnational organizations which carry out this task–or appeal to moral reasons about what should be done independently of what others do–which has obvious limitations.

  30. 30.

    We forget, for example, that the genetic manipulation of food often renders it cheaper, improves its quality and extends the areas in which it can be grown, which has important implications for the developing world, it also provides a solution to the problem of food security in the world and it renders plants more pest-resistant, thus lessening the need for pesticides; that nuclear power is the cheapest and least polluting energy source currently available; and that biotechnologies have important medical applications, etc.

  31. 31.

    The announcement appeared in the Spanish newspaper El País on 24 January 1999.

  32. 32.

    According to van de Poel, technologies are inherently normative and include instrumental and final values. The technical function of certain technologies is to prevent certain evils and dangers being instrumental regarding moral values. The example is a seawall for preventing flooding and to achieve security for people as part of its function. See van de Poel (2016).

  33. 33.

    Kitcher approach is inspired by the social choice theory related to social welfare functions, therefore, the final result, which is chosen, must be an expression of what everyone prefers and choose. For Longino decisions have to be taken in discursive interactive processes, egalitarian and plurals which produce a consensus as result. See, Kitcher (2002a), (b); and Longino (2002a, b).

  34. 34.

    See the characterization of internal and external values in technology in Gonzalez (2016).

  35. 35.

    As Simon has argued from an evolutionary approach to technological rationality. See Simon (1983), p. 72. For this topic, see Neira (2012), p. 345.

References

  • Agazzi, E. 1999. Límites éticos del quehacer científico y tecnológico. In Ciencia y valores éticos, ed. W. J. Gonzalez, monographic issue of Arbor 162: 241–263.

    Google Scholar 

  • Agazzi, E. 2004. Right, wrong and science. The ethical dimensions of the techno-scientific enterprise. Amsterdam: Rodopi.

    Google Scholar 

  • Balmer, B. 2013. Secrecy and science. A historical sociology of biological and chemical warfare. Burlington: Ashgate.

    Google Scholar 

  • Beck, U. 1992. Risk society: Towards a new modernity. London: Sage.

    Google Scholar 

  • Beck, U. 1998. World risk society. Cambridge: Polity Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bradbury, J. 1989. The policy implication of differing concepts of risk. Science, Technology and Human Values 14(4): 380–399.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Carson, C. 1962. Silent spring. Boston: Houghton Mifflin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ellul, J. 1964. The technological society. New York: Vintage.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ellul, J. 1980. The ethics of nonpower. In Ethics in an age of pervasive technology, ed. M. Kranzberg, 204–212. Boulder: Westview.

    Google Scholar 

  • Elster, J. 1983. Explaining technological change. Studies in rationality and social changes. Cambridge/London/New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Elster, J. 1988. Sour grapes: Studies in the subversion of rationality. Cambridge/London/New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Foster, K.R., P. Vecchia, and M.H. Repacholi. 2000. Risk management: Science and the precautionary principle. Science 288: 979–981.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gómez, A. 2001. Racionalidad, riesgo e incertidumbre en el desarrollo tecnológico. In Filosofía de la Tecnología, ed. J.A. López Cerezo, J.L. Luján, and E.M. García Palacios, 169–187. Madrid: OEI.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gómez, A. 2002. Estimación de riesgo, incertidumbre y valores en Tecnología. In Tecnología, civilización y barbarie, ed. J.M. De Cozar, 63–85. Barcelona: Anthropos.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gómez, A. 2003. El principio de precaución en la gestión internacional del riesgo. Política y Sociedad 40(3): 113–130.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gómez, A. 2007. Racionalidad y responsabilidad en Tecnología. In Los laberintos de la responsabilidad, ed. R. Aramayo and M.J. Guerra, 271–290. Madrid: Plaza y Janés.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gómez, A., and B. Balmer. 2013. Ciencia y política una cuestión de fronteras. In Estudios políticos de la ciencia. Políticas y desarrollo científico en el siglo XX, ed. A. Gómez and A. Fco Canales, 15–34. Madrid: Plaza y Valdés.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gonzalez, W.J. 1997. Progreso científico e innovación tecnológica: La ‘Tecnociencia’ y el problema de las relaciones entre Filosofía de la Ciencia y Filosofía de la Tecnología. Arbor 157(620): 261–283.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gonzalez, W.J. 1998. Racionalidad científica y racionalidad tecnológica: La mediación de la racionalidad económica. Agora, papeles de Filosofía 17(2): 95–115.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gonzalez, W.J. 1999a. Valores económicos en la configuración de la Tecnología. Argumentos de Razón Técnica 2: 69–96.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gonzalez, W.J. 1999b. Ciencia y valores éticos: De la posibilidad de la Ética de la Ciencia al problema de la valoración ética de la Ciencia Básica. Arbor 162(638): 139–171.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gonzalez, W.J. 2005. The Philosophical Approach to Science, Technology and Society. In Science, technology and society: A philosophical perspective, ed. W.J. Gonzalez, 3–49. A Coruña: Netbiblo.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Gonzalez, W.J. 2008. Economic values in the configuration of science. In Epistemology and the social, Poznan studies in the philosophy of the sciences and the humanities, ed. E.G. Agazzi, J. Echeverría, and A. Gómez, 85–112. Amsterdam: Rodopi.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gonzalez, W.J. 2016. On the role of values in the configuration of technology: From axiology to ethics. In Technology, values, and ethics, Boston studies in the philosophy of science, ed. W.J. Gonzalez, 3–27. Dordrecht: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jasanoff, Sh. 2001. Ordering life: Law and the normalization of biotechnology. Politeia 17(62): 34–50.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jonas, H. 1979. The imperative of responsibility: In search of an ethics for the technological age. Chicago: Chicago University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kitcher, Ph. 2002a. The third way: Reflections on Helen Longino’s The Fate of Knowledge. Philosophy of Science 69(4): 549–559.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kitcher, Ph. 2002b. Reply to Helen Longino. Philosophy of Science 69(4): 569–572.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Longino, H. 2002a. Science and the common good: Thoughts on Philip Kitcher’s Science, Truth, and Democracy. Philosophy of Science 69(4): 560–568.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Longino, H. 2002b. Reply to Philip Kitcher. Philosophy of Science 69(4): 573–577.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mayo, D. 1997. Sociological versus meta scientific view of technological risk assessment. In Technology and values, ed. K. Shrader-Frechette and L. Westra, 217–250. Lanham: Rowman and Littlefield Publishers.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mitcham, C. 1980. Philosophy of technology. In A guide to the culture of science, technology and medicine, ed. P. Durbin, 282–363. New York: The Free Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mitcham, C. 2005. Technology and ethics. In Encyclopedia of 20th-century technology, vol. 2, ed. C.A. Hempstead, 785–789. New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mitcham, C. 2016. Rationality in technology and in ethics. In Technology, values, and ethics, Boston studies in the philosophy of science, ed. W.J. Gonzalez, 63–87. Dordrecht: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Neira, P. 2012. Análisis de la racionalidad tecnológica en Internet: De la caracterización filosófica de la Tecnología al estudio de las TICs. Dissertation, University of A Coruña, mimeo.

    Google Scholar 

  • Niiniluoto, I. 1994. Nature, man, and technology – Remarks on sustainable development. In The changing circumpolar north: Opportunities for academic development, vol. 6, ed. L. Heininen, 73–87. Rovaniemi: Arctic Centre Publications.

    Google Scholar 

  • Niiniluoto, I. 1997. Límites de la Tecnología. Arbor 157(620): 391–410.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Quintanilla, M.A. 2005. Tecnología un enfoque filosófico y otros ensayos de Filosofía de la Tecnología. Madrid: FCE.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rescher, N. 1988. Rationality. A philosophical inquiry into the nature and the rationale of reason. Oxford: Clarendon.

    Google Scholar 

  • Simon, H.A. 1976. From substantive to procedural rationality. In Method and appraisal in economics, ed. S.J. Latsis, 129–148. Cambridge/London/New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Simon, H.A. 1978. Rationality as process and product of thought. American Economic Review 68(2): 1–16.

    Google Scholar 

  • Simon, H.A. 1983. Reason and human affairs. Stanford: Stanford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tversky, A., and D. Kahneman. 1973. Availability: A heuristic for judging frequency and probability. Cognitive Psychology 5: 207–232.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tversky, A., and D. Kahneman. 1974. Judgment under uncertainty: Heuristics and biases. Science 185: 1124–1130.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tversky, A., and D. Kahneman. 1981. The framing of decisions and the psychology of choice. Science 211: 453–458.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • van de Poel, I. 2016. Values in engineering and technology. In Technology, values, and ethics, Boston studies in the philosophy of science, ed. W.J. Gonzalez, 29–46. Dordrecht: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

This paper has been written thanks to the support of the Spanish Ministry of Economy and Competitiveness, Research Project FFI2012-33998. I am very grateful to Wenceslao J. Gonzalez for his insightful comments and suggestions on earlier drafts of this paper. Thanks are extended to Brian Balmer for reading an earlier draft of this article.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Amparo Gómez .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2015 Springer International Publishing Switzerland

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Gómez, A. (2015). Risk, Uncertainty, and the Dimensions of Technological Rationality. In: Gonzalez, W. (eds) New Perspectives on Technology, Values, and Ethics. Boston Studies in the Philosophy and History of Science, vol 315. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-21870-0_6

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics