Skip to main content

The Reshaping of Man and the Birth of Totalitarian Power

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Infrasocial Power
  • 54 Accesses

Abstract

This chapter analyses totalitarian power, whose origins are traced back to Plato’s political project. Plato did not merely take inspiration from the Spartan model. He intended to create a “New Sparta”, namely a polity where social conflict could be finally eliminated from the human condition. Karl R. Popper wrote that “those who […] exalt Plato’s reputation as a teacher of morals and announce to the world that his ethics is the nearest approach to Christianity before Christ, are preparing the way for totalitarianism and especially for a totalitarian […] interpretation of Christianity”. Since Augustine of Hippo largely took inspiration from Plato, the book compares Plato’s polity project to that of Augustine and, in so doing, shed significant light on commonalities. The most significant of these points is the idea that there is a privileged source of knowledge and that, through it, we can reach “human salvation”.

The totalitarian project is Machiavellian. It searches for consensus through the promise of recasting man and, since such recasting is impossible, imposes the most extreme form of repression: if on earth there is possible the realisation of God’s Kingdom or of “God’s Kingdom without God,” it is necessary to persecute all who disagree, for they are the ones permanently conspiring again the “salvation” of man. The naïve actor then becomes the classic victim of institutionalised hypocrisy. To avoid the possibility that those who dissent organise, there is a continuous plan to mobilise against subjects and groups considered to be enemies (internal and external): totalitarian regimes need to systematically employ social conspiracy theory and to continually find scape goats. Moreover, private property must be suppressed or placed under severe control of public power.

Throughout history, totalitarianism has had a long gestation. Besides considering Plato and Augustine, the chapter considers aspects of the Puritan Revolution and episodes of Jacobin Terror. This chapter also develops ideas hinted to by Hannah Arendt and Dolf Sternberger. Regarding the planned economy, it employs the analyses of the Austrian School of Economics.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

eBook
USD 16.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 16.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 99.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    Augustine (A), IV, 7, p. 34.

  2. 2.

    Augustine (C), vol. 1, VIII, 11, p. 321.

  3. 3.

    Op. cit., pp. 321–2.

  4. 4.

    Op. cit., p. 322.

  5. 5.

    Ibid.

  6. 6.

    Op. cit., pp. 322–3.

  7. 7.

    Hoffmann (1960), p. 218. Augustine (B, VII, 9.13, p. 125) himself specified that he had read “certain books of the Platonists, translated from Greek to Latin”. Alfaric (1918, vol. 1, p. 525) claimed that essentially Plato stands in relation to Plotinus as Plotinus stands in relation to Augustine. See also Cochrane (1957, p. 376). Jaeger (1961, p. 137, n. 10) remarked that Cochrane’s area of research was mostly Latin culture and added that, because of this, he underestimated the influence of Greek philosophy in the development of Christianity.

  8. 8.

    Plato (L), 326a-b.

  9. 9.

    Plato (G), 90a-b-c.

  10. 10.

    Augustine (C), vol. 1, XI, 2, pp. 437–8

  11. 11.

    Op. cit., vol. 2, XIV, 4, p. 6

  12. 12.

    Ibid. It is worth mentioning that Augustine (ibid., p. 7) quoted the First Letter to the Corinthians here, where Paul (2, 14) stated: “the natural man receiveth not the things of Spirit of God; for they are foolishness unto: neither can he know them, because they are spiritually discerned”. Addressing God, Augustine (B, VII, 21, 27, p. 136) “confessed”: “Most eagerly, then, did I seize the venerable writing of Thy Spirit, but more especially the Apostle Paul”. Paul was one of the links between Augustine and Greek culture. Hoffmann (1960, p. 148) rightly remarked: “in the Gospel there is no Hellas. But it is present in Paul’s letters. Paul wanted to be a Jew for the Jews, a Greek for the Greeks, and he was and had to be in order to carry out his mission as he understood it”. And also (ibid., p. 145): “The reception of Greek thought on the part of Christians already had its foundation in the fact that the Christian faith, in Paul and John, was taken up by minds shaped by the Greek style of education”.

  13. 13.

    Augustine (C), XIV, 4, p. 648.

  14. 14.

    Plato (G), 716c.

  15. 15.

    Protagoras (A) 1.

  16. 16.

    Hoffmann (1960), p. 176.

  17. 17.

    Ibid.

  18. 18.

    Plato (E), 81b.

  19. 19.

    Plato (A), 76e.

  20. 20.

    Ibid.

  21. 21.

    Plato (F), 518e.

  22. 22.

    Op. cit., 518c.

  23. 23.

    Jaeger (1986), vol. 2, p. 295.

  24. 24.

    Plato (F), 580a.

  25. 25.

    Augustine (B), VII, 10. 16 and 11. 17, pp. 128–9. It is worth comparing Augustine’s experience with Plotinus’s (A, IV, 8, 1): “Many times it has happened: liftet out of my body into my self, becoming external to all other things and self-centered, beholding a marvellous beauty, then, more than ever, assured of community with the loftiest order, enacting the noblest life, acquiring identity with the divine, stationing within It by having attained that activity, poised above whatsoever within the Intellectual is less than the Supreme yet, there comes the moment of descent from intellection to reasoning and after the sojourn in the divine, I ask myself how it happens that I can now be descending, and how did the Soul ever enter into my body, the Soul which, even within the body, is the high thing it has shown itself to be”.

  26. 26.

    Augustine (A), XXXIX, 72, p. 262.

  27. 27.

    I am using an expression taken from Simmel (1959), p. 31.

  28. 28.

    Grote (1867), vol. 3, p. 187. See also Zeller (1888), pp. 484–485. Popper (1966, vol. 1, p. 142) stressed that “Plato’s attitude towards religion […] is practically identical with that of Critias, his beloved uncle, the brilliant leader of the Thirty Tyrants, who established an inglorious blood-régime in Athens after the Peloponnesian war […]. In Critias’ view, religion is nothing but the lordly lie of a great and clever statesman”.

  29. 29.

    Kelsen (1938), p. 106.

  30. 30.

    Jaeger (1961), p. 66.

  31. 31.

    Jaeger (1986), vol. 2, p. 285. See also Reale (1997), vol. 2, pp. 272–281.

  32. 32.

    Jaeger (1964), p. 12.

  33. 33.

    Ibid., p. 94.

  34. 34.

    Ibid.

  35. 35.

    Ibid. See Parmenides (A), 1.

  36. 36.

    Jaeger (1964, p. 96) further commented: “No one who studies this supernatural overture could ever suppose that the philosopher’s aim in this passage is merely to provide an effective stage-setting. His mysterious vision in the realm of light is a genuine religious experience: when the weak human eye turns towards the hidden truth, life itself becomes transfigured. This is a kind of experience that has no place in the religion of the official cults. Its prototype is rather to be sought in the devotions we find in the mysteries and initiation ceremonies”. It is useful to compare the description Parmenides gave of his own “experience” with Plotinus’s and Augustine’s accounts (see note 25 in this chapter).

  37. 37.

    Jaeger (1964), pp. 106.

  38. 38.

    Ibid. We find the same method in Plotinus (A, V, 5, 11), who stated that God “is infinite also by right of being a pure unity with nothing towards which to direct any partial content. Absolutely One, it has never known measure and stands outside of number, and so is under no limit either in regard to any extern or within itself; for any such determination would bring something of the dual into it”. Plotinus works under the heavy burden of Plato’s Parmenides: the one is defined solely through negative determinations.

  39. 39.

    Jaeger (1964), p. 106.

  40. 40.

    Popper (1991), p. 12.

  41. 41.

    Jaeger (1961), p. 44.

  42. 42.

    Op. cit., p. 45.

  43. 43.

    Op. cit., p. 65.

  44. 44.

    Op. cit., p. 135. See Plato (H), 897b. Jaeger (1961, p. 135, note 39) stressed the fact that “Origen’s doctrine of the divine education of mankind” is a “new stage” in the history of paideia. In Jaeger’s opinion, the work which Koch (1932) carried out on Origen gives full legitimacy to such a conclusion.

  45. 45.

    Jaeger (1961), pp. 55–6.

  46. 46.

    Hoffmann (1960), p. 176.

  47. 47.

    Ibid.

  48. 48.

    Ibid. Hoffmann (ibid.) specified: “the stages are not the degrees of initiation of the epopts, but the stages of knowledge which the disciple […] must pass through […]. The redeemer […] is […] a man who has completed his studies and now must retrace his steps in to teach what he has learnt”.

  49. 49.

    Op. cit., p. 168. On the relationship between Orphism, Platonism and Plotinism, see the classic and detailed work by Macchioro (1922), which however does not figure among the references given by Hoffmann. On the other hand, Jaeger (1964, p. 58 and p. 216, note 13) did take Macchioro’s work into account. Macchioro’s book was translated into English in 1930 (From Orpheus to Paul: A History of Orphism).

  50. 50.

    Augustine (C), vol. 1, VIII, 5, p. 312.

  51. 51.

    Jaeger (1964), p. 48.

  52. 52.

    Hoffmann (1960), p. 214.

  53. 53.

    It is true that Plato made politics the “royal science”; and yet politics takes on that rank on account of being legitimated by its privileged connection with the divinity. It is thus a religious manifestation.

  54. 54.

    Plato (H), 890d.

  55. 55.

    Ibid., 903b.

  56. 56.

    Plato (B), 275b-c-d.

  57. 57.

    Ibid., 294a.

  58. 58.

    Plato (H), 910c-d.

  59. 59.

    Burckhardt (1929, vol. 1, p. 460–1) commented : “the family and its gods were the only refuge for the soul when it wanted to retreat from the polis”. The polis could not, and in realty did not, want to interfere with the soul of the individual. This is completely different from the “religious police” which Plato proposed. See, at greater length, Jones (1956, p. 91), Infantino (2003), pp. 2–4.

  60. 60.

    Plato (F), 500d.

  61. 61.

    Op. cit., 501a.

  62. 62.

    Op. cit., 735c.

  63. 63.

    Sternberger (1978), vol. 1, p. 298. In corroboration of Sternberger’s words, one may read the following passage from Plato (F, 735d-e): with regard to the “social purification, the case stands thus. There are many ways of effecting a purgation, some of them milder, some sharper. Some—the sharpest and best of all—will be at the disposal of one who is at once autocrat and legislator, but a legislator who establishes a new society and new laws with less than autocratic power will be well satisfied if he can so much as reach his end of purgation by the mildest of methods. The best method of all, like the most potent medicine, is painful; it is that which effects correction by combination of justice with vengeance, in the last instance, to the point of death or exile, usually with result of clearing society of its most dangerous members, great and incurable offenders”; see also 736a-b-c.

  64. 64.

    Plato (F), 462d.

  65. 65.

    Ibid.

  66. 66.

    Op. cit., 417a. For a detailed discussion of the issue, see Infantino (2003), pp. 41–48.

  67. 67.

    Popper (1966, p. 38) rightly wrote: “Plato’s greatness as a sociologist does not lie in his general and abstract speculations about the law of social decay. It lies rather in the wealth and detail of his observations, and in the amazing acuteness of his sociological intuition. He saw things which had not been seen before him, and which were rediscovered only in our own time. As an example, […] his emphasis upon the economic background of the political life and the historical development; a theory revived by Marx under the name of historical materialism”. On the relationship between economic freedom and political freedom, one should always bear in mind the pathbreaking contributions of James Harrington (1924) and François Bernier (1914). Cf. Pellicani (1979, 2005), Infantino (2003). In his extensive discussion of the issue, Pipes (1999) completely neglected Bernier’s work. See also note 86 in the next chapter.

  68. 68.

    Plato (D), 523b.

  69. 69.

    Plato (F), 551d, italics added.

  70. 70.

    Op. cit., 550e.

  71. 71.

    Porphyry (A, XII): “The Emperor Gallienus and his wife Salonina greatly honoured and venerated Plotinus, who thought to turn their friendly feeling to some good purpose. In Campania there had once stood, according to tradition, a City of Philosophers, a ruin now; Plotinus asked the Emperor to rebuild this city and to make over the surrounding district to the new-founded state; the population was to live under Plato’s laws: the city was to be called Platonopolis; and Plotinus undertook to settle down there with his associates. He would have had his way without more ado, but that opposition at court, prompted by jealousy, spite, or some such paltry motive, put an end to the plan”.

  72. 72.

    Paul (B), Letter to the Galatians, 3, 11–13.

  73. 73.

    Op. cit., 5, 18–22.

  74. 74.

    In the Acts of the Apostles (21, 17–24), it is stated: “And when we were come to Jerusalem, the brethren received us gladly. And the day following Paul went in with us unto James; and all the elders were present. And when he had salutated them, he declared particularly what things God had wrought among the Gentiles by his ministry. And when they heard it, they glorified the Lord, and said unto him, Thou seest, brother, how many thousands of Jews there are which believe; and they are all zealous of the law. And they are informed of thee, that thou teachest all the Jews which are among the Gentiles to forsake Moses, saying that they ought not to be circumcise their children, neither to walk after the customs. What is it therefore? The multitude must needs come together: for they will hear that thou art come. Do therefore this that we say to thee: We have four men which have a vow on them; Them take, and purify thyself with them, and be at charges with them, that they may shave their heads: and all may know that those things, whereof they were informed concerning thee, are nothing; but that thou thyself also walkest orderly, and keepest the law”.

  75. 75.

    Weber (1978), vol. 2, p. 1225.

  76. 76.

    Op. cit., p. 1227. Ortega (1933, p. 110) wrote: for Paul, “the law is an inextricable tangle where man loses his way. Enough with the law! Only the new union with God is necessary: faith, all that is needed is faith […]. Paul does not rule out […] the need for works in order to be saved, but – it is understood – works which spring from faith and not from the law”.

  77. 77.

    Paul, Second letter to the Corinthians, 6, 14–16.

  78. 78.

    Paul, Letter to the Ephesians, 4, 22–24.

  79. 79.

    Hoffmann (1960), pp. 223–4.

  80. 80.

    Op. cit., p. 197. Hoffmann (op. cit., p. 451, note 21) himself added that the use of the expression “foreign land” is authorized by Marcion, the “most rigid Pauline thinker ever”.

  81. 81.

    Augustine (C), vol. 2, XIV, 4, p. 7.

  82. 82.

    Op. cit., XIV, 28, p. 47.

  83. 83.

    Op. cit., XV, 1, p. 51.

  84. 84.

    Voegelin (2000, p. 176) wrote that the “church actually evolved from the eschatology of the real in history toward the eschatology of trans-historical, supernatural perfection”. He went on (op. cit., pp. 176–7) to point out that Augustine (C, vol. 2, XX, 7, 1, p. 356) dismissed as “ridiculous fancies” the “revolutionary expectation of a second Coming that would transfigure the structure of history on earth”. Voegelin saw in this a “break” between Augustine and John’s “revolutionary annunciation of the millennium in which Christ would reign with his saints on this earth” (op. cit., p. 176). The idea that the Church extinguished, or kept in check, the revolutionary message had already been well voiced by Troeltsch (1960, vol. 1, pp. 112–5). Nevertheless, there remains the fact that in Augustine’s work the earthly community of believers provides a foreshadowing of the celestial city. This, as indicated in the text, leads to the permanent temptation to coercively extend the “purity” of the “just” to the wicked, “saving” the latter from their perversions and sins. See also Boniolo (2011), pp. 226–229.

  85. 85.

    Sternberger (1978), vol. 1., p. 298. See also Pellicani (2007), p. 209.

  86. 86.

    Augustine (D), 2, 8, p. 402.

  87. 87.

    Op. cit., 1, 3, p. 379.

  88. 88.

    Op. cit., 2, 8, p. 382.

  89. 89.

    Op. cit., 2, 7, p. 381.

  90. 90.

    Ibid.

  91. 91.

    Op. cit., 2, 6, p. 400.

  92. 92.

    Augustine (E, 2, 11, pp. 185–6). It is therefore useful to point out that Brown (2000, p. 236) saw in Augustine “the first theorist of Inquisition”.

  93. 93.

    Augustine (C), vol. 1, V, 24, p. 223. Augustine (op. cit., V, 25–26, pp. 223–27) identified the imperator felix first in Constantine and then in Theodosius. The latter, as we know, was responsible for the edict of Thessalonica which “made Christianity a state religion, the Catholic church a state church and heresy a state crime” (Küng 1995, p. 183).

  94. 94.

    Augustine (D), 6, 20, p. 412, where he followed Paul (Letter to the Romans, 13, 1–4), who had already stated: “Let every soul be subject unto the higher powers. For there is no power but of God: the powers that be are ordained of God. Whosoever therefore resisteth the power, resisteth the ordinance of God; and they that resist shall receive to themselves damnation. For rulers are not a terror to good works, but to the evil. Wilt thou then not be afraid of the power? Do that which is good, and thou shalt have praise of the same: for he is the minister of God to thee for good”. If however authority descends from God and those who oppose it oppose the divinely established order, the life of the world becomes a providential plan, on the strength of which everything must find a justification. Which, mutatis mutandis, in Hegelian terms means that everything “which is real is rational”. We know that Hegel (1955, vol. 1, p. 49) presented his philosophy as “a theodicy, a justification of God”. On this topic, see Pellicani (2000), p. 31.

  95. 95.

    Popper (1966), vol. 1, p. 104.

  96. 96.

    On marriage as a form of exchange, see in particular Lévi-Strauss (1949).

  97. 97.

    Friedrich (1968), pp. 58–9.

  98. 98.

    Arendt (1962), p. 344.

  99. 99.

    Op. cit., p. 424.

  100. 100.

    This is why there can be regimes which are simply authoritarian or theocratic. And here one can agree with Friedrich, who did, however, overstep the mark when, in challenging the excessive expansion of the concept of totalitarianism, wrote (1968, p. 59): “if this view of totalitarianism were to be accepted, it would be necessary to describe the order of medieval (as well as other) monasteries as totalitarian; for it is certainly often characterized by such a scheme of total control of the life of its inmates”. Friedrich does not take into account the fact that entry into a monastery is voluntary and that a monastery is a small “circle”, placed within a much larger context provided with some freedom.

  101. 101.

    Plato (H), 797d.

  102. 102.

    I am making use here of an expression taken from Barbero (1965), p. 43.

  103. 103.

    For the distinction between “utopia” and “prophecy” the reader is referred to Popper (1991), pp. 336–46. One can in any case say that a utopian discloses the details of the future society, whereas the formulator of a prophecy, whether religiously or philosophically motivated, stops with the announcement of a new world. On this point, see Mises (1981, pp. 375–6), Pellicani (1996, p. 693). Marx (1976, vol. 1, p. 99) opposed the utopians and refused to write Comtian “recipes” for the “cook-shops of the future”. He formulated, that is, an “unconditioned prophecy”. Since the perfect world he announced is left to our imagination, his prophetic message has great power of delegitimation against an existing reality which is in any case “corrupt”. As explained in the text, the results which utopia and prophecy aim at are not however dissimilar. Once power has been achieved, even those who omitted any prefiguration of a future society will need to regulate social life in detail. This represents the all-pervading and at the same time the deepest triumph of “prescription”. Any possibility of choice is swept away.

  104. 104.

    It is very significant that, in referring to Christ, Luke (14, 25–26) wrote: “and he turned, and said unto them, ‘If any man come to me, and hate not his father, and mother, and wife, and children, and brethren, and sisters, yea, and his own life also, he cannot be my disciple’”.

  105. 105.

    Ortega y Gasset (1933, p. 103) gave a good description of the situation: “the issue is not this or that, but the life of the person in its entirety. It is not hunger, it is not diseases […], what now becomes problematic is the very being of the subject. And, if the response to those particular problems is called a solution, the one which needs to be given to the absolute problem of personal being is called salvation, soteria”. And if there is also the prospect of an afterlife, eternal salvation is added to its worldly variety.

  106. 106.

    As the bearers of salvific knowledge and morality, the “just” feel themselves alien to anything belonging to the material world. They thus avoid contamination with everything which is impure.

  107. 107.

    Augustine (H), vol. 2, 32, 20–21, p. 146.

  108. 108.

    Op. cit., 113, 4–4, p. 166.

  109. 109.

    Op. cit., 303c. According to Plato (H, 698a), Athens was the land of “entire freedom”, i.e. unbridled freedom.

  110. 110.

    Plato (B), 303a.

  111. 111.

    Troeltsch (1963), p. 137.

  112. 112.

    Sternberger (1978), vol. 1, p. 312.

  113. 113.

    As we know, Plato (I, 320b) acknowledged the antecedence of the Cretan constitution, going as far as to write that Minos “ordinated for his people those very laws, which have made Crete happy through the length of time, and Sparta happy also, since she began to use them; for they are divine”. The expression “myth of Sparta” is here used in the connotation suggested by Ollier, in his comprehensive two-volume work (1933, 1943).

  114. 114.

    Grote (1867), vol. 1, p. XI.

  115. 115.

    Plutarco (A, 5, 4).

  116. 116.

    Ollier (1933), p. 236.

  117. 117.

    Plato (F), 492a.

  118. 118.

    Ollier (1933), p. 236.

  119. 119.

    Plato (F), 501e.

  120. 120.

    Op. cit., 503d.

  121. 121.

    Plutarch (A), 24, 1.

  122. 122.

    See note 202 in Chap. 1.

  123. 123.

    The expression “monk-warrior” is from Pellicani (1995), p. 118.

  124. 124.

    Ferrero (1988), pp. 76–77.

  125. 125.

    Cf. also Settembrini (1974), pp. 102–103.

  126. 126.

    Ortega (1933), p. 120.

  127. 127.

    Op. cit., p. 77.

  128. 128.

    Ibid.

  129. 129.

    Ibid.

  130. 130.

    Gilson (1922), p. 147.

  131. 131.

    Ibid.

  132. 132.

    Op. cit., pp. 148–9.

  133. 133.

    Stark (2005), p. 55.

  134. 134.

    Ibid.

  135. 135.

    It is in this light that we need to interpret not only the work of scholastic philosophy, but also the output of late scholasticism: from Francisco de Vitoria to Luis de Molina and Juan de Mariana. Their contribution to the development of economic theory does not derive from the original principles of their religious doctrine, but from the need to understand the functioning of the rising capitalist world. It is therefore necessary to critically assess the work of Chafuen (1986) who, in attributing to the late scholastics a position in tune with the market economy, completely evades the underlying issue. This being that “social ethics applicable to earthly life can never be derived from words of the Gospels” (Mises 1981, p. 380).

  136. 136.

    This thesis was developed in an exemplary manner by Adam Smith. For the relevant references, see note 229 in Chap. 3. Cf. also Infantino (2008), pp. 39–66.

  137. 137.

    Mumford (1944), pp. 159–60

  138. 138.

    Op. cit., p. 160.

  139. 139.

    Letter to the faithful, written at Anagni, 24 August 1215, collected in Musca (1973), p. 94. Since the “lordship of the kingdom is due to the Roman Church”, King John, “could and should not have, without our specific mandate, changed anything within it so as to be to our detriment” (Ibid.). This was the reasoning advanced by Innocent III for his rejection of the Magna Charta. There is obviously a claim for the original sovereignty of the Roman Church, the power of which descends directly from God and the assignment of the King to the position of a “delegate”, who as such cannot act outside the remit of the powers delegated to him. This is the “doctrine of the two swords” (dating back to Gelasius), which was later dismantled with the rise of the modern State by the separation between politics and religion.

  140. 140.

    Thomas Aquinas (1952), p. 308. In order to fully appreciate Thomas’s position, it is worthwhile reading the following passage (1978, p. 157): “In regard to heretics two points must be kept in mind. The first with regard to heretics themselves. The second with regard to the Church. From the point of view of heretics themselves there is their sin, by which they have deserved not only to be separated from the Church, but to be eliminated from the world by death […]. On the part of the Church there is merciful hope of the conversion of those errors. For this reason She does not immediately condemn, ‘but only after a first and second admonition’, as the Apostle teaches. Only then, if the heretic remains pertinacious, the Church, despairing of his conversion, makes provision for the safety of others; and separating him, by the sentence of excommunication from the Church, passes him to secular judgement to be exterminated from the world by death. St. Jerome […] says, and we read: ‘The tainted flesh must be cut away, and the infected sheep cast out from the fold’[…]”.

  141. 141.

    Voegelin (2000), p. 175.

  142. 142.

    Op. cit., p. 178.

  143. 143.

    Pellicani (1995, pp. 16–17) in particular mentioned the cases of John Ball and Wat Tyler, as well as Jan Hus.

  144. 144.

    Léonard (1965), vol. 1, p. 42.

  145. 145.

    Ibid.

  146. 146.

    Op. cit., pp. 42–3. Léonard (op. cit., p. 41) wrote, more directly: “it was to St Augustine that Luther went for his interpretation of the Scriptures, that of the Psalms in 1513, and of the Pauline doctrine for his commentary on the Letter to the Romans. And finally, it was to be from St Augustine that he derived some of the doctrines and formulas in which he delighted to clothe his own philosophy: regeneration by faith, the frailty of human nature, the supreme power of Grace, and penitence. The influence was more profound because the great Augustinian antinomies, Spirit and Letter, Grace and Liberty, Gospel and Law, were admirably suited to his temperament and experience”.

  147. 147.

    Luther (1915), p. 347.

  148. 148.

    Léonard (1965), vol. 1, p. 297.

  149. 149.

    Calvin (2005), p. 40.

  150. 150.

    Boisset (1959), pp. 277–282.

  151. 151.

    Léonard (1965), vol. 1, pp. 304–5.

  152. 152.

    Op. cit., p. 305.

  153. 153.

    “Wretched masquerade” is an expression used by Sternberger (1978, vol. 1, p. 294).

  154. 154.

    Walzer (1965), p. 305. Walzer (op. cit., p. 30) stated: “Sure that the saints will not always and everywhere impose their discipline upon the fallen world, Calvin describes and justifies a purely secular repression. And he argues that this repression, brutal and bloody as it must be, nevertheless represents a considerable gain for a humanity alienated from God”. “Puritan zeal was not a private passion; it was instead a highly collective emotion and it imposed upon the saints a new and impersonal discipline […]. The conscientious activity that they favoured is perhaps best revealed in Cromwell’s New Army Model, with its rigid camp discipline, its elaborate rules against every imaginable sin, from looting and rapine to blasphemy and card-playing” (op. cit., pp. 12–13). As Cromwell himself wrote, “in the poor Army […] the great God has vouchsafed to appear” (Cromwell 1904, vol. 1, p. 397). The Army consists of “an aristocracy of grace, whose divinely appointed destiny is to conquer and rule the world” (Woodhouse 1951, p. 81). This means that freedom is exclusively of the Saints. And this is why Hasso Hofmann (1999, p. 13) wrote: “not only from the Catholic tradition, but also from the Reformed doctrines, there is non direct way which leads to the modern declarations of human rights. Christian freedom is freedom only in and from the truth of the faith. Correspondingly, the Christian is considered free and the non-Christian not free, whatever the social or legal status either of them have. Christian freedom is equality before God. But it distinguishes between truth and error and knows no equality between claims and truth”. It is significant that Hume (1903, p. 53) saw in Cromwell the real “absolute” monarch, a case which could be “sufficient to convince us that such a person will never resign his power, or establish any free government”. On the hostility of the Reformation to individualism, see also Mises (1978, pp. 39–42).

  155. 155.

    Ortega (1933), p. 98. Schwartz (1966, p. 143) himself stated that Greek ascetism “did not take the shape of that of the Christian hermits, as a battle against their sinful flesh”.

  156. 156.

    Ortega (1933), p. 109.

  157. 157.

    Descartes (1901b), p. 180. According to Ortega (1960, p. 401), Descartes experienced the “discovery of the method” as a “divine gift”, a “transcendent revelation”.

  158. 158.

    Descartes (1901a), p. 15.

  159. 159.

    Hayek (1988) aptly spoke of “fatal conceit”.

  160. 160.

    For an extensive list of the supporters of the “spirit of Sparta”, see Rawson (1969), Guerci (1979), Infantino (2003).

  161. 161.

    Rousseau (1997a), p. 11.

  162. 162.

    Rousseau (1997b), p. 175. Obviously, this is influenced by Fénelon (1847) who, for his Salento, took his inspiration from the Crete of Minos and the Sparta of Lycurgus.

  163. 163.

    Rousseau (1997a), p. 18. The theme of luxury will be dealt with in the next chapter. It however is appropriate to point out that here too Rousseau (op. cit., p. 19) was influenced by Fénelon (1847). As is known, Rousseau commented ironically on Voltaire, whose ideas on luxury were opposite to his own. On Voltaire and Rousseau, see Gouhier (1983). Cassirer (2000, p. 103) aptly wrote that, “in the middle of the Enlightenment, Rousseau raises his flaming invective against the ‘arts and sciences’ […, so that] all the values of culture are phantoms that we must renounce”. It is a rebellion against civilization. As Cassirer (1967, p. 96) further argued, Rousseau is “far from wishing to create room in his social and political ideal” for any “subjective inclination”, in other words he does not wish to allow any individual choice. On the subject, see also Bedeschi (2010).

  164. 164.

    Rousseau (1997a), p. 19.

  165. 165.

    Rousseau (1997c), p. 8.

  166. 166.

    Mably (1767), pp. 183–4. Therefore, it is not surprising that Rousseau and Mably were both criticized by Constant (1988), in his well-known essay comparing the liberty of the Ancients with that of Moderns. As we know, Constant considered the Athens of Pericles as the place where freedom of choice was first affirmed. The controversy, which in eighteenth century France opposed the supporters of the Spartan model and those of the Athenian model, shall be discussed in the next chapter.

  167. 167.

    Talmon (1952), pp. 64–5.

  168. 168.

    Cassirer (1967), p. 71. In relation to the Encylopaedists, Cassirer (op. cit., p. 66) also specified: “Everywhere a genuine and strong will to reform was at work; everywhere the most unsparing criticism was exercised on the Old Regime. And yet this will to reform neither explicity nor implicity rose to revolutionary demands. The thinkers of the Encyclopedist circle wanted to ameliorate and to cure; but hardly one of them believed in the necessity for, or in the possibility of, a radical transformation and reformation of state and society. They were satisfied when they succeeded in eliminating the worst abuses and in leading mankind gradually into better political conditions”. Even before Cassirer, this had been pointed out by Hubert (1923, 1928) Israel (2009, p. 232) recently stated that “the anti-Enlightenment purge hugely intensified once the Terror began”.

  169. 169.

    Cassirer (1967), p. 75.

  170. 170.

    Ibid.

  171. 171.

    Op. cit., p. 76.

  172. 172.

    Op. cit., p. 73.

  173. 173.

    Ibid.

  174. 174.

    Op. cit., p. 76.

  175. 175.

    Op. cit., p. 91.

  176. 176.

    Ibid.

  177. 177.

    Ibid.

  178. 178.

    Voegelin (2000).

  179. 179.

    This is why Ferrero (1986, pp. 121–122) identified not one, but “two French revolutions”, the one of 1789 and the revolution of 18 Brumaire, which in actual fact started on 2 June 1793: “The coup of 2 June was an event of an incalculable impact. It marked the definitive failure of the first French revolution: the revolution of 1789, […] of Mirabeau and Talleyrand, who had tried to give France a representative government based on a regime of political freedom. The second revolution was about to begin and it would be the negation of the first, the revolution of 1799 and of 18 Brumaire, the Constitution of year VIII and the Consulate, the revolution from which the first totalitarian government of Europe issued […]. This dualism of revolutions is still tearing the world apart one hundred and fifty years later. The current struggle is only its extension. The Anglo-Saxons fight for the revolution of 1789 and the totalitarian regimes for the revolution of 1799”.

  180. 180.

    Tocqueville (1983), pp. 12–3.

  181. 181.

    Op. cit., p.146. With specific regard to the government of the Convention, it is useful to underline the opinion expressed by Ferrero (1981, p. 212): [the Convention] “jettisons the principle of democratic legitimacy and, on its ruins, erects Public Safety, as conceived by its frenetic terror: the bloodthirsty idol, the insatiable Moloch to whom it sacrifices the majority, and all of human rights, as well as the opposition and thousands of victims of beheading, drowning and grapeshot”.

  182. 182.

    Tocqueville (1983), p. 157. This new species of actors are the “professional revolutionaries”: see Pellicani (1975).

  183. 183.

    Loewith (1949), p. 42.

  184. 184.

    Walzer (1965), pp. 304–305. Puritan radicalism, that is, leads to Jacobin radicalism. Bernstein (1930, p. 10) wrote: “[The] Girondists were the Presbyterians; [… the] Jacobins or the Mountain were the Independents; [… the] Hébertists and Babeuvists were the Levellers, whilst Cromwell was a combination of Robespierre and Bonaparte”.

  185. 185.

    Voegelin (2000), p. 221.

  186. 186.

    Social relations are “antagonistic”; that is, they create the conditions for the outbreak of “revolution”, which is exactly a civil war.

  187. 187.

    Marx (1984b), p. 89.

  188. 188.

    Communism thus produces “redemption from conflict”, it delivers humankind from the “wicked”. This is the basic belief which Marxian preaching tries to instill. The economic mechanisms, which with “iron necessity” cause the collapse of the capitalist system, are only the instrument, devoid of any scientific basis, through which a prophecy which should be self-fulfilling is erected; Cf. Infantino (1998, p. 56).

  189. 189.

    Marx (1984b), p. 79.

  190. 190.

    Nazism inherited from the Younger German historical school of economics the idea that relations between nations are “antagonistic”. See Schmoller (1897).

  191. 191.

    Cf. Hitler’s speech at the opening of the House of German Art in Munich (July 18, 1937), in Sax and Kuntz (1992), pp. 224–32.

  192. 192.

    The expressions in inverted commas are exactly the ones Hitler used in a famous interview and are reported in Calic (1971), p. 68. For a deeper analysis of the issue, the reader is referred to Pellicani (2009) and the vast bibliography provided therein.

  193. 193.

    Hitler (1941), p. 907.

  194. 194.

    Voegelin (2000), p. 180.

  195. 195.

    It is significant that Ernst Bloch, a thinker “who was generally considered a Marxist, or in any case passed off as one” (Sternberger 1978, vol. 1, p. 277), wrote that “the civitas Dei is triumphant when the earthly State goes to the devil, the devil whom it belongs to” (quoted by Sternberger 1978, vol. 1, p. 356).

  196. 196.

    As we have already said, such a project has a prevalently nihilistic character. Kolakowski (1977, p. 12) rightly spoke of a promise of “liberation through negation”. Fisichella (1987, p. 70) argued that the totalitarian project is what it is because it “wants to change the totality”; and added: “the basic political assumption […] is to erase the existent and build an entirely original city”. It is no accident that Ferrero (1898, p. 65) saw in the late nineteenth century German Social Democratic organization a kind of “State within the State”, which had in propaganda “a colossal, tireless dredge” which could constantly clean out the minds of believers (op. cit., pp. 65–69). On Kautsky and German Social Democracy, see Settembrini’s outstanding analysis (1974).

  197. 197.

    Engels (1939, p. 318) wrote: “The seizure of the means of production by society put an end to commodities production and therewith to the domination of the product over the producer. Anarchy in social production is replaced by conscious organization on a planned basis. The struggle for individual existence comes to an end”. The condition of scarcity is thus envisioned as a “bourgeois” creation. This point of view was expressed by Bucharin (1971, p. 11) in the following terms: “as soon as we look at an organized social economy, all fundamental ‘problems’ of political economy […] vanish”. On the “end of economy”, see Ricossa (2006). It remains however to be emphasized that Marx (1976, vol. 3, pp. 958–9) was very much aware of the impossibility of doing away with scarcity: “The realm of freedom really begins only where labour determined by necessity and external expediency ends; it lies by its very nature beyond the sphere of material production proper. Just as the savage must wrestle with nature to satisfy his needs, to maintain and reproduce his life, so must civilized man, and he must do so in all forms of society and under all possible modes of production”.

  198. 198.

    Mises (1981, p. 485; 1969a, p. 56; 1998), p. 6. The generalized system of interventionism established by Nazism obviously allowed “regime profits” to be made, profits, that is, which were obtained through the “protection” and connivance of public power. This does not, however, mean that National Socialism was in favour of the market. See also Barkai (1990, p. 248). And in any case Bettelheim (1971, vol. 1, p. 67) was also forced at least to recognize that under Nazism “the right” of capital to be freely invested was “greatly limited”. Hilferding (1947, p. 299) explained: “It is the essence of a totalitarian state that it subjects the economy to its aims. The economy is deprived of its own laws, it becomes a controlled economy. Once this control is effected, it transforms the market economy into a consumers’ economy. The character and extent of needs are then determined by the state. The German and Italian economies provide evidence of the fact that such control, once initiated in a totalitarian state, spreads rapidly and tends to become all-embracing as was the case in Russia from the very beginning”. In reference to Fascism, see in particular Settembrini (2001).

  199. 199.

    Mises (1981), p. 485; 1969a, p. 56; b; 1998, p. 6.

  200. 200.

    Marx (1984a, p. 62).

  201. 201.

    Evola (1981, p. 39) wrote : “the Jew was equated with those who have money as their only […]. The struggle against the Jew, against the Saujude, placed as the lynch-pin in the construction of the Third Kingdom, was confused with the struggle against the most characteristic aspects of modern economic and intellectual decadence, against all those things which, through different but converging paths, tried to stifle the ancient values of quality, dignity, honour, disinterest, race and aristocracy: it was confused essentially with the struggle against the civilization of the merchant and the usurer”.

  202. 202.

    Russell (1962), pp. 28–29.

  203. 203.

    Russell (1947), pp. 12–13. What produced distortionary effects in the perception of the Soviet and Nazi regimes was the fact that the former portrayed itself as internationalist and the latter as nationalist. Internationalism is an element which Marx took from liberal culture. And Spengler (1924, p. 2) vigorously suggested the need to “free German socialism from Marx”. Russell (1962, p. 29) also wrote that Bolshevism “is internally aristocratic”. It is consequently surprising that Gomperz (1905, vol. 3, p. 106) ruled out the possibility of seeing Plato as a “forerunner of the modern socialists and communists”. He stated that these “modern movements strive to obtain for the community as a whole”, while “Plato proposed to enact merely for his upper or ruling class of warriors and guardians” (ibid.). Gomperz did not realize that, even when collectivism is justified by egalitarian ideologies, it is always accompanied by the resort to a “privileged point of view on the world”, a knowledge possessed aristocratically by an elite which thus takes over the authoritative roles. It should also be said that Durkheim (1958, p. 15) made a clear distinction between modern socialism and the Platonic utopia, maintaining that “it is not possible that a social organization, conceived in contemplation of the industrial societies we actually have under our eyes, could have been imagined when these societies had not yet been born”. It escaped Durkheim’s notice that behind the industrial development of the West stands the rise of the market. And Plato was hostile to private property, the market and democracy: institutions which originate, develop and die together. Durkheim’s “oversight” is particularly serious, because he should at least have taken into account Constant’s lesson on Athenian democracy.

  204. 204.

    See note 108 in Chap. 1.

  205. 205.

    In this way, they commit an obvious logical error. See Chap. 1, note 110.

  206. 206.

    Plato (F), 389b.

  207. 207.

    The term just assassin” is Sternberger’s (1978, vol. 1, p. 288).

  208. 208.

    Despite having stated that “a constitution founded on the greatest possible human freedom, according to laws which enable the freedom of each individual to exist by the side of the freedom of others […], is […] a necessary idea”, Kant (1922, p. 257) wrote that it was wise to explore the Platonic project, thus showing that he did not have the slightest understanding of how foreign that project was to his political philosophy. Basing himself on Kant, Cassirer (1944, p. 86) also argued that “the great mission of Utopia is to make room for the possible as opposed to a passive acquiescence in the present state of affairs”. And he specified (op. cit., p. 85) that “the great political and social reformers are indeed constantly under the necessity of treating the impossible as though it were possible”. Cassirer failed to appreciate the true character of utopia, which is not just a simple social reform, but a plan to reshape man and existence. The reformer tries to correct a mistake. The utopian tries to remake the world: and this has no connection with the improvement of the conditions of individual and social life. Along the same lines, Ruyer (1950, p. 125) wrote that “the utopian exercise among the ruled is a good antidote to the propaganda and ideology imposed by the rulers”. But one can easily object to Ruyer that it is not the “utopian exercise” which protects the ruled, but rather the limitation of power they impose on rulers.

  209. 209.

    Dahrendorf (1958), p. 116.

  210. 210.

    Ibid.

  211. 211.

    The expression “a society of comrades” is taken from Bucharin and Preobrazenskij (1966, p. 114).

  212. 212.

    Marx and Engels (1984), p. 238.

  213. 213.

    Engels (1939), p. 315.

  214. 214.

    Mises (1981), pp. 279–91.

  215. 215.

    This means that, whatever circumstances co-exist, the clash remains the one foreshadowed by the Platonic-Augustinian design, i.e. that between the City of Good and the City of Evil. The Marxian idea that the collapse of the system would be brought about by the irreparable conflict caused by the simultaneous occurrence of a falling rate of profit and growing impoverishment, is a plain lie, transcribed into the language of economic theory. The Marxian announcement has the aim of disseminating a notion which has to be believed. The goal is to fuel the polarization between two opposing sides, where nostridad embodies the principle of Good and alteridad the principle of Evil. See Infantino (1998), p. 55. The positions held by Lenin and Hitler were no different: the clash must be the “final solution”.

  216. 216.

    As we know, Tocqueville (1994, pp. 121–4) laid great stress on the co-adaptability of interests, an idea which he believed to be alien to revolutionary extremism. Furet (1978, pp. 49–50) significantly wrote: “French thinkers substantially ignore the resort to the final harmony of interests and the common utility of particular conflicts; and even when they focus on economics […], as in the case of Physiocrats, they have to embody the social in an unified image, namely the rational authority of a legal despotism, because they continue to cleave to a political vision of the social”. Even though the term “harmony” is misplaced, Furet’s passage is useful in understanding “Tocqueville’s problem”. It is also worthwhile recalling that Drewermann (1991, p. 181), in referring to Christianity, stated that there is “hidden inside a pathological element, which transforms intentions” into their “opposites”. But the “pathological” element is not “hidden” at all. It resides in the very nature of the salvific project, in the idea of reshaping man and the world. Here too, therefore, we are confronted by “Tocqueville’s problem”.

  217. 217.

    Social reality is a product of intersubjective relations. This is an idea which was greatly emphasized by Simmel, but which is also the keystone of methodological individualism. Intersubjectivity as a constituent element of reality was extensively discussed by Schutz (1962a, b); Cf. also Berger and Luckmann (1967).

  218. 218.

    As we know, Rousseau tried to identify the “general will”, understood as the “point of view of society” which is independent of the interests of individuals. The failure of this endeavour is borne out by the following statement written by Rousseau (1970, pp. 68–9) himself: “To discover the best rules of society suited to each Nation would require a superior intelligence who saw all of man’s passions and experienced none of them, who had no relation to our nature yet knew it thoroughly, whose happiness was independent of us and who was nevertheless willing to care for ours; finally, one who, preparing his distant glory in the progress of times, could work in one century and enjoy the reward in another. It would require gods to give men laws”. If however such divinities existed, there would be no individual freedom of choice. Here too one can see that Rousseau is influenced by Fénelon (1847, p. 209, italics added): “to speak freely, are not men to be pitied, for their necessary subjection to a mortal like themselves? A god only can fulfil the duties of dominion”.

  219. 219.

    Orwell (1949, p. 24) spoke of “reality control”, an expression which does not fully convey the idea. Nevertheless, the “Ministry of Truth” (op. cit., p. 29) presupposes precisely that reality is uni-determined.

  220. 220.

    Ferrero (1981, pp. 221–222) rightly argued that Napoleon Bonaparte was the first to use the press as an instrument to counterfeit social reality: “he runs the whole press like someone conducting an orchestra and he turns it into a gigantic gramophone player, which every day, for his subjects and his enemies, plays the same record: that he is the infallible and invincible one”. In corroboration of his words, Ferrero quoted the following statement by Metternich: “The newspapers for Napoleon are worth more than an army of three hundred thousand men, which would definitely be incapable of watching over the interior and scaring the exterior better than his half a dozen hired pen-pushers”. It is also worthwhile recalling that it was Napoleon who conferred a negative connotation to the term “ideologue”, using it “as a favourite expression of contempt for all who ventured to defend freedom against him” (Hayek 1979, p. 209). He felt “repugnance for all discussion and teaching of political matters” (op. cit., p. 210, the expression is however A.C. Thibaudeau’s). When he was able to, he eliminated or obstructed the teaching of moral and political sciences. Napoleon did not hesitate to ban the publication of the second edition of J.B. Say’s Traité d’économie politique, and Destutt de Tracy’s Commentaire sur l’esprit des lois. Making use of Ferrero (1981) once again, one could say that Napoleon, sensing the illegitimacy of his power, was “afraid” of the least signs or possibilities of opposition. And without resorting to Ferrero, one could also understand that rulers, particularly when they embody total power or aspire to it, fear any kind of critical discussion. Xenophon (A) had already drawn attention to the fear which grips tyrants: “kings find it always necessary to march as through an enemy’s country”, because they “never really are at peace with those whom they hold in subjection; nor dares a tyrant rely upon the faith of any treaty which he makes with the rest of mankind” (op. cit., cap. 7, pp. 325–6).

  221. 221.

    Nietzsche (1986), p. 40.

  222. 222.

    It is worthwhile recalling that Orwell (1949) aptly referred to “reality control”, “double think” and “newspeak”. On the issue, see also Klemperer (2006).

  223. 223.

    Cf . Arendt (1961, pp. 136–41), Belohradsky (1979, pp. 22–25).

  224. 224.

    Popper (1966), vol. 2, p. 94. Hayek (1972, p. 139) himself wrote: “The enemy, whether be internal, like the Jew or the kulak, or external, seems to be an indispensable requisite in the armoury of a totalitarian leader”.

  225. 225.

    Popper (1991), p. 8. In this way, “manifest truth” is the “privilege” of the pure. It is therefore a “privileged point of view on the world”.

  226. 226.

    Popper (1966), vol. 2, p. 95.

  227. 227.

    Ibid.

  228. 228.

    Ferrero (1981, p. 41) significantly wrote “Power is afraid of men who can rebel”. And in the case of totalitarian power, fear takes on an obsessive character. As we know, Hobbes (1651, p. 106) observed that public power has the strength to form “by terror” the wills of all. But it is also true, taking Ferrero’s position on board, that rulers are “afraid” of the ruled, because the latter can at any time withdraw the consent on which public power is based.

  229. 229.

    See Mises (1969b), p. 17.

  230. 230.

    Spencer (1881, p. 46) rightly wrote that in communism “the army is simply the mobilized society and the society is the quiescent army”. This is applicable to every totalitarian regime. It should not be forgotten, furthermore, that the political leader, who is the bearer of the salvific message, is also the military leader. Permanent mobilization “alters” the individual, keeping him constantly outside himself, so that he cannot think critically, keep a distance from the existent and commit what Orwell (1949) called “thoughtcrimes”. And the hatred of those who are different is a precise consequence of having the conceit of owning the “formula” with which to regenerate the human condition, which has “lapsed” because of the intervention of the forces of Evil. Weber (1946, p. 125) aptly wrote that anyone who “wants to establish absolute justice on earth by force” must hold out “the satisfying of hatred and the craving of revenge; above all, resentment and the need for a pseudo-ethical self-righteousness: the opponents must be slandered and accused of heresy”.

  231. 231.

    Ferrero (1981), p. 219.

  232. 232.

    Ibid. In analysing Leninism, Selznick (1952, p. 6) stated that its “over-all aim” was a “total transformation of society”, investing “every institution with political meaning”. In the light of what has been said in the text, this is equivalent to stating that public power should englobe every moment of social life, in order to prevent even the slightest form of dissent.

  233. 233.

    Engels (1939), p. 315.

  234. 234.

    Lenin (1974), p. 475.

  235. 235.

    See Mises (1969a, 1977).

  236. 236.

    Comte (1974, p. 145) went as far as to state that in the “re-organised society” there will be no more room for chance. For Hegel, on the other hand, the problem was already settled. He (1955, vol. 1, p. 29) wrote: “We must take into history the belief and the thought that the world of the will has not put itself into the hands of chance. That in what happens to peoples the dominating element should be an ultimate end, that in universal History there should be a reason – and not the reason of a particular person, but divine absolute reason – is a truth that we assume; its proof is the very way History is treated: it is the symbol and act of reason”. As Ortega (1960, p. 391) stressed, “historians are horrified by chance. It irritates and offends them because, in their opinion – the childish opinion historians are accustomed to express – chance is a negation of historical science, in that it is the power which is the enemy of “reason”. Since, furthermore, between the lines of their writing chance roams constantly like an enfant terrible, mocking them and their “reason”, they see it not only as the enemy of the possibility of history, but as the great insolent knave who, always hanging around putting on cynical displays, threatens the decency of science. It is however clear that the historian of the future will, at last!, be a historian who, by placing chance in reality, as one of its ingredients, will not hesitate to give it his attention, emphasising its appearance and influence, in exactly the same way he does with other historical forces”. The opposite of intentional order is what occurs when individuals, in the attempt to pursue their own ends, cooperate voluntarily. Here the mutual co-adaptation of actions gives rise to an unintended order, which does not derive from the plans of a single mind or the prescriptions of a restricted group of rulers. See, extensively, Infantino (1998).

  237. 237.

    It is worth recalling what Ferrero (1981, p. 222) wrote regarding the Napoleonic administrative apparatus: “Napoleon was the first to transform the Administration into a machine to produce enthusiasm: speeches, demonstrations, processions, triumphal arches, agendas, booklets, pamphlets, illustrated apologetical leaflets, presentations of keys at the gates of cities, showers of flowers, popular receptions. Napoleon is the first to organize the enthusiasms of the people, subtracting them from political parties, into a kind of State monopoly”.

  238. 238.

    The expression “charismatic bureaucracy” is from Belohradsky (1979, pp. 54–57).

  239. 239.

    As far as factional battles are concerned, it is enough to think of the Stalinist “purges” under communism and the “night of the long knives” under Nazism. Obviously, the exponents of the victorious group proclaim themselves to be genuine defenders of “public safety”; they thus present their crimes as an act of “truth” and “self-defence” on the part of the State or, that is, of the order they have imposed and from which they benefit. As we know, Fromm (1973) dwelt at length on the personalities of Stalin and of Hitler. He identified the former as a clinical case of “nonsexual sadism”, or in other terms “mental sadism”, characterized by the fact that Stalin enjoyed “to assure people that they were safe, only to arrest them a day or two later […]. Stalin could enjoy the sadistic pleasure of knowing the man’s real fate at the same time that he was assuring him of his favour” (op. cit., p. 285). As far as Hitler is concerned, a few days before he betrayed him and had him killed, he had an amiable conversation with Ernst Röhm. And yet, even without going to the extent of analysing the personalities of certain political criminals, one can understand, using what has been said in the text, that it is the utopian-totalitarian design which fuels simulation and betrayal. Fromm also emphasized Hitler’s “necrophilia”, marked by the “disproportionality between the destruction he ordered and the realistic reasons for it” (op. cit., p. 401). But here too one can say that the utopian-totalitarian programme, having the reshaping of man and the world as its goal, expresses an extremely powerful destructive charge against existing reality. It is therefore necessary to repeat that investigating the personalities of certain political criminals can be important. But one should not forget that, in the absence of that given habitat, their “perversions” would not have been able to materialize. These men were responsible for the crimes they committed. And yet the context made it possible for them to be selected as leaders and allowed their crimes to be committed. It is significant that, in analyzing the politico-social conditions created by the French Revolution, Burke (1951, p. 216) had already foreseen that a military leader would have been selected who would become the “master” of France. See also Chap. 4, note 127, with the text it refers to.

  240. 240.

    Cf. the comments made on the subject in Chap. 1, Sect. 1.3. As Simmel (1908, p. 38) stressed , in intersubjective relations there is always a “negative reserve” in one part of our personality, which does not enter into the relationship or which we simply do not display.

  241. 241.

    Weber (1946), p. 125.

  242. 242.

    Ibid.

  243. 243.

    Topitsch (1973), p. 212.

  244. 244.

    Mises (1978), p. 153.

  245. 245.

    Ibid.

  246. 246.

    The “emotional revolutionism” is a part of the phase of mobilisation which Weber (1978, vol. 2, p. 1231) himself called statu nacendi. The transition to “everyday life”, the institutionalization of the “message”, that is, is “justified” by the salvific promise which becomes the “conventional phraseology” of any hierarchical positioning. Since it presents itself as the realization of the Good, the new hierarchy avoids being supervised in any way and fuels a bloody, relentless and base battle to secure power. This bears out Hannah Arendt (1963): in the actions of apparatchiks there is nothing heroic; hence the “banality of evil” which they carry out.

  247. 247.

    Mises (1978), p. 153.

  248. 248.

    In this connection, a perfect example is the case of Trotskij (1972), who invoked the “betrayal” of the revolution only because he was the loser in his struggle with Stalin. See Mises (1981, pp. 513–8) and the classic criticism, from a socialist position, delivered by Rizzi (1977). Cf. also Mises (1978), p. 217.

  249. 249.

    Popper (1966), vol. 1, p. 172.

  250. 250.

    Weber (1952), pp. 108–9.

  251. 251.

    Op. cit., p. 109.

  252. 252.

    Ibid.

  253. 253.

    Op. cit., pp. 110–1.

  254. 254.

    Op. cit., p. 111.

  255. 255.

    Ortega (1960, p. 423). Ricciotti (1955, vol. 1, pp. 386–387) presented the dispute between Amasia, priest of Bethel, and Amos, as hinging on economic reasons. And yet, if one has a clear understanding of the task of the “prophet of doom”, it is difficult to accept such an interpretation. The prime concern of Amasia is to denounce the preaching of the prophet before King Jeroboam: “Amos hath conspired against thee in the midst of the house of Israel; the land is not able to bear all his words” (Amos, 7,10). And the fact that this is the problem is borne out by the order: “but prophesy not again any more at Beth-el: for it is the kin’s chapel, and it is the king’s court” (Amos, 7, 13). In other words, Amasia is afraid that Amos’s preaching may delegitimise established power. And he commands Amos: “O thou seer, go, flee thee away into the land of Judah, and there eat bread, and prophecy there” (Amos, 7, 12). But the urgency of Amos is not represented by “bread”, so much so that he answers: “I was not prophet, neither was I a prophet’s son; but I was an herdman, and a gatherer of sycomore fruit; and the Lord took me as I followed the flock, and the Lord said unto me, Go, prophecy unto my people Israel” (7, 14–15).

  256. 256.

    Ricciotti (1955), vol. 1, p. 389, italics added.

  257. 257.

    Amos (8, 9–10).

  258. 258.

    Ricciotti (1955), vol. 1, p. 393. And yet the killing of the prophet did not prevent honours being paid to him posthumously; see Matthew (23, 29), Acts of the apostles (7, 52). Ricciotti (op. cit., p. 395) also wrote: “The attitude of the masses towards prophets was the ordinary attitude of moral pigmies confronted by giants who had appeared in their midst: an illogical, changeable attitude which fluctuated between veneration and repulsion, trust and incomprehension, which in a moment of feral exasperation stoned the giant but immediately afterwards, with those same stones soaked with his blood, erected a monument to him”.

  259. 259.

    Weber (1952), p. 130.

  260. 260.

    Ibid.

  261. 261.

    Op. cit., p. 131.

  262. 262.

    Op. cit., pp. 131–2.

  263. 263.

    Popper (1966, vol. 1, p. 172) quite rightly wrote: “When I speak of the rigidity of tribalism I do not mean that no changes can occur in the tribal ways of life. I mean rather that the comparatively infrequent changes have the character of religious conversions or revulsions”.

References

  • Alfaric P. (1918) L’évolution intellectuelle de St. Augustin, Paris: Nourry.

    Google Scholar 

  • Aquinas (1952) Compendium of Theology, St. Louis and London: Herder.

    Google Scholar 

  • Aquinas (1978) Summa Theologica, in Aquinas (1978c).

    Google Scholar 

  • Arendt H. (1961) Between Past and Future, New York: Viking Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Arendt H. (1962) The Origins of Totalitarianism, Cleveland and New York: Meridien Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Arendt H. (1963) Eichmann in Jerusalem, New York: Viking Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Barbero G. (1965) Introduzione to Il pensiero politico cristiano, vol. 2, Torino: Utet.

    Google Scholar 

  • Barkai A. (1990), Nazi Economics, Oxford: Berg.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bedeschi G. (2010) Il rifiuto della modernità. Saggio su Jean-Jacques Rousseau, Firenze: Le Lettere.

    Google Scholar 

  • Belohradsky V. (1979) “Rivoluzione e burocrazia”, in Belohradsky V. (ed.), Rivoluzione e burocrazia, Roma: Città Nuova.

    Google Scholar 

  • Berger P.L., Luckmann T. (1967) The Social Construction of Reality, London: Allen Lane/Penguin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bernier F. (1914) Travels in the Mogul Empire, London and New York: Milford/Oxford U.P.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bernstein E. (1930) Cromwell and Communism, London: Allen & Unwin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bettelheim C. (1971) L’économia allemande sous le nazisme, Paris: Maspero.

    Google Scholar 

  • Boisset J. (1959) Sagesse et sainteté dans le pensée de Calvin, Paris: P.U.F.

    Google Scholar 

  • Boniolo G. (2011) Il pulpito e la piazza, Milano: Cortina.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brown P. (2000) Augustine of Hippo, Berkeley/Los Angeles: University of California Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bucharin N. (1971) Economics of the Transformation Period, New York: Bergman Publishers.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bucharin N., Preobrazenskij E. (1966) The Abc of Communism, London: Penguin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Burckhardt J. (1929) Griechische Kulturgeschichte, Leipzig: Kröner.

    Google Scholar 

  • Burke E. (1951) Reflections on the French Revolution, London: Dent.

    Google Scholar 

  • Calic E. (1971) Unmasked. Two Confidential Interview with Hitler in 1931, London: Ghatto & Windus.

    Google Scholar 

  • Calvin J. (2005) “Epistle to Faithful Showing that Christ Is the End of the Law” in Commentaires, Grand Rapids: Ethereal Library.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cassirer E. (1944) An Essay on Man, New Haven: Yale U.P.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cassirer E. (1967) The Question of Jean Jacques Rousseau, Bloomington and London: Indiana U.P.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cassirer E. (2000) The Logic of Cultural Sciences, New Haven: Yale U.P.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chafuen A.A. (1986) Christians for Freedom: Late-Scholastic Economics, San Francisco: Ignatius Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cochrane C.N. (1957) Christianity and Classical Culture, New York: Oxford U.P.

    Google Scholar 

  • Comte A. (1974) The Crisis of Industrial Civilization: The Early Essays of Auguste Comte, London: Heinemann.

    Google Scholar 

  • Constant B. (1988), “The Liberty of the Ancients Compared with that of the Moderns”, in Constant (1988c)

    Google Scholar 

  • Cromwell O. (1904) The Letters and Speeches, (S.C. Lomas ed.), London: Methuen.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dahrendorf R. (1958) “Out of Utopia”, in American Journal of Sociology, vol. 64, pp. 115–27.

    Google Scholar 

  • Descartes R. (1901a) Discourse on Method, in Descartes (1901c).

    Google Scholar 

  • Descartes R. (1901b) Metaphisical Meditations, in Descartes (1901c).

    Google Scholar 

  • Drewermann E. (1991) Der Krieg und das Christentum, Regensburg: Pustet.

    Google Scholar 

  • Durkheim É. (1958) Socialism and Saint Simon, Yellow Springs: Antioch Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Engels F. (1939), Herr Eugen Dühring’s Revolution in Science (Antidühring), New York, International Publishers.

    Google Scholar 

  • Evola J. (1981), Il nuovo mito germanico del Terzo Regno, Padova: Il Corallo.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fénelon F. de (1847) The Adventures of Telemachus, Manchester: Johnson.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ferrero G. (1898) L’Europa giovane, Milano: Treves.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ferrero G. (1981) Potere. I geni invisibili della città, Milano: SugarCo.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ferrero G. (1986) Le due rivoluzioni francesi, Milano: SugarCo.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ferrero G. (1988) La rovina della civiltà antica, Milano: SugarCo.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fisichella D. (1987) Totalitarismo, Roma: La Nuova Italia.

    Google Scholar 

  • Friedrich C.J. (1968) “The Evolving Theory and Practice of Totalitarian Regimes”, in Il Politico, vol. 33, pp. 53–76.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fromm E. (1973) The Anatomy of Human Destructiveness, New York: Holt, Rinehart & Winston.

    Google Scholar 

  • Furet F. (1978) Penser la Révolution française, Paris: Gallimard.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gilson É (1922) La philosophie au moyen âge, Paris: Payot.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gomperz T. (1905) Greek Thinkers. A History of Ancient Philosophy, London: Murray.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gouhier H. (1983) Rousseau et Voltaire. Portraits dans deux Miroirs, Paris: Vrin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Grote G. (1867) Plato and the Other Companions of Sokrates, London: Murray.

    Google Scholar 

  • Guerci L. (1979) La libertà degli antichi e la libertà dei moderni, Napoli: Guida.

    Google Scholar 

  • Harrington J. (1924) The Commonwealth of Oceana, Heidelberg: Winters.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hayek F.A. (1972) The Road to Serfdom, Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hayek F.A. (1979) The Counter-Revolution of Science, Indianapolis: Liberty Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hayek F.A. (1988) The Fatal Conceit, London: Routledge.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Hegel G.W.F. (1955) Vorlesungen über dei Philosophie der Geschichte, Hamburg: Meiner.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hilferding R. (1947) “State Capitalism or Totalitarian State Economy?”, in Modern Review, June 1947, pp. 266–71.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hitler A. (1941) Mein Kampf, New York: Reynal & Hitchcock.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hitler A. (1992) “Hitler’s Speech at the Opening of the House of German Art in Munich”, in B.C. Sax, D. Kuntz (eds), Inside Hilter’s Germany, Lexington (Mass.): Health.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hobbes Th. (1651) Leviathan, London: Crooke.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hoffmann E. (1960) Platonismus und christliche Philosophie, Zürich: Artemis.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hofmann H. (1999) Die Entdeckung der Menschenrechte, Berlin: de Gruyter.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Hubert R. (1923) Les sciences sociales dans l’Encyclopédie, Paris: Alcan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hubert R. (1928) Rousseau et l’Encyclopédie, Paris: Gamber.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hume D. (1903) Essays Moral, Political and Literary, London: Richards.

    Google Scholar 

  • Infantino L. (1998), Individualism in Modern Thought. From Adam Smith to Hayek, London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Infantino L. (2003) Ignorance and Liberty, London-New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Infantino L. (2008) Individualismo, mercato e storia delle idee, Soveria Mannelli: Rubbettino.

    Google Scholar 

  • Israel J. (2009) The Revolution of the Mind, New Jersey: Princeton U.P.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Jaeger W. (1961) Early Christianity and Greek Paidea, Cambridge (Mass.): Belnap Press of Harvard U.P

    Google Scholar 

  • Jaeger W. (1964) The Theology of the Early Greek Philosophers, Westport: Greenwood Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jaeger W. (1986) Paidea, New York: Oxford U.P.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jones J.W. (1956) The Law and the Legal Theory of the Greeks, Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kant I. (1922) Critique of Pure Reason, London: Macmillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kelsen H. (1938) What is Justice? Law and Politics in the Mirror of Science, Berkeley: University of California Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Klemperer V. (2006) The Language of the Third Reich, London: Continuum.

    Google Scholar 

  • Koch H. (1932) Pronoia und Paideusis, Berlin-Lepzig: de Gruyter.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kolakowski L. (1977) Der revolutionäre Geist, Stuttgart: Kohlhammer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Küng H. (1995) Christianity, London: SCM Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lenin V.I. (1974) State and Revolution, in Collected Works, vol. 25, Moscow: Progress Publishers.

    Google Scholar 

  • Léonard É.G. (1965) A History of Protestantism, London: Nelson.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lévi-Strauss (1949) Les structures élémentaires de la parenté, Paris: P.U.F.

    Google Scholar 

  • Loewith K. (1949) Meaning in History, Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Luther M. (1915) The Papacy at Rome, in Works, vol. 1, Philadelphia: Holman.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mably G. de (1767) Entretiens de Phocion, sur le rapport de la morale avec la politique, Amsterdam (without Publisher’s name).

    Google Scholar 

  • Macchioro V. (1922) Orfismo e paolinismo, Montevarchi: Casa Editrice Cultura Moderna.

    Google Scholar 

  • Marx K. (1976) Capital, London: Penguin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Marx K. (1984a) “On the Jewish Question”, in Marx (1984c).

    Google Scholar 

  • Marx K. (1984b) “Economic and Philosophical Manuscripts”, in Marx (1984c).

    Google Scholar 

  • Marx K, Engels F. (1984) “The Communist Manifesto”, in Marx (1984c).

    Google Scholar 

  • Mises L. (1969a) Omnipotent Government, Westport: Arlington House.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mises L. (1969b) Bureaucracy, New Rochelle: Arlington House.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mises L. (1977) A Critique of Interventionism, New Rochelle: Arlington House.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mises L. (1978) In Namen des Staates, Stuttgart, Bonn Aktuell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mises L. (1981) Socialism, Indianapolis: Liberty Fund.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mises L. (1998) Interventionism, Irvington-on-Hudson: Foundation for Economic Education.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mumford L. (1944) The Condition of Man, New York: Harcourt, Brace & Co.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Musca G. (ed., 1973) La Magna Charta e le origini del parlamentarismo inglese, Messina-Firenze: D’anna.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nietzsche F. (1986) Human, All Too Human, Cambridge: Cambridge U.P.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ollier F. (1933) Le mirage spartiate, vol. 1, Paris: de Boccard.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ortega y Gasset J. (1933) “En torno a Galileo”, in Ortega y Gasset (1946–1983), vol. 5.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ortega y Gasset J. (1960) “Origen y epílogo de la filosofía”, Ortega (1946–1983), vol. 9.

    Google Scholar 

  • Orwell G. (1949) Nineteen Eighty-Four, London: Penguin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pellicani L. (1975) I rivoluzionari di professione, Firenze: Vallecchi.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pellicani L. (1979) Il mercato e i socialismi, Milano: Sugarco.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pellicani L. (1995) La società dei giusti. Parabola storica dello gnosticismo rivoluzionario, Milano: Etaslibri.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pellicani L. (1996), “Millenarismo”, in Enciclopedia delle scienze sociali, Roma: Istituto della Enciclopedia Italiana.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pellicani L. (2000, I nemici della modernità, Roma: Ideazione.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pellicani L. (2005) Le sorgenti della vita, Lungro di Cosenza: Marco Editore.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pellicani L. (2007) Le radici pagane dell’Europa, Soveria Mannelli: Rubbettino.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pellicani L. (2009) Lenin e Hitler, Soveria Mannelli: Rubbettino.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pipes R. (1999) Property and Freedom, New York: Knopf.

    Google Scholar 

  • Popper K.R. (1966) The Open Society and Its Enemies, London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Popper K.R. (1991) Conjectures and Refutations, London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rawson E. (1969) The Spartan Tradition in European Thought, Oxford: Oxford U.P.

    Google Scholar 

  • Reale G. (1997) Storia della filosofia antica, Milano: Vita e Pensiero.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ricciotti G. (1955) Storia d’Israele, Torino: SEI.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ricossa S. (2006) La fine dell’economia, Soveria Mannelli: Rubbettino.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rizzi B. (1977, Il collettivismo burocratico, Milano: Sugarco.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rousseau J.-J. (1997a) “Discourse on the Science and Arts”, in Rousseau (1970c).

    Google Scholar 

  • Rousseau J.-J. (1997b) “Discourse on the Origin and Foundations of Inequality Among Men”, in Rousseau (1997c).

    Google Scholar 

  • Rousseau J.-J. (1970) The Discourses and Other Early Political Writings, Cambridge: Cambridge U.P.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rousseau J.-J. (1997c) “Discourse on Political Economy”, in Rousseau (1997f)

    Google Scholar 

  • Russell B. (1947) Philosophy and Politics, Cambridge: National Book League.

    Google Scholar 

  • Russell B. (1962) The Practice and Theory of Bolshevism, London: Allen & Unwin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ruyer R. (1950, L’utopie et les utopies, Paris: P.U.F.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schmoller G. (1897) The Mercantile System and Its Historical Significance, London: Macmillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schutz A. (1962a) “On Multiple Realities”, in Schutz (1962c), vol. 1.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schutz A. (1962b) “Don Quixote and the Problem of Reality”, in Schutz (1962b), vol. 2.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schwartz E. (1966) Figuras del mundo antiguo, Madrid: Revista de Occidente.

    Google Scholar 

  • Selznick P. (1952) The Organizational Weapon, New York: McGraw-Hill.

    Google Scholar 

  • Settembrini D. (1974) Socialismo e rivoluzione dopo Marx, Napoli: Guida.

    Google Scholar 

  • Settembrini D. (2001) Fascismo, controrivoluzione imperfetta, Roma: SEAM.

    Google Scholar 

  • Simmel G. (1908) Soziologie, Leipzig: Duncker & Humblot.

    Google Scholar 

  • Simmel G. (1959) Sociology of Religion, New York: Philosophical Library.

    Google Scholar 

  • Spencer H. (1881) The Man versus the State, London: Williams & Norgate.

    Google Scholar 

  • Spengler O. (1924), Preussentum und Sozialismus, München: Beck’sche Verlagsbushhandlung.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stark R. (2005) The Victory of Reason, New York: Random House.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sternberger D. (1978) Drei Wurzeln der Politik, Frankfurt am Main: Insel Verlag.

    Google Scholar 

  • Talmon (1952) The Origins of Totalitarian Democracy, London: Secker & Warburg.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tocqueville A. de (1983) The Old Regime and the French Revolution, New York: Anchor Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Topitsch E., (1973) Gottwerdung und Revolution, Pullack-München: Verlag Dokumentation.

    Google Scholar 

  • Troeltsch E. (1960) The Social Teaching of the Christian Churches, Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Troeltsch E. (1963) Augustin, die christliche Antike und das Mittelalter, Aalen: Scientia Verlag.

    Google Scholar 

  • Trotskij L. (1972) The Revolution Betrayed, New York: Pathfinder Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Voegelin E. (2000) The New Science of Politics, in Collected Works, vol. 5, Columbia-London: University of Missouri Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Weber M. (1946) Essays in Sociology, New York: Oxford U.P.

    Google Scholar 

  • Weber M. (1952) Ancient Judaism, New York: Free Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Weber M. (1978) Economy and Society, New York: Bedminster Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Walzer M. (1965) The Revolution of Saints, New York: Atheneum.

    Google Scholar 

  • Woodhouse A.S.P. (1951) Puritanism and Liberty, London: Dent.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zeller E. (1888) Plato and the Older Academy, London: Longmans & Green.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Lorenzo Infantino .

Appendix: The “prophet of doom”

Appendix: The “prophet of doom”

The monopolistic paradigm, on which every kind of closed society has based itself, prevents the control of the rulers by the ruled. The rulers live in a condition of permanent self-referentiality. Any change or turnover of people is an extraordinary event. They are not the consequence of an institutionalised mechanism for the scrutiny of the government activity and they “are not based upon a rational attempt to improve social conditions”.Footnote 249

In reference to ancient Judaism, Weber pointed out the following: “Elijah received his commands from Yahwe in solitude and announced them personally as the emissary of his God […]. His incomparable prestige rested on this and upon his hitherto unheard of lack of discretion in standing up to the political power holders. Historically he is important as the first fairly ascertainable prophet of doom. In this is the forerunner of a series of grand figures which for our present day literary sources begin with Amos and end with Ezekiel”.Footnote 250 As Weber also observed, “the sociological reason for the prophets’ solitude was, in first place, the fact that the prophecy of doom could not be taught professionally like that of good fortune. Further, it could not be exploited for profit”Footnote 251; and this is easily understandable: first of all, because “no one would buy an evil omen”Footnote 252; and also for the reason that the “the question of Temple construction, succession to the throne, the private sins of the monarchs, worship, and the most varied political and personal decisions became topics of their [of the prophets of doom] oracles and their mostly undesired and extremely sharp criticism”Footnote 253; and spoke out against the “social injustice of the king” and the “whole bureaucratic apparatus”, seen as an “Egyptian abomination”.Footnote 254

Ortega aptly pointed out that God forced Amos to prophesy against his people, that is, against the course into which public life had been channelled.Footnote 255 Consequently, one can say that the “prophet of doom” stood up against the phenomena which we can concisely encapsulate in the term of “Machiavellianism”.

It follows that prophetism was to some extent the instrument through which the decisions of rulers were subjected to scrutiny. In other words, an attempt was made to prevent the actions of public power from being carried out in total self-referentiality. The prophet was “the herald, the speaker of Yahweh. […. In] that society established on a theocratic foundation, all of a sudden a special envoy of Yahweh appeared; all therefore felt, or at least should have felt, reverence towards him […]. The prophet, in the performance of his mission, came before the king and before the priests: he shouted out a rebuke in a sanctuary or in the Temple in Jerusalem, and then moved on to enunciate a threat on the threshold of the royal palace; he railed against political alliances, and turning elsewhere, he uttered his disapproval of syncretistic cults; he made public the scandals of the court and he cursed entire dynasties, as he exposed to the people’s contempt the greedy ministers of the sanctuary and he scolded the astonished crowd who listened to him for the corruption of their ways. And all recognised him this right, since he came from Yahweh”.Footnote 256

The threats the prophet uttered on behalf of God were terrifying. Through Amos, Yahweh says: “it shall come to pass that day, saith the Lord God, that I will cause the sun to go down at noon, and I will darken the earth in the clear day: and I will turn your feasts into mourning, and all your songs into lamentation; and I will bring up sackcloth upon all loins, and baldness upon every head; and I will make it as the mourning of an only son, and the end thereof as a bitter day”.Footnote 257 It is no surprise therefore that the “prophet of doom”, despite being recognised as the envoy of God, could be unwelcome to rulers: he challenged them and obviously had to be ready to suffer the consequences of his preaching. This is why “being killed was the normal and ordinary prospect for a prophet”: if this did not happen it was “an exception”.Footnote 258

For the purposes considered here, the most relevant point is in any case another one. It refers to the identification of the conditions which made the “prophet of doom” possible. As Weber pointed out, Yahwe was, “since Moses, […] the god of the covenant of the Israelite confederacy, and, corresponding to the purpose of the confederacy, he was primarily its war god. He played this role in a very special manner. He became war god by virtue of a treaty of confederation. This contract had to be concluded, not only among confederates, but also with him, for he was no god residing in the midst of the people, a familiar god, but rather a god hitherto strange. He continued to be a god from afar. This was the decisive element in the relationship”.Footnote 259 In other words: “Yahwe was an elective god. The confederate people had chosen him through berith with him, just as, later, it established its king by berith. Yahwe, in turn, had chosen this people before all others by free resolve”.Footnote 260

Weber further specified: “In this manner Yahwe became not only the war god of the confederacy but also the contractual partner of its law established by berith above all of the socio-legal orders. Since the confederacy was at first a stateless association of tribes, new statutes, whether cultic or legal in nature, could in principle originate only by way of agreement (berith) based on oracle like the original covenant”.Footnote 261 And, “as guardian of confederate orders, Yahwe protects the customs and mores. That which is ‘unheard of’ in Israel is an abomination to him. In agreement with his original nature, however, and unlike Varuna and similar deities, he was not the guardian of the confederate law and mores in the sense of sanctifying an already existing immutable order of law or a ‘righteousness’ measurable in terms of fixed norms. On the contrary, this positive law for Israel was created through berith with him. It had not always been in existence and it was possible that by new revelation and a new berith with god it could be changed again”.Footnote 262

There was therefore no one single “revelation” of the will of Yahweh. And there was no definitive monopoly over it. Public power and “charismatic bureaucracy” could at any time undergo “disintermediation” through the action of another envoy of God. The work of delegitimation performed by the “prophet of doom” is precisely an action of “disintermediation” made possible by the fact that Yahweh sent continual “messages” and kept them outside the monopoly of those who held public power. And this, even inside a theocracy, allowed an irregular and uncertain scrutiny over government activity. As if to say that possible control is only performed through the delegitimation of rulers. Accordingly, it was an extraordinary occurrence, which materialised through the initiative of men who in turn were devoid of any certain legitimation and who, for this reason, were often destined to fail. A genuine action of scrutiny requires a context where the formula of authority moves in an upward direction, hinging on the consent of the ruled and is not a “gift” from the divinity; and where the limitation of power is institutionalised.Footnote 263

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2020 The Author(s)

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Infantino, L. (2020). The Reshaping of Man and the Birth of Totalitarian Power. In: Infrasocial Power. Palgrave Macmillan, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-45081-6_2

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-45081-6_2

  • Published:

  • Publisher Name: Palgrave Macmillan, Cham

  • Print ISBN: 978-3-030-45080-9

  • Online ISBN: 978-3-030-45081-6

  • eBook Packages: Social SciencesSocial Sciences (R0)

Publish with us

Policies and ethics