Skip to main content

From Atheism of the Concept Towards Atheism Without the Concept

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Atheism Revisited
  • 248 Accesses

Abstract

The author explores a typically philosophical atheism, which he dubs the “atheism of the concept”, which for him gives rise to the “cult of the concept”. He asks if the “atheism of the concept” might not be a vestige of theistic thinking, which we ought to overcome. He also asks if an “atheism beyond the concept” might be possible. He does not present “atheism of the concept” as opposite to “atheism without the concept”, in as far as “the concept” is not the opposite of “life”. “Atheism without the concept” is rather an atheistic practice and concerns “lifestyle” rather than the content of convictions. In an atheistic world, it is not the reality of time that creates the reality of events, but the events themselves allow the course of time to unfold.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 119.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 159.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 159.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    For this reason, Žižek writes: “In our officially atheistic, hedonistic, post-modern secular culture, where no one is prepared to publicly admit to his faith, the fundamental structure of faith is ubiquitous – we all believe in secret. Atheism is not a zero-level of comprehension for everyone, because it only means God’s absence (belief) – perhaps there is nothing more difficult than to maintain a position, to be a true materialist. Because the structure of faith is in the form of a fetishistic Spaltung und Verleugnung, [fission and negation] (‘I know that there is no great Other, but ... I secretly believe in Him’)”. Slavoj Žižek, On Belief, London: Routledge, 2001, p. 10.

  2. 2.

    Daniel Barber in his intriguing book on Deleuze’s “atheism” offers a slightly different interpretation, one that is more kind to Deleuze. For Barber, “the production of the gods” is the production of values, which leads to the devaluation of the action by which all value is produced. God, who is an idol, recreates itself in a captivated imagination, which from then on becomes dead. This is the true meaning—according to Barber—of Nietzsche’s famous statement: “Do not believe those who talk about other worlds”. Deleuze’s discourse is a discourse on the very possibility of novelty, and therefore creativity. This discourse should not be treated and interpreted as one more story about secularization, rationalization, or modernization of the world. Deleuze’s philosophy is political, but not because he thinks of “politics”, Deleuze’s philosophy is political because he categorically insists on fidelity to immanence, that is, maintaining a close bond between immanence, imagination, and the world. Imagination belongs to the world, but the world is the imagination. Immanence for Deleuze is a well-thought-out anti-Christian theology, and at the same time cannot be reduced to secular and post-secular categories. According to Barber, Deleuze’s philosophy is an operation of language practices that are inextricably linked to religious practices. This thought is already present at Spinoza and Nietzsche. As a result, Deleuze’s thought becomes the mere articulation of the “space of immanence”, and also, it is the thought that immanence is a constant problem for thinking. It requires us to be able to imagine change without referring to the idea of “transcendence”, demanding “differentiated and differentiated immanence”, “internally dispersed”. This immanence can fold and change itself, without having to refer to anything beyond. For Barber, the main question is: what does it mean to speak of immanence, which is the ability to self-differentiate? Barber replies: This implies that immanence is “without object” and “without ultimate goal”, “without a designated destination” (Daniel Colucciello Barber, Deleuze and the naming of God. Post-Secularism and the Future of Immanence, Edinburgh University Press 2014). By agreeing with the premises on which this interpretation is based, there is no transition from “the concept of atheism” to practice, especially if the practice of language (naming) and religious practice (ceremonies) are central.

References

  • Adorno, Theodor W., and Max Horkheimer. 2016. Dialectic of Enlightenment. Trans. Edmund Jephcott. London: Verso Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Agamben, Giorgio. 1993. The Coming Community. Trans. Michael Hardt. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2005. The Time that Remains: A Commentary on the Letter to the Romans. Trans. Patricia Dailey. Stanford: Stanford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2007. Profanations. Trans. Jeff Fort. New York: Zone Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Althusser, Louis. 1971. Ideology and Ideological State Apparatuses. In Lenin and Philosophy and Other Essays, 127–189. Trans. Ben Brewster. New York: Monthly Review Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Badiou, Alain. 2006. Being and Event. Trans. Oliver Feltham. London: Continuum.

    Google Scholar 

  • Baggini, Julian. 2003. Atheism: A Very Short Introduction. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Barthes, Roland. 1972. Mythologies. Trans. Annette Lavers. New York: Farrar, Straus & Giroux.

    Google Scholar 

  • Benjamin, Walter. 2004. Capitalism as Religion. In Selected Writings Volume I, 1913–1926, ed. Marcus Bullock and Michael W. Jennings, 288–291. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bergson, Henri. 1935/1977. The Two Sources of Morality and Religion. Trans. R. Ashley Audra, Cloudesley Brereton and W. Horsfall Carter. Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bourdieu, Pierre. 1977. Outline of a Theory of Practice. Trans. Richard Nice. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Butler, Judith. 2008. Excitable Speech: A Politics of the Performative. New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Certeau, Michel de. 1984. The Practice of Everyday Life. Trans. Steven Rendall. Berkeley: University of California Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Colucciello Barber, Daniel. 2014. Deleuze and the Naming of God. Post-Secularism and the Future of Immanence. Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Defoe, Daniel. 2009/1719. Robinson Crusoe. Edited with an Introduction by Thomas Keymer and Notes by James Kelly. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Deleuze, Gilles. 1989. Cinema 2: The Time-Image. Trans. Hugh Tomlinson and Robert Galeta. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Deleuze, Gilles, and Félix Guattari. 2015. What Is Philosophy? Trans. Hugh Tomlinson and Graham Burchill. London: Verso.

