Skip to main content

Pareto and Machiavellianism: The Problem and the Errors

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Infrasocial Power
  • 54 Accesses

Abstract

This chapter considers the work of Vilfredo Pareto. Shifting from the study of engineering to that of economics, he started to study social phenomena broadly defined. Pareto faced a crisis of Italian (and French) democracy, but did not realise that the problems originated from the fact that “limited democracy” was continually under attack by the political class. This stimulated significant episodes of corruption. In a letter of January 9, 1894, Pareto writes: “This is the condition of our homeland now: every liberty has been extinguished apart from that of theft on the part of self-serving politicians and everything is undertaken to extinguish in the minds of the people every upright and honest”.

The problem raised by Pareto was well-known to Mandeville, Montesquieu, Hume and Smith. These scholars had understood that the “government of the law” was the only one able to contain corruption. They understood that, by establishing boundaries between actions, the rule of law stop an individual from damaging another. That is, they understood that the path to follow was the one limiting public and infrasocial power, which is the same path that leads to “limited democracy”. Pareto instead considered that the solution could be found in a strengthening of public power. He embraced the “government of men” rather than that of the law. He very likely reached such conclusion through his engineering approach to economics, which is based on the assumption that individuals in power know the “relevant data” for policymaking. What is more, his theory of the social cycle, which sees “history like a succession of elites characterized by the use of cunning (foxes) and elites characterized by the resort to force (lions), governments marked by skepticism, which mainly make use of deception, and governments based on material force and the force of religious feelings”, is totally misleading. As Norberto Bobbio has written, “Pareto takes an exclusively psychological stance; and, in addition to that, it is a rudimentary type of psychology”.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

eBook
USD 16.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 16.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 99.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    Freund (1974), p. 6.

  2. 2.

    Aron (1967), p. 471.

  3. 3.

    Ibid., p. 475.

  4. 4.

    Gurvitch (1957), p. 78.

  5. 5.

    Schumpeter (1949), p. 168, Aron (1967), pp. 414–5.

  6. 6.

    Letter quoted by Busino (1974), p. 21. In this connection, Bobbio (1971, pp. 54–55) wrote: “As far as social morphology is concerned, Pareto takes no notice of it, because the only kind of society he has in mind is political society, characterized by the relations between rulers and ruled, so that he has much more the appearance of a successor to Machiavelli than a contemporary of Durkheim”. And not just Durkheim.

  7. 7.

    See note 153 in the previous chapter. As we know, Mandeville was influenced by Bayle. Pareto (1935, in particular vol. 1, pp. 226–230, sections 360–366) knew Bayle’s work. But this did not lead him to Mandeville.

  8. 8.

    Hume (1930), vol. 2, p. 251.

  9. 9.

    Cf. Chap. 3, note 209.

  10. 10.

    Ibid.

  11. 11.

    Hayek (1949), p. 11.

  12. 12.

    Schumpeter (1997), vol. 3, p. 1057.

  13. 13.

    Schumpeter (1949), p. 151. See also Arendt (1969), pp. 65–6.

  14. 14.

    Pareto (1971), p. 779.

  15. 15.

    Perhaps, believing he was providing a more acceptable “portrait” of the character, Parsons (1949, p. 293) wrote that for Pareto “freedom in thought and personal conduct was far more important than in business”. This certainly does not do a good service to the cause of Pareto, since Parsons transfers onto Pareto his own lack of knowledge of the link connecting freedom of thought with economic freedom. And it is a most serious flaw (cf. Chap. 3, note 86).

  16. 16.

    Pareto (1966), p. 233.

  17. 17.

    This was recognised by Pareto (1966, p. 732) himself: “Having arrived at a certain stage of my research into political economy, I found myself in a blind alley”.

  18. 18.

    See Chap. 1, note 55.

  19. 19.

    Mises (1981, p. 94). The discovery of this led Pareto (1935, vol. 2, p. 586, section 2142 to write: “a society determined exclusively by ‘reason’ does not exist and cannot exist. And not because the ‘prejudices’ of men prevent them from following the dictates of ‘reason’; but because the data of the problem one wishes to resolve with logical-experimental reasoning are not available”.

  20. 20.

    Pareto (1974a), p. 52.

  21. 21.

    Hume (1930), vol. 2, p. 284.

  22. 22.

    Pareto (1974a, p. 42) believed he was arguing something particularly original, saying that the concept of a “scientific religion” was “truly monstrous”. Bobbio (1971, p. 30) rightly wrote: “Pareto must have had the feeling that he had made one of those discoveries which open up an infinity of paths”.

  23. 23.

    Ricossa (1988), pp. 11–12.

  24. 24.

    Parsons (1949) devoted an entire book to this problem. The limits of his criticism lie in the fact that he focused on utilitarianism in the narrower sense, without noticing the evolutionist tradition and without understanding that the subjectivist theory of value can take into account the pre-logical and extra-scientific element of action. Cf. Infantino (1998), pp. 131–65.

  25. 25.

    See Chap. 1, note 102. For a lengthier discussion, cf. Infantino (2003), pp. 108–115 and the bibliography indicate therein.

  26. 26.

    Mayer (1937), p. 670. Aron (1967, p. 410) wrote that the rational conduct of Pareto’s subject is the same as that of a “speculator” in the strictly economic field. But this is not so. Pareto (1974a, p. 34) well knew that the actions of speculators are to a significant extent non-logical, because they are based on conjectural and unknown data. As far as the theory of general economic equilibrium is concerned, there is no speculation in it, because the relevant data are known and there is no uncertainty. As Kirzner (1973, pp. 10–1) wrote , we would in that case have a “pattern of perfectly dovetailing decisions. No decision made will fail to be carried out, and no opportunity will fail to be exploited. Each market participant will have correctly forecast all the relevant decisions of others; he will have laid his plans fully cognizant of what he will be unable to do in the market, but in the same time fully awake to what he is able to do in the market. Clearly, with such a state of affairs the market process must immediately cease”. Perrin (1971, p. 34) had later argued that the “assumptions of Pareto’s economics are those of classical economics: only the rational behaviour of individual agents are taken into account”. But Perrin’s statement contains a very serious misunderstanding. As we have already seen (cf. Chap. 3, note 251), the expressions “classical economics” and “neo-classical economics” are misleading, because both encompass two conflicting traditions: the evolutionist one and the strictly utilitarian tradition. It is therefore extremely incorrect to place on the same level Adam Smith and Bentham (and John Stuart Mill) or Menger and Walras. Pareto is a rigorous utilitarian, who methodologically prolongs the excesses and the naiveties of Mill’s homo oeconomicus . See Infantino (2010).

  27. 27.

    Pareto (1935), vol. 1, pp. 87–8, section 161.

  28. 28.

    Op. cit., p. 77, section 150. It is worth pointing out that Pizzorno (1989, pp. 28–30) equates non-logical action with irrational action, thus altering the meaning Pareto gave to that kind of action. Nietzsche (1986, p. 28) rightly argued that “only very naive people are capable of believing that the nature of man could be transformed into a pure logical one”. He (ibid.) also stated: “Among the things that can reduce a thinker to despair is the knowledge that the illogical is a necessity of mankind, and that much good proceeds from the illogical”. Leaving aside the dramatisation Nietzsche was so fond of, one can more simply say that action is initiated by pre-logical and extra-scientific elements.

  29. 29.

    Weber (1978), vol. 1, p. 5.

  30. 30.

    One should add that Weber himself was not aware of the consequences which the dependence of economic value on subjective elements produces for the theory of action. In his well-known essay on marginal utility, he (1922, p. 379) accused economic theory, including marginalism in all its versions, of operating with an idea of action which is permanently subjected to “calculation”. This led him to his well-known quadripartite division, in which the “instrumentally rational action” coincides with the utilitarian approach. And yet, as was soon pointed out by Mises (1981, pp. 75–91), that type of action does not exist, because all actions originate from a pre-logical and extra-scientific element. See also Infantino (1998, pp. 125–30), where there is a discussion (p. 200) of the “knock-on effect” of Weber’s error on Parsons.

  31. 31.

    Pareto (1935), vol. 2, p. 501, section 850.

  32. 32.

    Op. cit., p. 502, section 854.

  33. 33.

    Schumpeter (1949), p. 172. Similarly Parsons (1949, p. 270), according to whom “the real forces of action are not expressed in the theory, but the latter is like a veil covering them”. Pareto (1935, vol. 2, p. 520, section 875) explained that “the residues a must not be confused with the sentiments or instincts which they correspond. The residue are the manifestations of sentiments and the instincts just as the rising of the mercury in a thermometer is a manifestation of the rise in temperature”.

  34. 34.

    Pareto (1935), vol. 2, pp. 516–7, section 888.

  35. 35.

    Op. cit., p. 519, section 889.

  36. 36.

    Parsons (1949), p. 279.

  37. 37.

    Pareto (1935), vol. 2, p. 520, section 891.

  38. 38.

    Parsons (1949), p. 279.

  39. 39.

    Pareto (1935), vol. 4, p. 1576, section 2254.

  40. 40.

    Op. cit., p. 1635, section 2300.

  41. 41.

    Op. cit., p. 1623, section 2275.

  42. 42.

    Op. cit., pp. 1622–3, section 2274.

  43. 43.

    Op. cit., p. 1556, section 2227.

  44. 44.

    Pareto (1974b, p. 136) wrote: “This phenomenon of new elites which, owing to a ceaseless motion of circulation, originate from the lower strata of society, rise to the higher ones, expand there and, later, fall into decadence, are annihilated and disappear, is one of the main historical facts, and it is indispensable to bear it in mind, in order to understand major social movements”. Pareto (ibid.) explained the phenomenon in the following terms: “The decadence of the elites, which are recruited by cooptation or in some similar way, has various and in part obscure causes. [… The] example which comes immediately to mind is that of the Catholic clergy. How deep the decadence of this elite from the ninth to the eighteenth century! Heredity is not involved here. Decadence has its cause in the fact that the elite for its recruitment chose individuals who were always of mediocre quality. In part this derives from the fact that this elite was gradually losing sight of its ideal, was less sustained by faith and by the spirit of sacrifice; and in part it also derives from external circumstances: from the fact that other elites rose and took the best elements away from the declining elite. Since the proportion of these elements in relation to the rest of the population varies very little, if they move to one side they are lacking on the other; if commerce, industry, administration, etc., provide them with broad opportunities, they will necessarily be lacking for some other elite”.

  45. 45.

    Pareto (1935), vol. 1, p. 104, section 180.

  46. 46.

    Bobbio (1971), p. 119. Valade (1990) presented Pareto as the deviser of “another sociology”. But what Pareto really did not formulate is a genuine theory of social action.

  47. 47.

    Pareto (1935), vol. 3, p. 1314, section 1884.

  48. 48.

    Ibid.

  49. 49.

    Ibid.

  50. 50.

    Op. cit., p. 1481, section 1479.

  51. 51.

    Perelmann and Olbrechts-Tyteca (1976), p. 59.

  52. 52.

    Pareto (1974a), p. 33.

  53. 53.

    Mises (1981), p. 3. See also Weber (1922), p. 361. Cf. Also Chap. 1, note 18.

  54. 54.

    Mises (1981), p. 57.

  55. 55.

    Pareto (1935), vol. 3, p. 983, section 1537.

  56. 56.

    For a more extensive discussion of the topic, see Infantino (1998), pp. 53–4.

  57. 57.

    Pareto (1966), p. 324.

  58. 58.

    Pareto (1935), vol. 4, p. 1475, section 2142.

  59. 59.

    Borkenau (1936), p. 169.

  60. 60.

    Bobbio (1971), p. 79.

  61. 61.

    Op. cit., p. 75.

  62. 62.

    Pareto (1935), vol. 4, p. 2085, section 2083.

  63. 63.

    Op. cit., vol. 3, p. 1201, section 1746. Obviously, Pareto (op. cit., p. 1300, section 1868) knew that this route was shared with Sorel: “The capacity for influencing human conduct that is possessed by sentiments expressed in form of derivations that overstep experience and reality throws light upon a phenomenon that has been well observed and analysed by Georges Sorel, the fact, namely, that, if a social doctrine (it would be more exact to say the sentiments manifested by a social doctrine) is to have any influence, it has to take the form of a myth”. It is also useful to point out that this “suggestion” is no different to what was advocated by Rousseau (1997, p. 53), who looked towards a “most remarkable change”, capable of “substituting justice for instinct” in man’s conduct. See also Rousseau (1974), p. 49. Considering the “sentimentalism” Pareto attributed to Rousseau, this is truly ironic.

  64. 64.

    Pareto (1935, vol. 3, p. 948, section 1498) was led, by his blindness towards the mechanism of social cooperation, to argue: “If the [collective] interest is real and the individual acts logically to favour it, there is not derivation: it is a case of plain logical conduct designed to attain an end designed by an individual […]. More often, however, the objective end differs from the subjective purpose, and we get non-logical conduct justified by derivations. This type of derivation is very generally used by people who want something and pretend to be asking for it not for themselves, but in behalf of the community”. Pareto never suspected in the least that the objective end, what we do for others, and the subjective end, what we personally wish to pursue, coexist and engender the Janus-like entity of social life. Cf. previous chapter, Sect. 3.7.

  65. 65.

    Durkheim (2010), pp. 21–2.

  66. 66.

    See Durkheim (2010, p. 48), Weber (1978, p. 1120), Sorokin (1942, pp. 14–15).

  67. 67.

    Simmel (1908), p. 36.

  68. 68.

    Op. cit., p. 38.

  69. 69.

    Cf. also previous chapter, Sect. 3.7.

  70. 70.

    After a brief trip to Germany (in 1935), where he fully understood what was happening in German society at the time, Ortega y Gasset (1935, p. 191) wrote : “when a people mainly set themselves the task of organising their collective life, it pays this result with the de-individualisation of the men who are part of it”.

  71. 71.

    Topitsch (see note 243 in Chap. 2) wrote that in these situations “the deluded person is the classic victim of the hypocrites”.

  72. 72.

    Gilbert (1977), p. 48.

  73. 73.

    Pareto (1935), vol. 2, p. 502–3, section 854.

  74. 74.

    Pareto (1974b, pp. 138–139).

  75. 75.

    Pareto (1935), vol. 2, p. 517, section 888.

  76. 76.

    See Chap. 2, note 221.

  77. 77.

    For the relevant references, see Infantino (2003), pp. 45–8.

  78. 78.

    Weber (1978), vol. 2, p. 1115.

  79. 79.

    Weber (1946), p. 125.

  80. 80.

    Ibid. This text is also quoted in Chap. 2 (note 241). On this topic, see also Michels (1966), p. 519.

  81. 81.

    Weber (1978), p. 1120. Alberoni (1977, p. 366) wrote that “every nascent state comprises an exploration of the possible starting from the impossible“.

  82. 82.

    Cf. Chap. 2, note 241.

  83. 83.

    Perelman and Olbrechts-Tyteca (1976), p. 62. Furthermore (op. cit., p. 73): “The use of argumentation implies renouncing the exclusive resort to force, implies that some value is attributed to the adhesion of the interlocutor obtained with the help of reasoned persuasion, that the interlocutor himself is not treated like an object, but that his freedom of judgement is resorted to. The use of argumentation assumes that a community of spirits is established which for its entire duration excludes the use of violence”. And he added (op. cit., p. 77): “since the purpose of argumentation is to obtain consent, one could say that argumentation aims at eliminating the preliminary conditions to a future argumentation. But since a rhetorical test never has a constraining value, the silence which is imposed should never be considered definitive, if the conditions which allow for argumentation are actually established. The institutions which regulate discussion are important, because argumentative thought and the action it prepares and determines are intimately linked to each other”.

  84. 84.

    Op. cit., p. 679.

  85. 85.

    This is a paradox which has affected many people, including Michels.

  86. 86.

    However “indulgent” one might be with Pareto, it is difficult to forgive him the (not only linguistic) “tangle”, out of which the following statement issues: “In the sphere of political economy, certain measures (for example, wage cutting) of business men (entrepreneurs) working under conditions of free competition are to some extent non-logical actions […], that is, the objective end does not coincide with the subjective purpose. On the other end, if they enjoy a monopoly, the same measures (wage cutting) become logical actions” (Pareto 1935, vol. 1, p. 89, section 159).

  87. 87.

    Cf. note 6 in this chapter.

  88. 88.

    Engels (1975a), p. 379.

  89. 89.

    Engels (1975b), p. 393.

  90. 90.

    Marx (1984), p. 52.

  91. 91.

    Marx, Engels (1974), p. 64.

  92. 92.

    Op. cit., p. 37. Marx and Engels (op. cit., p. 64) also wrote: “The ideas of the ruling class are in every epoch the ruling ideas, i.e. the class which is the ruling material force of society is at the same time its ruling intellectual force”. And further: “The division of labour […] manifests itself also […] as division of mental and material labour, so that inside this class one part appears as the thinkers of the class (its active, conceptive ideologists, who make the perfecting of the illusion of the class about itself their source of livelihood)” (op. cit., p. 65). In order to declare himself unaffected by such conditioning, Marx attributes to himself and the class he claims to be the representative of a monopoly over historical truth, a “privileged point of view on the world”, which makes it possible to foresee the goal to which humankind is proceeding. Hence also Mannheim’s theory of freischwebende Intelligenz, which postulates precisely the existence of a privileged source of knowledge. Cf. on the topic, Infantino (1998, p. 182) and the bibliography presented there.

  93. 93.

    Marx (1976), vol. 1, p. 916.

  94. 94.

    Pareto (1935, vol. 3, p. 1293, section 1858), who also wrote: “The facts which have occurred and are occurring in Italy give us many confirmations of the conclusions drawn from history […], the remissive will, the weakness of the rulers are opposed by the fierce actions and the violence of their adversaries, who are made strong by the cowardice of those could stand up to them” (Pareto 1966, p. 999). Compare the following statement by Marx (1976, vol. 1, p. 874): “In actual history, it is a notorious fact that conquest, enslavement, robbery, murder, in short, force play the greatest part”. It is also worth stressing that Pareto (1935, vol. 4, p. 1535, note 2) recognised “the surpassing merit” of Sorel’s Réflexions sur la violence. In actual fact, Pareto and Sorel levelled the same criticism against “democratic demoralization”. In both cases, it is therefore “bourgeois degeneration” which legitimises the resort to violence.

  95. 95.

    Pareto (1935), vol. 3, p. 948, section 1498.

  96. 96.

    Op. cit., vol. 4, pp. 1577–8, section 2254.

  97. 97.

    Op. cit., p. 1576, section 2254.

  98. 98.

    Op. cit., vol. 3, p. 948, section 1498.

  99. 99.

    Simmel (1919), p. 190.

  100. 100.

    Ibid.

  101. 101.

    Op. cit., p. 193.

  102. 102.

    Ibid.

  103. 103.

    Ortega y Gasset (1916), p. 92.

  104. 104.

    Weber (1950), p. 20.

  105. 105.

    Weber (1978), vol. 2, p. 1118.

  106. 106.

    Op. cit., p. 199.

  107. 107.

    Op. cit., p. 346. Miglio (2011, vol. 2, p. 321) in this case referred to “political rent”.

  108. 108.

    Weber (1978), vol. 1, p. 199.

  109. 109.

    Paraphrasing Merriam (1934, p. 99), one could say that there are groups organised against the political organisation itself or “gangs within the law” (op. cit., p. 97).

  110. 110.

    Pareto (1966), p. 970.

  111. 111.

    Pareto (1974c), vol. 2, p. 700.

  112. 112.

    Op. cit., p. 596.

  113. 113.

    Op. cit., p. 707.

  114. 114.

    Pareto (1966), p. 998.

  115. 115.

    Ibid., p. 999.

  116. 116.

    De Viti de Marco (1920), p. 151.

  117. 117.

    De Viti de Marco (1922), p. 461.

  118. 118.

    See note 14 in this chapter.

  119. 119.

    Pareto (1935), vol. 4, p. 1572, section 2251.

  120. 120.

    I am here making use of statements presented, in a broader context, by Mises (1985, p. 44).

  121. 121.

    Pareto (1966), p. 1111.

  122. 122.

    Mises (1969), pp. 7–11.

  123. 123.

    Pareto (1974c, vol. 2, p. 709) wrote: “The government then intervened rapidly; driven by political or also parliamentary interests, it prepared to dispel these troubles, without giving a thought as to whether this would lead to other greater or more lasting troubles”.

  124. 124.

    In describing the adventurer, Ferrero (1947, p. 35) presented a profile which is not far removed from the one sketched out by Simmel and Weber: “few scruples, no vision and no concern for the future, for remote consequences: the only concern is immediate success”. It is useful to recall that Pareto did not have a good opinion of Ferrero. In a letter to Maffeo Pantaleoni, he wrote that Ferrero’s writings “are all novels” (Pareto 1960, vol. 2, p. 61). More careful attention would however have suggested a very different judgement.

  125. 125.

    See Chap. 3, note 212.

  126. 126.

    Mises (1985, p. 170) rightly wrote that this is often presented as the “crisis of parliamentarianism”, whereas in actual fact it is the result of the intermingling of politics and the economy. Cf. also Mises (1978), pp. 89–90. On the problem of the prevalence of legislative output, see the classic works by Hayek (1960 1982) and Leoni (1991).

  127. 127.

    The intermingling of politics and the economy makes it possible to use the resources of other people, the tax-payers, to extend the power of rulers and the groups connected to them. It is always possible to find a noble social justification for this. Pareto was very critical of “bail outs”, or measures taken to keep alive companies which were incapable of staying in the market. He knew well that the resources used in such initiatives mean a genuine destruction of capital. It appears that problems are solved, but they are aggravated because of the fact that those resources are subtracted from initiatives which are capable of surviving the test bench of competition. Following Thoreau, Friedman (1972) wrote that there is nothing easier and more pernicious than doing good at the expense of others.

  128. 128.

    It is no coincidence that Hayek (1949, p. 20) stated that the liberal policy is “a long-run policy”.

  129. 129.

    Pareto (1893, pp. 3–28) identified the issuing of paper money as one of the instruments of political adventurism. He devoted a lot of attention to the events of the Banca Romana. And he took as an “example which is far from the present and therefore in part unaffected by emotions” the case of John Law (Pareto 1974c, vol. 2, p. 707). We shall deal with the “power to issue money” in the next chapter.

  130. 130.

    Among the texts translated by Small, there are also the chapters which, in his Soziologie, Simmel devoted to the treatment of power and conflict.

  131. 131.

    Hughes (1964), p. 18.

  132. 132.

    The text (Park and Burgess 1921) contains ten pieces by Simmel, two by Durkheim, Hobhouse and Spencer, three by Le Bon and none by Weber.

  133. 133.

    Levine (1971), p. LI.

  134. 134.

    Lasswell (1935), pp. V-VI.

  135. 135.

    Lasswell, Kaplan (1950), p. 286.

  136. 136.

    Stoppino (1975, p. XVIII) wrote that the “materials” available to Lasswell made it possible for him to present “a political analysis, not in the narrower and trivial sense, but in the broader and significant sense, where the political is everything which has significant consequences on the general distribution of power among individuals and groups in society, and therefore on the general distribution of social values, or the things, that is, which men desire”.

  137. 137.

    Lasswell, Kaplan (1950), p. 3.

  138. 138.

    Op. cit., p. 85.

  139. 139.

    Ibid. Lasswell reinforced his statement with a reference to Tawney (1931, pp. 228–9): “The discussion of the problem which power presents has been prejudiced […] by the concentration of interest upon certain of its manifestation to the exclusion of others […]. A realistic treatment of it has suffered, in particular, from the habit of considering it primarily, or even purely, in political terms. Power is identified with political power, and political power is treated as a category by itself”. Lasswell (op. cit., p. 93) also referred to Russell (1938, pp. 13–4): “power has many forms, such as wealth, armaments, civil authority, influence on opinion. No one of these can be regarded as subordinate to any other, and there is no one form from which the others are derivative”.

  140. 140.

    Lasswell, Kaplan (1950), p. 85.

  141. 141.

    Ibid.

  142. 142.

    Lasswell (1948), p. 10.

  143. 143.

    Op. cit., p. 13.

  144. 144.

    Op. cit., p. 18.

  145. 145.

    Lasswell, Kaplan (1950), p. 80.

  146. 146.

    Lasswell (1948), p. 10.

  147. 147.

    Op. cit., p. 13.

  148. 148.

    See note 28 in this chapter.

  149. 149.

    Lasswell (1948), p. 16. Notwithstanding this, Lasswell (op. cit., p. 160) also wrote: “what the infant-child does initially is too treat every discomfort as a provocation for every form of expression at his command. It is not too far fetched to say that everyone is born a politician”. Here, alongside a rebuttal of the idea that there can be societies without power, there is a failure to understand the fact that a child is already inside a social relationship, hence the political character of his responses.

  150. 150.

    Op. cit., p. 16.

  151. 151.

    In fact, moving on a trajectory which is different from the one we have followed here, Stoppino (2001, p. 40) wrote : “to say that intentional social causation is power is not to say that only intentional social causation is power”.

  152. 152.

    Lasswell (1936), p. 411. See also Lasswell (1935), p. 45 and (1948), p. 442.

  153. 153.

    Lasswell, Kaplan (1950), p. XXIV, where it is also said that public power “is as limited a standpoint for inquiry as for policy”.

  154. 154.

    Op. cit., pp. 78–80.

  155. 155.

    Lasswell (1948), p. 54.

  156. 156.

    Ibid.

  157. 157.

    Op. cit., pp. 55–8.

  158. 158.

    Lasswell, Kaplan (1950), p. 78.

  159. 159.

    As we have pointed out (Chap. 1, note 58), Hayek spoke of homo oeconomicus as the “skeleton in our cupboard”, meaning the cupboard of economists, “exorcised with prayer and fasting”. One should add that, in the pages in which he brought up homo oeconomicus , Lasswell showed no great knowledge in the area of economic theories. He even attributed the paternity of that economic model to Jevons. But that figure (see Chap. 1, section 3) stems from the definition of economy formulated by John Stuart Mill. Cf. in any case Infantino (2008), pp. 69–111.

  160. 160.

    Lasswell (1936), p. 239.

  161. 161.

    Lasswell (1948), p. 150. Lasswell here neglected to take into consideration the input of Merriam (1934, p. 100), who highlighted the fact that damage is not produced by “the inborn viciousness of man”, but from the “inadequacies” of rules. It is strange that, in introducing him to Italy, Stoppino (1975) did not focus on the major flaw this represented in Lasswell. Furthermore, Stoppino never realised that the idea of maximisation produces misleading results in economics, sociology and politics.

  162. 162.

    See Merton (1968, p. 120). Hayek repeatedly drew attention to the knowledge incorporated in social norms. On this issue, his main points of reference were the Scottish moralists and Burke. In his last work, Hayek (1988, p. 157) also referred to Frazer (1909).

  163. 163.

    Cf. Mead (1934) and Lasswell (1936), pp. 374–375.

  164. 164.

    Popper (1966), p. 93.

  165. 165.

    Ortega (1923), p. 215.

  166. 166.

    Ortega (1930, p. 180) also argued “we are what our world invites us to be”. In other words: “men with the most diverse psychologies encounter a certain common and inescapable repertory of problems which endows their existences with an identical basic structure. Psychological differences […] are secondary and only introduce insignificant perforations in the outline of the common drama […]. It is time for history to abandon psychologism […]. Each of us is immersed in a system of problems, dangers, facilities, difficulties, possibilities and impossibilities which are not part of us but are part of the world which we inhabit, which we must come to terms with, which we need to deal and struggle with and which our lives necessarily consist of. If we had been born a hundred years ago, even with the same character and the same capabilities, the drama of our lives would have been very different” (Ortega 1933, pp. 26–27).

  167. 167.

    Hayek (1949), p. 47.

References

  • Alberoni F. (1977) Movimento e istituzione, Bologna: Il Mulino.

    Google Scholar 

  • Arendt H. (1969) On Violence, New York: Harcourt Brace.

    Google Scholar 

  • Aron R. (1967) Les étapes de la pensée sociologique, Paris: Gallimard.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bobbio N. (1971) Saggi sulla scienza politica in Italia, Torino: Einaudi.

    Google Scholar 

  • Borkenau F. (1936) Pareto, London: Chapman & Hall.

    Google Scholar 

  • Busino G. (1974) Introduzione to Pareto (1974c).

    Google Scholar 

  • De Viti de Marco A. (1920) “Il terzo partito”, in L’Unità, IX, no. 37, pp. 151–2.

    Google Scholar 

  • De Viti de Marco A. (1922) “Economie o imposte?”, in Problemi italiani, I, vol. 2, pp. 429–62.

    Google Scholar 

  • Durkheim É. (2010) Sociology and Philosophy, Abingdon: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Engels F. (1975a) “Letters from London”, in Marx-Engels (1975), vol. 3.

    Google Scholar 

  • Engels F. (1975b) “Progress of Social Reform on the Continent”, in Marx-Engels (1975), vol. 3.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ferrero G. (1947) Avventura. Bonaparte in Italia (1796–1797), Milano: Garzanti.

    Google Scholar 

  • Frazer J. (1909) Psyche’s Task, London: Macmillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Freund J. (1974) Pareto, Paris: Seghers.

    Google Scholar 

  • Friedman M. (1972) An Economist’s Protest: Columns in Political Economy, Glen Ridge: Horton.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gilbert F. (1977) History, Choice and Commitment, Cambridge (Mass.): Harvard U.P.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gurvitch G. (1957) Le concept de classes sociales de Marx à nos jours, Paris: CDU.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hayek F.A. (1949) Individualism and Economic Order, London: Routledge & Kegan Paul.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hayek F.A. (1960), The Constitution of Liberty, London, Routledge & Kegan Paul.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hayek F.A. (1982) Law, Legislation and Liberty, London: Routledge

    Google Scholar 

  • Hayek F.A. (1988) The Fatal Conceit, London: Routledge.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Hughes E.C. (1964) “Robert Park”, in New Society, 31 Dec., p. 18.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hume D. (1930) A Treatise of Human Nature, London: Dent.

    Google Scholar 

  • Infantino L. (1998), Individualism in Modern Thought. From Adam Smith to Hayek, London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Infantino L. (2003) Ignorance and Liberty, London-New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Infantino L. (2008) Individualismo, mercato e storia delle idee, Soveria Mannelli: Rubbettino.

    Google Scholar 

  • Infantino L. (2010) “Hayek and the Evolutionary Tradition Against the Homo Oeconomicus”, in Advances in Austrian Economics, vol. 13, pp. 159–77.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kirzner I.M. (1973) Competition and Entrepreneurship, Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lasswell H.D. (1935) World Politics and Personal Insecurity, New York: McGraw-Hill.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lasswell H.D. (1936) Who Gets What, When, How, New York: McGraw-Hill.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lasswell H.D. (1948) Power and Personality, New York: Norton.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lasswell H.D., A. Kaplan (1950) Power and Society, London: Yale U.P.

    Google Scholar 

  • Leoni B. (1991) Freedom and the Law, Indianapolis: Liberty Fund.

    Google Scholar 

  • Levine D.N. (1971) Introduction to Simmel (1971).

    Google Scholar 

  • Marx K. (1976) Capital, London: Penguin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Marx K. (1984) “On the Jewish Question”, in Marx (1984c).

    Google Scholar 

  • Marx K, Engels F. (1974) The German Ideology, London: Lawrence & Wishart.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mayer H. (1937) “Il concetto di equilibrio nella teoria economica”, in G. Del Vecchio (ed.), Economia pura, Torino: Utet.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mead G.H. (1934) Mind, Self and Society, Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Merriam C.E. (1934) Political Power, London: McGraw-Hill.

    Google Scholar 

  • Merton R.K. (1968) Social Theory and Social Structure, New York: Free Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Michels R. (1966) La sociologia del partito politico, Bologna: Il Mulino.

    Google Scholar 

  • Miglio G. (2011) Lezioni di politica, Bologna: Il Mulino.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mises L. (1969) Bureaucracy, New Rochelle: Arlington House.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mises L. (1978) In Namen des Staates, Stuttgart, Bonn Aktuell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mises L. (1981) Epistemological Problems of Economics, New York: New York U.P.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mises L. (1985) Liberalism, San Francisco: Cobden Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nietzsche F. (1986) Human, All Too Human, Cambridge: Cambridge U.P.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ortega y Gasset J. (1916), “Ideas sobre Pío Baroja”, in Ortega y Gasset (1946–1983), vol. 2.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ortega y Gasset J. (1923) “El ocaso de las revoluciones”, in Ortega y Gasset (1946–1983), vol. 3.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ortega y Gasset J. (1930) “La rebelion de las masas”, in Ortega y Gasset (1946–1983), vol. 4.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ortega y Gasset J. (1933) “Goethe desde dentro”, in Ortega y Gasset (1946–1983), vol. 4.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ortega y Gasset J. (1935) “Un rasgo de la vida alemana”, in Ortega y Gasset (1946–1983), vol. 5.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pareto V. (1893) “L’intervention de l’état dans le banques d’émission en Italie”, in Journal des Economistes, vol. 14, pp. 138–63.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pareto V. (1935) The Mind and Society: A Treatise of General Sociology, New York: Dover Publications.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pareto V. (1960) Lettere a Maffeo Pantaleoni, Roma: Banca Nazionale del Lavoro.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pareto V., (1966) Scritti sociologici, Torino: Utet.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pareto V. (1971) Corso di economia politica, Torino: Utet.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pareto V. (1974a) Manuale di economia politica, Padova: Cedam.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pareto V. (1974b) I sistemi socialisti, Torino: Utet.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pareto V. (1974c) Scritti politici, Torino: Utet.

    Google Scholar 

  • Park R.E., Burgess E.W. (1921) Introduction to the Science of Sociology, Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Parsons T. (1949) The Structure of Social Action, Glencoe: Free Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Perelman C., Olbrechts-Tyteca L. (1976) Traité de la’argumentation, Bruxelles: Editions de l’Université de Bruxelles.

    Google Scholar 

  • Perrin G. (1971) Sociologie de Pareto, Paris: PUF.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pizzorno A. (1989), “Sistema sociale e classe politica”, in Storia delle idee politiche, economiche e sociali, vol. 6, Torino: Utet.

    Google Scholar 

  • Popper K.R. (1966) The Open Society and Its Enemies, London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ricossa S. (1988) “Sugli abusi del razionalismo nell’economia politica”, in Rivista di Politica Economica, vol. 78, pp. 7–14.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rousseau J.-J. (1974) Emile, London: Dent.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rousseau J.-J. (1997) “Discourse on the Origin and Foundations of Inequality Among Men”, in Rousseau (1997c).

    Google Scholar 

  • Russell B. (1938) Power. A New Social Analysis, London: Allen & Unwin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schumpeter J.A. (1949) “Vilfredo Pareto”, in Quarterly Journal of Economics, vol. 63, pp. 147–73.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schumpeter J.A. (1997) History of Economic Analysis, London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Simmel G. (1908) Soziologie, Leipzig: Duncker & Humblot.

    Google Scholar 

  • Simmel G. (1919) Philosophische Kultur, Leipzig: Kröner.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sorokin P. (1942) Man and Society in Calamity, New York: Dutton.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stoppino (1975) Introduzione to H.D. Lasswell, Potere, politica e personalità, Torino: Utet.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stoppino (2001) Potere e teoria politica, Milano: Giuffrè.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tawney R.H. (1931) Equality, London: Allen & Unwin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Valade B. (1990) Pareto. La naissance d’une autre sociologie, Paris: PUF.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Weber M. (1922) “Die Grenznutzlehre und das psychophysiche Grundgesets”, in Gesammelte Aufsatze zur Wissenschaftslehre, Tübingen: Mohr.

    Google Scholar 

  • Weber M. (1946) Essays in Sociology, New York: Oxford U.P.

    Google Scholar 

  • Weber M. (1950) The Protestant Ethic and the Spirit of Capitalism, New York: Scribner; London: Allen & Unwin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Weber M. (1978) Economy and Society, New York: Bedminster Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Lorenzo Infantino .

Appendix: Lasswell in the Trap of Psychologism

Appendix: Lasswell in the Trap of Psychologism

Psychologism was damaging for Pareto. And it has also damaged the study of economic, social and political phenomena. To make this even clearer we shall consider the writings of Harold D. Lasswell, who produced a very extensive body of work on which a number of influences converged. While he was still at high school, he came into contact with the works of Marx and Freud. He later studied at the University of Chicago, which at the time counted Robert E. Park, Charles E. Merriam and George H. Mead as members of its staff. Later he was able to spend a number of periods of study in Europe, where he studied the Italian elitists.

In the light of the approach we have so far taken, it is particularly useful to focus on Park, who was director of the Department of Sociology which had been founded by Albion W. Small. Both of these authors had done a great deal to introduce Simmel to the United States. Small had translated and published a number of the German thinker’s texts in the “American Journal of Sociology”.Footnote 130 And Park had been to Berlin, in the 1899–1900 winter semester, where he had attended Simmel’s lectures: that had been “his only formal instruction in sociology – instruction that influenced him and the course of American sociology deeply”.Footnote 131 In 1921, in cooperation with Ernest Burgess, Park had collected a number of sociological texts for the use of his students: a selection in which there was a clear prevalence of Simmel’s writings.Footnote 132 The “frame of reference used to organize the readings was largely Simmelian in conception. Park’s impression of Simmel became part of local lore for generations of Chicago graduate students”.Footnote 133

When he sent off World Politics and Personal Insecurity for printing in November 1934, Lasswell wrote of Park: “it is possible, without binding him to the enterprise, to record my long standing indebtedness to his sagacious insight and my appreciation of his respect for creative interplay between hours of high abstraction and days of patient contact with humble detail”.Footnote 134 In Power and Society too, a book written later in cooperation with Abraham Kaplan, Park remained one of his references.Footnote 135

The cultural context which allowed the shaping of Lasswell’s views was therefore not foreign to Simmel’s analysis and, in any case, provided the elements for a wide-ranging analysis of the social process and the relations of superordination and subordination which it produces.Footnote 136 Lasswell stated that “central throughout are persons and their acts, not ‘government’ and ‘states’. Terms like ‘state’, ‘government’, ‘law’, ‘power’ – all the traditional vocabulary of political science – are words of ambiguous reference until it is clear how they are to be used in describing what people say and do”.Footnote 137 And from here Lasswell reached a broad definition of political science, which “is concerned with power in general, with all the forms in which it occurs”Footnote 138: since “failure to recognize that power may rest on various bases, each with a varying scope, has confused and distorted the conception of power itself, and retarded inquiry into the conditions and consequences of its exercise in various ways”.Footnote 139

Therefore, power is not only what is held by those who have a prominent position inside the state organisation. Nay, political power “is a complex form which presupposes always other forms of power, and though of course it differs from these others in characteristic ways, it has much in common with them”.Footnote 140 Consequently, the “power of the state cannot be understood in abstraction from the forms of power manifested in various types of interpersonal relations”.Footnote 141

So, “speaking of power and the powerful is an ellipsis, leaving out what is perhaps the longest arc of the circle constituting a power relation”, which “is an interpersonal situation; those who hold power are empowered. They depend upon and continue only so long as there is a continuing stream of empowering responses. Even a casual inspection of human relations will convince any competent observer that power is not a brick that can be lugged from place to place, but a process that vanishes when the supporting responses cease”.Footnote 142 One must accordingly “recognize as power whatever relationships involve expectation of severe deprivations”Footnote 143; and it is even necessary to include friendships among these relationships, since they comprehend the possibility of the loss of affection, which takes on the shape of a sanction.Footnote 144

Lasswell stated that he had been inspired by the pattern which occurs with exchange.Footnote 145 This because subjects are involved in a “continuing spiral of interaction”,Footnote 146 based on a web of expectations. And yet, when one considers things carefully, he understands that his reference to exchange is only formal, because deprivations need to be “severe”; and, in order to determine their severity, it is necessary to base oneself on the interpretation of a “considerable number of those in the community who acquainted with such circumstances”.Footnote 147 This reminds one of what Pareto wrote in reference to “logical actions”, which are such “not only from the standpoint of the subject performing them, but from the standpoint of others persons who have a more extensive knowledge”.Footnote 148 Therefore the evaluation is not only up to the actors involved. This means that we cannot say we are inside the realm of the theory of exchange, which requires that evaluations be exclusively in the hands of the parties directly involved.

Despite making use of good assumptions, Lasswell’s theory undergoes a continual drift, which refutes his premises. This is immediately visible when one reads that the statement according to which men seek power “is a statement we can accept as true in every society where power exists”.Footnote 149 But the fact is that there are no societies in which power does not exist. Furthermore, as we have stressed from the very first pages, society and power are an inseparable pairing. There is no social relationship in which different degrees of freedom do not interact.

This is why, unlike Lasswell claims, there is no need for a voluntary “politicisation” of social relations. Whether we like it or not, each social relationship carries with it a political element. It is not true, therefore, that “any human situation can be converted into a power relation” and that “this can be done if a participant demands certain conduct and ‘thinks he can get away with it’ by threatening or actually inflicting severe deprivation on anyone who deviates”Footnote 150: at the very moment in which the interaction occurs, the degrees of freedom and the constraints of the actors involved determine positions of superordination and subordination. In other words, we are already inside a relationship of power. Obviously there are actors who are particularly directed towards to securing degrees of freedom. But their intentions do not ensure them any acquisition. If we remain inside the rule of law (and “socially regulated exchange”), intentions can only connotate the way in which power is exercised.Footnote 151 No more than that. To go further, it is necessary to enter into the area of adventure. And this is the “destination” towards which Lasswell’s analysis inexorably moves.

His continual emphasis on “severe deprivations” shows that Lasswell had his permanent point of reference in public power. It is no accident that he referred to those sanctions. And he configured homo politicus as he who “displaces his private motives upon public objects, and rationalizes the displacement in terms of public advantage”.Footnote 152 But Lasswell should have first of all explained that everyone must always transfer their private motivation onto social objects; for only in this way can they offer something to others and, in exchange, obtain the means to pursue their own ends. And he should have then added that one can channel that motivation towards public objects. By skipping over the first part of that mechanism, he deprived exchange, notwithstanding some momentary and weak oscillation, of one of its legs—what the rulers have to do for the ruled. And there is no value in his declared rejection of the politics of power, understood as “power for the sake of power”.Footnote 153 His rejection is a mere flatus vocis. This becomes obvious with the adoption of the essentially utilitarian postulate of maximisation of values,Footnote 154 which opens wide the gates to the “politics of power” itself; something which Lasswell himself fully realised. In fact, he wrote: “The image I refer to is that of the power-hungry man, the person wholly absorbed in getting and holding power, utterly ruthless in his insatiable lust to impose his will upon all men”Footnote 155; and also: “Suppose that we refine this traditional conception into a speculative model of the political man comparable with the economic man of the older economic science”.Footnote 156

It is true: Lasswell judged the model of homo oeconomicus to be at the same time extreme and inadequate,Footnote 157 but that did not prevent him from subscribing to it definitively and claiming that political man is “one who demands the maximization of his power in relation to all his values, who expects power to determine power, and who identifies with the others as means of enhancing power position and potential”.Footnote 158

Obviously, if one introduces the idea of maximisation into the territory of politics in the narrower sense of the term, one inevitably falls captive to “power politics”, which is an action having the purpose of exercising power for power’s sake. A ruler turns into an “adventurer”, who cares nothing about any obligations or medium- and long-term considerations. And yet the motivations of an individual are not enough to make political adventure possible. To think so means to forget that power is a relationship and that adventure itself is an intersubjective relationship. So in order to “assault” the rule of law, the adventurer needs to win people over and make promises which are capable of attracting the consent at least of some social groups. And this is indispensable (even when force is resorted to). Then, once he has reached the point of wielding public power or a part of it, he will “justify” his position with the promises which initiated the relationship. But this will be a mere disguise of his personal aims. And, if one analyses this closely, what are decisive are not the intentions but rather the conditions which provide the political actor’s habitat. Which is tantamount to saying that adventure is a mode in which power is acquired and exercised in a situation where mechanisms of selection have failed to adequately operate and where, for a huge variety of reasons, there is a lack of social control, which is basically always due to insufficient competition. It follows that only if the “rule of law” is in a weak or precarious condition is it possible for the adventurer to carry out his plans.

As we know, the notion of homo oeconomicus was generated through a number of serious methodological errors.Footnote 159 And the fact of borrowing it reveals the high coefficient of psychologism present in Lasswell’s work. Although he always claimed that the science of politics “states conditions”,Footnote 160 he continually channelled energy into constructing the psychological diagram of homo politicus. And, in order to defend himself from the troubling traits attributed to that figure, he resorted to “goodness”: “the sharing of power and respect in adult life depends, in no small part, on basic character structure”; and also: “This is consistent with part, at least, of William Penn’s famous overstatement: ‘If men be good, government cannot be bad’. Penn was also referring to the interlocking bonds of affection that give strength to social structure”.Footnote 161

As we well know, “good intentions” are not enough to provide a solution to the problems of collective life. By resorting to them, Lasswell ended up in a blind alley: being “good” does not mean being omniscient or mastering the “relevant data”. Human actions produce proximate consequences and medium- and long-term outcomes. Despite “good intentions”, what happens in the immediate, or apparently occurs in the initial phase, may subsequently generate completely different and harmful effects. One should, if anything, require that individuals play by the rules in their conduct. But this is not the product of “intentions”. It is most of all the result of mechanisms of social orientation, of the actual enforcement of norms and their penalties, within which there is incorporated a knowledge which very often escapes us.Footnote 162

Lasswell was well aware, having learnt this from George Herbert Mead at least, that each human being must learn from Others to be an I.Footnote 163 This means that, “if a reduction is to be attempted at all, it would therefore be more hopeful to attempt a reduction or interpretation of psychology in terms of sociology than the other way round”.Footnote 164 Accordingly, what is significant is the context in which each interacts and the social process which derives from it. Napoleon Bonaparte remarked: “Vanity made the revolution: liberty was only a pretext”. Discussing “civil heroism” and vanity as well, Ortega y Gasset rightly wrote: “I am not denying that they are both ingredients of revolutions. But in all the great eras of history there is an abundance of both heroism and vanity, without any subversion erupting. In order for both these powers […] to forge a revolution they need to operate within” a specific contextFootnote 165; meaning that they need to meet the social conditions which make their deployment possible.Footnote 166

The cultural context in which he was trained should have allowed Lasswell to make use of the theory of exchange. And, if he had taken that route, he would have subscribed to the view that sees the raison d’être of social science in the identification of the conditions which make a given event or phenomenon possible or impossible. In other words: whatever the actors’ intentions, the social sciences need to address the (positive or negative) unintended consequences associated with that interaction. From which there ensues the attempt to establish norms which, independently of the intentions of the subject, prevent him from causing harm to his neighbour.

Thus configured, the social sciences shed a powerful light on the territory of (voluntary) social cooperation. They highlight the differing degrees of freedom actors benefit from. And, in the attempt of one party to avoid their performance, they identify an amputation of the exchange: the use of a social “justification” for ends which are exclusively personal. But Lasswell embraced a different route: the one suggested by the notion of homo oeconomicus and the short-term maximisation of advantages. It is a theory which prevents exchange from being observed and which conceals the great reality of social exchange. It unrealistically focuses on an actor who knows the “relevant data”, who does not have to undergo the “responses” of the other parties involved and who therefore does not need to concern himself with any consequences. This actor is not confronted by a problem in which the utility of rules can be of help to him. What counts is the utility of a single act. And he can maximise: because the situation denies him nothing. It only asks him to apply himself to an exercise in pure logic.Footnote 167 This kind of approach says very little about the economy, social cooperation and politics.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2020 The Author(s)

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Infantino, L. (2020). Pareto and Machiavellianism: The Problem and the Errors. In: Infrasocial Power. Palgrave Macmillan, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-45081-6_4

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-45081-6_4

  • Published:

  • Publisher Name: Palgrave Macmillan, Cham

  • Print ISBN: 978-3-030-45080-9

  • Online ISBN: 978-3-030-45081-6

  • eBook Packages: Social SciencesSocial Sciences (R0)

Publish with us

Policies and ethics