Skip to main content

An Analytical Foundation of Rule Scepticism

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Legal Interpretation and Scientific Knowledge

Abstract

The essay distinguishes a few different senses of ‘interpretation’ and a few different kinds of ‘indeterminacy’ that are relevant for the law. In light of such distinctions, the author defends a ‘moderate’ approach to interpretive scepticism. Under this approach, interpretation has (conceptual, not factual) limits, in the sense that not every sentence claiming to be interpretive can be reasonably subsumed under the concept of interpretation. Interpreting consists not in ascribing just any meaning but in ascribing one meaning in the range of meanings admitted by (a) linguistic usage, (b) accepted interpretive methods and (c) juristic (‘dogmatic’) constructions. A limited concept of interpretation is essential in view of distinguishing between ordinary ascription of meaning to legal texts—i.e. adjudicative interpretation properly understood—and genuine ‘interstitial legislation’ by jurists and judges.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

eBook
USD 16.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 16.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 139.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. 1.

    Cf. Guastini (2011, p. 15 ff).

  2. 2.

    This is a classical realistic stand, as pointed out by Leiter (2007, p. 61): ‘the Realists all embraced the following descriptive thesis: in deciding cases, judges react primarily to the underlying facts of the case, rather than to the applicable legal rules and reasons (the latter figuring primarily as ways of providing post-hoc rationales for decisions reached on other grounds)’. Cf. also Ross (1958, p. 152). The same view, however, is shared also by the ‘hermeneutical’ trend in legal interpretation. See, e.g., in Italian literature, Zaccaria (1995, 1996), Viola and Zaccaria (1999), Zagrebelsky (1992, 2008) and Marcenò and Zagrebelsky (2018).

  3. 3.

    No clear-cut distinction exists between what a rule-formulation means and what its meaning entails. Alchourrón and Bulygin (1971, p. 67 f): ‘The description of the law […] involves the operation which jurists refer to under the vague term ‘interpretation’ and which fundamentally consists in the determination of the consequences that can be derived from […] norms.’

  4. 4.

    A similar distinction is drawn by Aarnio (1983, p. 165). Cf. also Twining and Miers (1982, ch. 4), distinguishing between interpretation and application.

  5. 5.

    See Troper (1994, ch. XVIII).

  6. 6.

    Guastini (2000, p. 119 ff).

  7. 7.

    I borrow the phrase from Prieto Sanchís (1997, p. 33).

  8. 8.

    This is the opinion of the Italian constitutional court: Corte costituzionale, decision 1146/1988. The topic is by and large discussed in Guastini (2007, p. 325 ff).

  9. 9.

    Eco (2003, ch. X) and Marmor (2001, p. 76).

  10. 10.

    E.g., ‘The President of the Republic shall sign the ordinances and decrees deliberated by the Council of Ministers’ means that the President is under the obligation to sign; ‘The republic recognizes and guarantees the inviolable rights of man’ means that the constitutional provisions ascribing the mentioned rights are not liable to constitutional amendment; etc.

  11. 11.

    The distinction is inspired by Kelsen (1934, p. 80 f) and Kelsen (1960, p. 353 ff).

  12. 12.

    Kelsen (1960, p. 355): ‘Jurisprudential [i.e., cognitive] interpretation can do no more than exhibit all possible meanings of a legal norm. Jurisprudence as cognition of law cannot decide between the possibilities exhibited by it, but must leave the decision to the legal organ who […] is authorized to apply the law.’

  13. 13.

    Kelsen (1960, p. 354): ‘In the application of law by a legal organ, the cognitive interpretation of the law to be applied is combined with an act of will by which the law-applying organ chooses between the possibilities shown by cognitive interpretation.’

  14. 14.

    Kelsen (1960, p. 354): ‘By way of authentic interpretation (that is, interpretation of a norm by the law-applying organ), not only one of the possibilities may be realized that have been shown by the cognitive interpretation […]; but also a norm may be created which lies entirely outside the frame of the norm to be applied.’ Cf. also Kelsen (1950, p. xv).

  15. 15.

    Kelsen (1934, p. 80): ‘If “interpretation” is understood as discovering the meaning of the norm to be applied, its result can only be the discovery of the frame that the norm to be interpreted represents and, within this frame, the cognition of various possibilities for application. Interpreting a statute, then, leads not necessarily to a single decision as the only correct decision, but possibly to a number of decisions, all of them of equal standing.’

  16. 16.

    Kelsen (1960, p. 355): ‘The interpretation of law by the science of law (jurisprudence) must be sharply distinguished […] from the interpretation by legal organs. Jurisprudential interpretation is purely cognitive ascertainment of the meaning of legal norms.’

  17. 17.

    Kelsen (1960, p. 355 f): ‘An attorney who, in the interest of his client, propounds to the judge only one of several possible interpretations […], or a writer who in his commentary extols a specific interpretation among many possible ones as the only “correct” one, does not render a function of legal science, but of legal politics.’ See also Kelsen (1934, p. 82).

  18. 18.

    Kelsen (1960, p. 354): ‘The interpretation by the law-applying organ is always authentic. It creates law […].’ See also Troper (2001a, b, c, p. 85 ff).

  19. 19.

    See Corte costituzionale, decision 168/1963.

  20. 20.

    Guastini (2011, p. 155 ff).

  21. 21.

    European Court of Justice, July 15, 1964, Case 6/64, Costa. Cf. also European Court of Justice, March 9, 1978, Case 106/77, Simmenthal.

  22. 22.

    See article 16 of the Déclaration des droits de l’homme et du citoyen: ‘Toute société dans laquelle la garantie des droits n’est pas assurée, ni la séparation des pouvoirs déterminée, n’a point de constitution.’

  23. 23.

    See, e.g., Zagrebelsky (1992).

  24. 24.

    Guastini (2011, p. 39 ff).

  25. 25.

    The kind of indeterminacy I have in mind (interpretive indeterminacy) is not to be confused with indeterminacy depending on the vagueness of the criteria of validity (so-called rule of recognition in Hart’s language). One thing is wondering whether a given text expresses a certain rule R or not; a different thing is wondering whether R (provided that it is actually expressed) is valid or not (e.g., whether it is compatible with the constitution or not).

  26. 26.

    One should take into account this remark when discussing the radical form of interpretive scepticism, such as the one defended by Troper (2001a, b, c, p. 69 ff), according to which no legal meaning exists before and independently of the ‘authentic’ interpretation of law-applying organs.

  27. 27.

    Ross (1958, p. 123 ff).

  28. 28.

    Alchourrón (1996). See also Twining and Miers (1982, p. 216 f) on ‘implied exceptions’; Schauer (1991, p. 115 ff); Guastini (2012, pp. 182–192).

  29. 29.

    The question was answered in the affirmative by Corte costituzionale, decision 6/1996.

  30. 30.

    Distinguishing between vagueness and open texture is not necessary for my present purposes.

  31. 31.

    The most extended inquiries on this subject are: Luzzati (1990) and Endicott (2000). Both elaborate a great number of significant distinctions that, however, are immaterial in the present context.

  32. 32.

    Cf. Grice (1989, p. 177).

  33. 33.

    Guastini (1997a).

  34. 34.

    A fourth, minor, reason for distinguishing between normative sentences and rules is that two different rule-formulations can express one and the same rule: see Schauer (1991, p. 62 f).

  35. 35.

    See Twining and Miers (1982, p. 218 ff), on the ‘puzzled interpreter’ and the ‘conditions of doubt’ in interpretation.

  36. 36.

    ‘The set of interpretive operations that can be legitimately performed on [legal] sources (to generate rules and principles of law)’: Coleman and Leiter (1995, p. 213).

  37. 37.

    Tarello (1974, p. 329 ff).

  38. 38.

    I am aware that the phrase ‘legal dogmatics’ is not familiar to Anglo-American jurisprudence. However, it is commonly used in continental juristic parlance as to refer to the literary products of legal scholars (textbooks, commentaries, etc.). Cf. e.g. Aarnio (1977, p. 266 ff); Alexy (1978); Bulygin (1986, pp. 193–210); Aarnio (1987, ch. 3); Peczenik (2005, ch. 1).

  39. 39.

    See, e.g., Ross (1958, p. 145 ff).

  40. 40.

    Kelsen (1950, p. xiii). Cf. Llewellyn (1950, p. 228 ff); Ross (1958, p. 148 ff); Tarello (1980, p. 341 ff); Diciotti (1999, esp. ch. V); Chiassoni (2007, ch. II).

  41. 41.

    Cf. Coleman and Leiter (1995, p. 214).

  42. 42.

    Twining and Miers (1982, p. 338 f).

  43. 43.

    Scarpelli (1982, p. 179 ff).

  44. 44.

    Benjamin Hoadley, Bishop of Bangor, quoted by Gray (1948, p. 102).

  45. 45.

    See Gray (1948, pp. 124, 170); Tarello (1974, esp. 265 ff, 389 ff). Troper (2001b). Cf. also Guastini (1992, esp. ch. VIII); Mazzarese (1991, p. 39 ff); Guastini (1996).

  46. 46.

    Troper (2001a, b, c, p. 35 ff); Troper (2005).

  47. 47.

    Kelsen (1960, p. 354).

  48. 48.

    Admittedly, outside legal-theoretical literature, one could mention the so-called Kripkenstein’s semantic scepticism: Kripke (1982). But Kripke’s argument, as I understand it, simply shows that ‘sentences that ascribe meanings are […] non cognitive’ (Coleman and Leiter 1995, p. 220). In my view, as far as adjudicative interpretation in the legal domain is concerned, this is true, but does not entails the no-prior-meaning thesis. Asserting that a rule-formulation is ambiguous (in a broad sense) is quite different from asserting that it has no meaning at all. For some criticism of semantic scepticism, see Coleman and Leiter (1995, p. 221 ff). For criticism of the ‘particularistic understanding of meaning’, see Schauer (1991, p. 55 ff).

  49. 49.

    Literal or plain meaning, one could say following A. Marmor, is a matter of understanding, not of interpretation. See Marmor (2005, p. 9 f); Marmor (2001, p. 73 ff). Nonetheless, it is important to stress that when someone ascribes a legal text its literal meaning (discarding other possible meanings) he/she does accomplish an act of adjudicative interpretation. Literal meaning has no privileged status among the various possible meanings of a legal text. See Chiassoni (2008, esp. 149 ff).

  50. 50.

    Guastini (1997a, b, p. 279 ff).

References

  • Aarnio A (1977) On legal reasoning. Turun Yliopisto, Turku

    Google Scholar 

  • Aarnio A (1983) Philosophical perspectives in jurisprudence. Acta Philosophica Fennica, vol 36. Helsinki

    Google Scholar 

  • Aarnio A (1987) The rational as reasonable. Reidel, Dordrecht

    Google Scholar 

  • Alchourrón CE (1996) On law and logic. Ratio Juris 9:331–348

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Alchourrón CE, Bulygin E (1971) Normative systems. Springer, Wien

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Alexy R (1978) A theory of legal argumentation (1978) (trans: Adler R, MacCormick N). Clarendon Press, Oxford, 1989

    Google Scholar 

  • Bulygin E (1986) Legal dogmatics and the systematization of law. In: Eckhoff T, Friedman LM, Uusitalo J (eds) Vernunft und Erfahrung im Rechtsdenken der Gegenwart. Duncker & Humblot, Berlin. (Rechtstheorie, Beiheft 10)

    Google Scholar 

  • Chiassoni P (2007) Tecnica dell’interpretazione giuridica. Il Mulino, Bologna

    Google Scholar 

  • Chiassoni P (2008) On the wrong track: Andrei Marmor on legal positivism, interpretation, and easy cases. In: Comanducci P, Guastini R (eds) Analisi e diritto 2007. Ricerche di giurisprudenza analitica. Giappichelli, Torino

    Google Scholar 

  • Coleman JL, Leiter B (1995) Determinacy, objectivity, and authority. In: Marmor A (ed) Law and interpretation. Essays in legal philosophy. Clarendon Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Diciotti E (1999) Interpretazione della legge e discorso razionale. Giappichelli, Torino

    Google Scholar 

  • Eco U (2003) Dire quasi la stessa cosa. Esperienze di traduzione. Bompiani, Milano

    Google Scholar 

  • Endicott TAO (2000) Vagueness in law. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Gray JC (1948) The nature and sources of the law, 2nd edn. Macmillan, New York, from the author’s notes, by Gray

    Google Scholar 

  • Grice HP (1989) Studies in the way of words. Harvard University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Guastini R (1992) Dalle fonti alle norme, 2nd edn. Giappichelli, Torino

    Google Scholar 

  • Guastini R (1996) Fragments of a theory of legal sources. Ratio Juris IX:364–386

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Guastini R (1997a) Rules, validity, and statutory construction. In: Jori M, Pintore A (eds) Law and language. The Italian analytical school. Deborah Charles Publication, Liverpool

    Google Scholar 

  • Guastini R (1997b) Interpretive statements. In: Garzón Valdés E, Krawietz W, von Wright GH, Zimmerling R (eds) Normative systems in legal and moral theory. Festschrift for Carlos E. Alchourrón and Eugenio Bulygin. Duncker & Humblot, Berlin

    Google Scholar 

  • Guastini R (2000) La primauté du droit communautaire: une révision tacite de la Constitution italienne. Les Cahiers du Conseil Constitutionnel 9:119–125

    Google Scholar 

  • Guastini R (2007) Esercizi d’interpretazione dell’art. 2 cost. Ragion pratica (2):235–338

    Google Scholar 

  • Guastini R (2011) Interpretare e argomentare. Giuffré, Milano

    Google Scholar 

  • Guastini R (2012) Defeasibility, axiological gaps, and interpretation. In: Ferrer Beltrán J, Ratti GB (eds) The logic of legal requirements. Essays on defeasibility. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Kelsen H (1934) Introduction to the problems of legal theory (trans: Litschevski Paulson B, Paulson SL). Clarendon Press, Oxford, 1992

    Google Scholar 

  • Kelsen H (1950) The law of the United Nations. Stevens & Sons, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Kelsen H (1960) The pure theory of law (trans: Knight M). University of California Press, Berkeley-Los Angeles-London, 1967

    Google Scholar 

  • Kripke SA (1982) Wittgenstein on rules and private language. Blackwell, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Leiter B (2007) Legal realism and legal positivism reconsidered. In: Leiter B (ed) Naturalizing jurisprudence. Essays on American legal realism and naturalism in legal philosophy. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Llewellyn KN (1950) Remarks on the theory of appellate decisions and the rules or canons about how statutes are to be construed. In: viz., the fragment reprinted in Fisher III WW, Horwitz MJ, Reed TA (eds) American legal realism. Oxford University Press, New York, 1993

    Google Scholar 

  • Luzzati C (1990) La vaghezza delle norme. Un’analisi del linguaggio giuridico. Giuffré, Milano

    Google Scholar 

  • Marcenò V, Zagrebelsky G (2018) Giustizia costituzionale, I. Storia, principi, interpretazioni. Il Mulino, Bologna

    Google Scholar 

  • Marmor A (2001) Positive law and objective values. Clarendon, Oxford

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Marmor A (2005) Interpretation and legal theory, 2nd edn. Hart Publishing, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Mazzarese T (1991) ‘Norm Proposition’: epistemic and semantic queries. Rechtstheorie XXII:39

    Google Scholar 

  • Peczenik A (2005) Scientia juris. Legal doctrine as knowledge of law and as a source of law. In: Pattaro E (ed) A treatise of legal philosophy and general jurisprudence, vol 4. Springer, Dordrecht

    Google Scholar 

  • Prieto Sanchís L (1997) Constitucionalismo y positivismo. Fontamara, México

    Google Scholar 

  • Ross A (1958) On law and justice. Stevens & Sons, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Scarpelli U (1982) Il metodo giuridico. In: Scarpelli U (ed) L’etica senza verità. Il Mulino, Bologna

    Google Scholar 

  • Schauer F (1991) Playing by the rules. A philosophical examination of rule-based decision-making in law and in life. Clarendon, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Tarello G (1974) La semantica del neustico. Osservazioni sulla ‘parte descrittiva’ degli enunciati precettivi. In: Tarello G (ed) Diritto, enunciati, usi. Studi di teoria e metateoria del diritto. Il Mulino, Bologna

    Google Scholar 

  • Tarello G (1980) L’interpretazione della legge. Giuffré, Milano

    Google Scholar 

  • Troper M (1994) La signature des ordonnances: fonctions d’une controverse. In: Troper M (ed) Pour une théorie juridique de l’Ètat. Presses universitaires de France, Paris

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Troper M (2001a) La liberté d’interprétation du juge constitutionnel. In: Troper M (ed) La théorie du droit, le droit, l’État. Presses universitaires de France, Paris

    Google Scholar 

  • Troper M (2001b) Une théorie réaliste de l’interprétation. In: Troper M (ed) La théorie du droit, le droit, l’État. Presses universitaires de France, Paris

    Google Scholar 

  • Troper M (2001c) Les contraintes de l’argumentation juridique dans la production des normes. In: Pfersmann O, Timsit G (eds) Raisonnement juridique et interprétation. Publications de la Sorbonne, Paris

    Google Scholar 

  • Troper M (2005) L’interprétation constitutionnelle. In: Mélin-Soucramanien F (ed) L’interprétation constitutionnelle. Dalloz, Paris

    Google Scholar 

  • Twining W, Miers D (1982) How to do things with rules. A primer of interpretation, 2nd edn. Weidenfeld and Nicholson, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Viola F, Zaccaria G (1999) Diritto e interpretazione. Lineamenti di teoria ermeneutica del diritto. Laterza, Roma

    Google Scholar 

  • Zaccaria G (1995) L’arte dell’interpretazione. Saggi sull’ermeneutica giuridica contemporânea. Cedam, Padova

    Google Scholar 

  • Zaccaria G (1996) Questioni di interpretazione. Cedam, Padova

    Google Scholar 

  • Zagrebelsky G (1992) Il diritto mite. Legge, diritti, giustizia. Einaudi, Torino

    Google Scholar 

  • Zagrebelsky G (2008) La legge e la sua giustizia. Il Mulino, Bologna

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Riccardo Guastini .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2019 Springer Nature Switzerland AG

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Guastini, R. (2019). An Analytical Foundation of Rule Scepticism. In: Duarte, D., Moniz Lopes, P., Silva Sampaio, J. (eds) Legal Interpretation and Scientific Knowledge. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-18671-5_2

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-18671-5_2

  • Published:

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Cham

  • Print ISBN: 978-3-030-18670-8

  • Online ISBN: 978-3-030-18671-5

  • eBook Packages: Law and CriminologyLaw and Criminology (R0)

Publish with us

Policies and ethics