    Google Scholar 

  • Derrida, Jacques. 1994. Specters of Marx: The State of the Debt, the Work of Mourning. Trans. Peggy Kamuf. New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2003. Knowledge and Belief. Two Sources of “Religion” Within Reason Itself. In Religion, ed. Gianni Vattimo and Jacques Derrida, 1–78. Trans. David Webb et al. Cambridge, UK: Polity Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Descartes, René. 2009. Meditations on the First Philosophy. In Descartes: Selected Philosophical Writings. Trans. John Cottingham, Robert Stoothoff and Dugald Murdoch. 1–126. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Esposito, Roberto. 2012. Politics of Life and Philosophy of the Impersonal. Trans. Zakiya Hanafi. Cambridge, UK: Polity Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Feuerbach, Ludwig. 1972. The Essence of Christianity. Trans. Zawar Hanfi. New York: Anchor.

    Google Scholar 

  • Freud, Sigmund. 1967. Moses and Monotheism. Trans. Katherine Jones. New York: Vintage.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1989. The Future of an Illusion. Trans. and Ed. James Strachey. New York: W. W. Norton & Co.

    Google Scholar 

  • Girard, René. 2001. I Saw Satan Fall Like Lightning. Trans. James G. Williams. New York: Orbis Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Habermas, Jürgen. 2004. Dialectical Idealism in Transition to Materialism: Schelling’s Idea of a Contraction of God and Its Consequences for the Philosophy of History. Trans. Nick Midgley and Judith Norman. In The New Schelling, ed. Judith Norman and Alistair Welchman, 43–89. London: Continuum.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hägglund, Martin. 2008. Radical Atheism: Derrida and the Time of Life. Stanford: Stanford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Heidegger, Martin. 1977. The Word of Nietzsche: ‘God Is Dead.’ In The Question Concerning Technology and Other Essays, 53–112. Trans. William Lovitt. New York: Harper and Row.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2008. Identity and Difference. Trans. Joan Stambaugh. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hobbes, Thomas. 1968. Leviathan or The Matter, Forme, & Power of a Common-Wealth Ecclesiasticall and Civil. Ed. Crawford Brough Macpherson. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • King, Elizabeth. 2003. Clockwork Prayer. A 16th-Century Mechanical Monk. In Breaking the Disciplines: Reconceptions in Knowledge, Art, and Culture, ed. Martin L. Davies and Marsha Meskimmon, 84–129. London/New York: IB Tauris.

    Google Scholar 

  • Latour, Bruno. 2000. Pandora’s Hope. Essays on the Reality of Science Studies. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2002. We Have Never Been Modern. Trans. Cathy Porter. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2004. Why Has Critique Run Out of Steam? From Matters of Fact to Matters of Concern. Critical Inquiry 30 (2, Winter): 225–248.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2011. On the Modern Cult of the Factish Gods. Trans. Cathy Porter and Heather MacLean. Durham: Duke University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Marion, Jean-Luc. 2001. The Idol and Distance: Five Studies. Trans. Thomas A. Carlson. New York: Fordham University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2012. God Without Being Hors-Texte. Trans. Thomas A. Carlson. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Marx, Karl. 1976. Critique of Hegel’s Contributions to the Philosophy of Law. In Collected Works, ed. Karl Marx and Friedrich Engels, 3–130. New York: Int. Pubs.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mauss, Marcel. 1973. Techniques of the Body. Trans. Ben Brewster. Economy and Society 2 (1): 70–88.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Meillassoux, Quentin. 2010. After Finitude: An Essay on the Necessity of Contingency. Trans. Ray Brassier. London: Continuum.

    Google Scholar 

  • Montaigne, Michel de. 2003. The Complete Essays. Trans. M. A. Screech. London: Penguin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nietzsche, Friedrich. 1974. The Gay Science, with a Prelude in Rhymes and an Appendix of Songs. Trans. Walter Kaufmann. New York: Random House.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1977. Twilight of the Idols and the Anti-Christ. Trans. R. J. Hollingdale. London: Penguin.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2013. The Wanderer and His Shadow. Trans. Gary Handwerk. Stanford: Stanford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rancière, Jacques. 2014. Hatred of Democracy. Trans. Steve Corcoran. London: Verso.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ricoeur, Paul. 1974. Religion, Atheism, Faith. Trans. Charles Freilich. In The Conflict of Interpretations, 436–463. Evanston: Northwestern University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ruse, Michael. 2015. Atheism: What Everyone Needs to Know. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Spinoza, Benedictus De. 1994. Ethics Demonstrated in Geometrical Order. In A Spinoza Reader: The Ethics and Other Works, ed. and Trans. Edwin Curley, 85–265. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Vattimo Gianni. 2003. Tracking the Trace. In Religion, ed. Gianni Vattimo and Jacques Derrida, 79–94. Trans. David Webb et al. Cambridge, UK: Polity Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wall, Thomas C. 1999. Radical Passivity: Lévinas, Blanchot, and Agamben. New York: Suny Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Watkin, Christopher. 2011. Difficult Atheism. Post-Theological Thinking in Alain Badiou, Jean-Luc Nancy and Quentin Meillassoux. Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Wittgenstein, Ludwig. 1922. Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus. Trans. Charles Kay Ogden. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul.

    Google Scholar 

  • Žižek, Slavoj. 2001. On Belief. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2020 The Author(s)

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Wróbel, S. (2020). From Atheism of the Concept Towards Atheism Without the Concept. In: Wróbel, S., Skonieczny, K. (eds) Atheism Revisited. Palgrave Macmillan, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-34368-2_13

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics