Skip to main content

An Empirical Method for the Study of Exemplar Explanations

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Empirical Philosophy of Science

Part of the book series: Studies in Applied Philosophy, Epistemology and Rational Ethics ((SAPERE,volume 21))

Abstract

The most common way of studying explanations in philosophy of science and science education is through case studies. Recently these have been supplemented with studies based on empirical methods. This chapter provides an empirical method for collecting and comparing exemplar explanations across scientific disciplines with the aim exposing possible qualitative differences between them. The method is based on the use of science textbooks as sources of explanations. I discuss a number of possible strategies for identifying explanations in these sources, and specify a set of reliable linguistic indicators that can be used for this purpose. A pilot study is presented to illustrate the method and its limitations.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

eBook
USD 16.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Hardcover Book
USD 54.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    Woody actually calls her method “quasi-empirical” (2004a, p. 13). This seems reasonable given that her empirical material is limited to just one textbook. However there is nothing semi-empirical about the methodology employed in the study.

  2. 2.

    Textbooks are not only particularly suited for studies of explanations to students, they are also more generally good sources of explanations. Indeed, anyone interested in widely accepted explanations should be interested in textbooks, since the explanations found in scientific articles are not necessarily uncontroversial. Furthermore textbooks are useful for a study (like Woody’s) that aims to answer why explanations are so important in scientific practice, because textbook explanations can provide clues as to why and how explanations are valuable to practitioners since one of the aims of a textbook is to show future practitioners how to use the tools of the discipline (Woody 2004a, p. 18).

  3. 3.

    See Chambliss (2001) for an example of a study of explanations based on assumptions about understanding.

  4. 4.

    A different kind of objection to this approach might also be raised: Even if it can be safely assumed that any good explanation will increase the reader’s understanding of the explanandum, this does not mean that a good explanation is necessary for an increase in understanding. Thus we will be making the fallacy of affirming the consequent if we claim to have found explanations by identifying passages that increases the readers understanding. Lipton (2009) has explored other sources of understanding (for instance thought experiments), and this potential objection could be overcome by simply assuming that Lipton’s list of sources of understanding is exhaustive. If a textbook passage increases the readers understanding and does not belong to one of the other sources of understanding on Lipton’s list, it can safely be assumed that an explanation has been found.

  5. 5.

    Rowan (1988) has also discussed the advantages and challenges related to the study of explanations through assumptions about either their function or their structure. She argues that if the purpose of the study is to improve teaching, then assumptions about the function of explanations is preferable, but unfortunately she does not give us any hints as to how the practical problems associated with this approach might be overcome.

  6. 6.

    Bearing in mind the possible objection raised in note 4 about the possibility of other sources of understanding.

  7. 7.

    The book was recommended to me by a lecturer in physical chemistry as the most rigorous presentation of chemical thermodynamics that he knew of.

  8. 8.

    The final instance also appears in the caption to a picture (Young and Freedman 2010, p. 564).

  9. 9.

    Furthermore, the physical format of the two books is quite different, so the number of words on a page with no equations or figures is about 50 % higher in University Physics than in Chemical Thermodynamics. Thus even if the key words were equally frequent in the two texts I would still have identified a more instances in University Physics than in Chemical Thermodynamics. One should thus be careful not to read too much into the absolute differences in the number of instances of any of the individual keywords between the two texts.

  10. 10.

    This makes it more abundant than the words ‘explain’ and ‘understand’ which appear 821 and 500 times respectively, but less abundant that the word ‘because’ which appears 1009 times. The word ‘how’ occurs 2140 times but as mentioned the majority of these appear in how-much-questions.

  11. 11.

    This type of questions is common in more recent introductory textbooks.

  12. 12.

    Assuming that there is data to be found. It may be that the reason why explanation seeking questions are so hard to find in more advanced textbooks is because they are not posed, but given the commonness of explanation seeking questions in everyday discourse and the consensus among philosophers and scientists that explanations are important in science I find that highly unlikely.

  13. 13.

    Chapters 3–4 in Mandl (1988) and Chaps. 8–9 in Griffiths (1999).

  14. 14.

    An alternative approach would be to interview practicing scientists and ask them what characterizes good explanations for students or what they think are the main differences between the explanations from their discipline and explanations from other disciplines. How useful such an approach would be is an empirical question, and I am not aware that it has ever been attempted.

References

  • Braaten, M., Windschitl, M.: Working toward a stronger conceptualization of scientific explanation for science education. Sci. Educ. 95, 639–669 (2011)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chambliss, M.: Analyzing science textbook materials to determine how “persuasive” they are. Theory Pract. 40, 255–264 (2001)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Collins, H.: Interactional expertise as a third kind of knowledge. Phenomenol. Cogn. Sci. 3, 125–143 (2004)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dagher, Z.: Methodological decisions in interpretive research: the case of teacher explanations. In: Gallagher, J. (ed.) Interpretive Research in Science Education, pp. 61–83. National Association for Research in Science Teaching (1991)

    Google Scholar 

  • Dagher, Z., Cossman, G.: Verbal explanations given by science teachers: their nature and implications. J. Res. Sci. Teach. 29, 361–374 (1992)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • De Regt, H.W., Leonelli, S., Eigner, K.: Scientific understanding: philosophical perspectives. University of Pittsburgh Press, Pittsburgh (2009)

    Google Scholar 

  • Draper, S.: What’s going on in everyday explanations. In: Antaki, C. (ed.) Analysing Everyday Explanation: A Casebook of Methods, pp. 15–32. Sage Publications, London (1988)

    Google Scholar 

  • Edgington, J.R., Barufaldi, J.P.: How research physicists and high-school physics teachers deal with the scientific explanation of a physical phenomenon. Paper Presented at the Annual Meeting of the National Association for Research in Science Teaching, San Francisco, CA, 22–25 Apr 1995

    Google Scholar 

  • Faye, J.: Explanation explained. Synthese 120, 61–75 (1999)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Friedman, M.: Explanation and scientific understanding. J. Philos. 71, 5–19 (1974)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Goddiksen, M.: Interdisciplinarity and explanation: how interdisciplinary education calls for a new approach to research on scientific explanations. In: Proceedings of the 12th Biennial IHPST Conference. http://archive.ihpst.net/2013-pittsburgh/conference-proceedings/ (2013)

  • Godfrey-Smith, P.: Theory and Reality: An Introduction to the Philosophy of Science. University of Chicago Press, Chicago (2003)

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Goodwin, W.: Explanation in organic chemistry. Ann. N. Y. Acad. Sci. 988, 141–153 (2003)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Griffiths, D.J.: Introduction to Electrodynamics, 3rd edn. Prentice Hall, Upper Saddle River (1999)

    Google Scholar 

  • Hempel, C.G.: Aspects of Scientific Explanation. The Free Press, New York (1965)

    Google Scholar 

  • Kirkwood, J.G., Oppenheim, I.: Chemical Thermodynamics. McGraw-Hill, New York (1961)

    Google Scholar 

  • Kuhn, T.S.: The structure of Scientific Revolutions, 3rd edn. University of Chicago Press, Chicago (1996)

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Lipton, P.: Understanding without explanation. In: de Regt, H.W., Leonelli, S., Eigner, K. (eds.) Scientific Understanding, pp. 43–64. University of Pittsburgh Press, Pittsburgh (2009)

    Google Scholar 

  • Machamer, P., Darden, L., Craver, C.: Thinking about mechanisms. Philos. Sci. 67, 1–25 (2000)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mahan, B.M., Myers, R.J.: University Chemistry, 4th edn. Benjamin/Cummings cop, Menlo Park, Calif (1987)

    Google Scholar 

  • Mandl, F.: Statistical Physics, 2nd edn. Wiley, Chichester (1988)

    Google Scholar 

  • McMullin, E.: Rationality and paradigm change in science. In: Horwich, P. (ed.) World changes: Thomas Kuhn and the Nature of Science. MIT Press, Cambridge (1993)

    Google Scholar 

  • Nersessian, N.J.: Opening the black box: cognitive science and history of science. Osiris 10, 194–211 (1995)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ogborn, J., Kress, G., Martins, I., McGillicuddy, K.: Explaining Science in the Classroom. Open University Press, London (1996)

    Google Scholar 

  • Overton, J.A.: “Explain” in scientific discourse. Synthese 190, 1383–1405 (2013)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Peker, D., Wallace, C.: Characterizing high school students’ written explanations in biology laboratories. Res. Sci. Educ. 41, 169–191 (2011)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rowan, K.E.: A contemporary theory of explanatory writing. Written Commun. 5, 23–56 (1988)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Salmon, W.C.: Why ask “why?”? An inquiry concerning scientific explanation. In: Salmon, W. (ed.) Causality and Explanation, pp. 125–142. Oxford University Press, New York (1998)

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Solomon, J.: Higher level understanding of the nature of science. Sch. Sci. Rev. 76, 15–22 (1995)

    Google Scholar 

  • Treagust, D., Harrison, A.: The genesis of effective scientific explanations for the classroom. In: Loughran, J.L. (ed.) Researching Teaching: Methodologies and Practices for Understanding Pedagogy, pp. 28–43. Routledge, London (1999)

    Google Scholar 

  • Unsworth, L.: Evaluating the language of different types of explanations in junior high school science texts. Int. J. Sci. Educ. 23, 585–609 (2001)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Van Fraassen, B.C.: The Scientific Image. Clarendon, Oxford (1980)

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Woodward, J.: Scientific explanation. In: Zalta, E.N. (ed.) Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2011/entries/scientific-explanation/. Accessed 4 May 2014 (2011)

  • Woody, A.I.: On explanatory practice and disciplinary identity. Ann. N. Y. Acad. Sci. 988, 22–29 (2003)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Woody, A.I.: Telltale signs: what common explanatory strategies in chemistry reveal about explanation itself. Found. Chem. 6, 13–43 (2004a)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Woody, A.I.: More telltale signs: what attention to representation reveals about scientific explanation. Philos. Sci. 71, 780–793 (2004b)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Young, H.D., Freedman, R.D.: Sears and Zamansky’s University Physics: With Modern Physics, 13th int. edn. Addison-Wesley, San Francisco (2010)

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

This chapter benefitted from critical feedback from Hanne Andersen, Douglas Allchin and an anonymous reviewer. Furthermore it benefitted from insights and comments provided by the entire philosophy of contemporary science in practice group at Aarhus University. The group is supported by the Danish Council for Independent Research|Humanities.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Mads Goddiksen .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2015 Springer International Publishing Switzerland

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Goddiksen, M. (2015). An Empirical Method for the Study of Exemplar Explanations. In: Wagenknecht, S., Nersessian, N., Andersen, H. (eds) Empirical Philosophy of Science. Studies in Applied Philosophy, Epistemology and Rational Ethics, vol 21. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-18600-9_6

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics