Skip to main content

Toward a Genuine Understanding

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Towards a Liberatory Epistemology

Part of the book series: Palgrave Innovations in Philosophy ((PIIP))

  • 195 Accesses

Abstract

Understanding involves the grasping of networks of ideas, which itself involves seeing connections and arriving at further conclusions and interrelations. To understand people, then, is to synthesize information in ways that allow a comprehensive and systematic vision of what is going on in someone else’s life. Instead of allowing for ignorance, understanding requires an open-mindedness that considers multiple ways of interpreting experiences and that defends views using reasons that others can accept. It also requires placing knowers in social situations, taking into account the relations of epistemic agents acting in the world. In the end, understanding involves learning to adopt different perspectives so that one can clearly see what it is like for others to live in the world around them.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

eBook
USD 16.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Hardcover Book
USD 84.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    It also begs the question about understanding one’s own social reality, but my emphasis here will be on understanding others.

  2. 2.

    For a summary of much of this recent attention see Grimm et al. (2017).

  3. 3.

    The precise nature of understanding is actually a matter of widespread discussion and debate. My own discussion is concerned specifically with the relationship of understanding to socially constructed ignorance, and as a result, I will not be able to do justice to all the variations of understanding. For more on the issue see Grimm et al. (2017).

  4. 4.

    Of course, philosophers worry about what understanding has to do with fact, whether, that is, understanding is factive. For a summary of views on the factivity of understanding see Baumberger et al. (2017, 7–11).

  5. 5.

    Also see Lynch (2016, 16).

  6. 6.

    Kvanvig (2003) is focused on understanding objects and that something is the case rather than understanding, say, people or social situations. This is something that will make a difference.

  7. 7.

    For a full discussion of the use of “grasping” in discussions of understanding see Baumberger et al. (2017, 12–17).

  8. 8.

    As Baumberger, Beisbart, and Brun note, “the most prominent accounts [of understanding] analyze grasping in terms of suitable abilities” (2017, 13).

  9. 9.

    For another overview on how grasping conditions should be explicated see Kelp (2015).

  10. 10.

    For more on the notion of understanding as a cognitive achievement see Pritchard (2010).

  11. 11.

    See especially, Elgin (2017, 83).

  12. 12.

    Such failure of understanding is something rarely discussed explicitly, although it is addressed in a backhanded way by race and feminist theorists. What they “grasp” that more direct discussions of understanding do not is that something quite significant happens when we fail to understand others: we oftentimes don’t see them—or when we do see them, we observe facts about them, but we don’t actually achieve understanding.

  13. 13.

    Of course, it is a sad fact that even in safe environments, women are often not safe.

  14. 14.

    Whether there is a common thread is to those things we understand is less than clear. One theorist who thinks we can find a common thread is Grimm, who speaks of us understanding “subject matters (Fred understands quantum mechanics), or particular states of affairs (Jada understands why the cup spilled), or institutions (the U.S. House of Representatives), or other people (Jada herself), and so on” (2017, 214). In the discussion that follows Grimm’s list, however, there is no specific mention of how to understand other people. In fact, most discussion of “objectual understanding” tends to focus on theories and systems, even though people are said to be included in this form of understanding. For more on the types of understanding and what they may have in common see Baumberger et al. (2017, 4–6).

  15. 15.

    Three distinct ways of conceiving of understanding boil down to: objectual, propositional, and interrogative. For a further discussion of these types see Baumberger et al. (2017, 5).

  16. 16.

    What constitutes a “worthwhile perspective” will be a topic of discussion shortly.

  17. 17.

    This contrasts with Forster’s assessment that scientists need to rely to a rigorous empirical process, absent Kant’s metaphysical theory. See Gray (2012, 401–404).

  18. 18.

    A rather large skeptical problem enters at this point: I must use some principles that I make my own to evaluate the worth of other perspectives. The deck is, then, stacked against the white supremacist because my principles will not support such a viewpoint. I will address this problem, but not just yet.

  19. 19.

    Whether understanding is factive is a matter of some debate. Elgin (2007, 2009) says no. Kvanvig (2003) says yes. For a summary of the debate see Baumberger et al. (2017, 7–11).

  20. 20.

    See Zagzebski (2001, 244).

  21. 21.

    See Elgin (2007, 34–35).

  22. 22.

    For a detailed discussion of open mindedness, see Baehr (2011).

  23. 23.

    This is different from being skeptical about understanding. In fact Carter and Pritchard (2017) argue that shifting to understanding from knowledge requires a resituating of the skepticism that Saul (2013) tries to generate.

  24. 24.

    See Wittgenstein (1958, 226).

  25. 25.

    For more on coming up with the realities for all humans see Nussbaum (1992).

  26. 26.

    Kant was not the only one with contemporary critics. Immerwahr (1992) argues that Hume weakened the scope of his claims about the lack of civilization in “four or five different kinds of men” to apply only to negroes in response to criticism by James Beattie. In other words, Hume weakened his view, but remained insistent that “negroes are naturally inferior to whites” (1992, 483).

  27. 27.

    Also see Mills (1997, 18).

  28. 28.

    See Fricker (2007, 148).

  29. 29.

    To make this argument as normatively convincing as possible, I need the concept of reasonableness, which is the subject of the following chapter. At this point, I offer a promissory note that such an argument will be forthcoming. For now, I simply assume that we have an obligation to attempt an understanding of the social reality of others even when we do not already understand.

  30. 30.

    To be clear, I do not believe Mills thinks whites are in principle unable to understand non-whites. He would prefer we overcome white ignorance rather than simply lament it. I take it that Mills’ position on white ignorance has more of an emphasis on historical fact than in principle possibility. Regardless of Mills position, however, what I wish to consider is how such an understanding could come about.

  31. 31.

    Even in racial theory, which is concerned greatly with oppression, there is little acknowledgement of gender issues.

  32. 32.

    See Ruetsche (2004, 88).

  33. 33.

    Riggs (2016) argues that open-mindedness and insightfulness provide a means to advancing understanding.

References

  • Baehr, Jason. 2011. “The Structure of Open-Mindedness.” Canadian Journal of Philosophy 41 (2): 191–214.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Baehr, Jason. 2018. “Intellectual Virtues and Truth, Understanding, and Wisdom.” In The Oxford Handbook of Virtue, edited by Nancy E. Snow, 800–816. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bailey, Alison. 2007. “Strategic Ignorance.” In Race and Epistemologies of Ignorance, edited by Shannon Sullivan and Nancy Tuana, 77–94. Albany: SUNY Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Baldwin, James. 1963. The Fire Next Time. New York: Dial Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Baumberger, Christoph, Claus Beisbart, and Georg Brun. 2017. “What Is Understanding? An Overview of Recent Debates in Epistemology and Philosophy of Science.” In Explaining Understanding: New Perpectives from Epistemology and Philosophy of Science, edited by Stephen R. Grimm, Christoph Baumberger, and Sabine Ammon, 1–31. New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Carter, J. Adam, and Duncan Pritchard. 2017. “Cognitive Bias, Skepticism and Understanding.” In Explaining Understanding: New Perpectives from Epistemology and Philosophy of Science, edited by Stephen R. Grimm, Christoph Baumberger, and Sabine Ammon, 272–292. New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dalmiya, Vrinda. 2001. “Knowing People.” In Knowledge, Truth, and Duty, edited by Matthias Steup, 221–234. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Debes, Remy. 2018. “Understanding Persons and the Problem of Power.” In Making Sense of the World: New Essays on the Philosophy of Understanding, edited by Stephen R. Grimm, 54–77. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dennett, Daniel. 1969. Content and Consciousness. London: Routledge and Kegan Paul.

    Google Scholar 

  • Elgin, Catherine. 1996. Considered Judgment. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Elgin, Catherine. 2007. “Understanding and the Facts.” Philosophical Studies 132 (1): 33–42.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Elgin, Catherine. 2009. “Is Understanding Factive?” In Epistemic Value, edited by Adrian Haddock, Alan Millar, and Duncan Pritchard, 322–330. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Elgin, Catherine. 2017. “Exemplification in Understanding.” In Explaining Understanding: New Perspectives from Epistemology and Philosophy of Science, edited by Stephen R. Grimm, Christoph Baumberger, and Sabine Ammon, 76–91. New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Forster, Georg. 2013. “Something More About the Human Races.” In Kant and the Concept of Race, translated and edited by Jon M. Mikklesen, 146–167. Albany: SUNY Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fricker, Miranda. 2007. Epistemic Injustice: Power and the Ethics of Knowing. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Gordon, Emma C. 2017. “Social Epistemology and the Acquisition of Understanding.” In Explaining Understanding: New Perpectives from Epistemology and Philosophy of Science, edited by Stephen R. Grimm, Christoph Baumberger, and Sabine Ammon, 293–317. New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Grasswick, Heidi. 2014. “Epistemic Normativity in Feminist Epistemology.” In The Ethics of Belief, edited by Jonathan Matheson and Rico Vitz, 216–243. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Gray, Sally Hatch. 2012. “Kant’s Race Theory, Forster’s Counter, and the Metaphysics of Color.” The Eighteenth Century 53 (4): 393–412.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Grimm, Stephen R. 2017. “Understanding and Transparency.” In Explaining Understanding: New Perpectives from Epistemology and Philosophy of Science, edited by Stephen R. Grimm, Christoph Baumberger, and Sabine Ammon, 213–229. New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Grimm, Stephen R. 2018. “Introduction.” In Making Sense of the World: New Essays on the Philosophy of Understanding, edited by Stephen R. Grimm, 1–13. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Grimm, Stephen R., Christoph Baumberger, and Sabine Ammon, eds. 2017. Explaining Understanding: New Perspectives from Epistemology and Philosophy of Science. New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Haack, Susan. 2001. “‘The Ethics of Belief’ Reconsidered.” In Knowledge, Truth, and Duty, edited by Matthias Steup, 21–33. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Hoagland, Sarah Lucia. 2007. “Denying Relationality.” In Race and Epistemologies of Ignorance, edited by Shannon Sullivan and Nancy Tuana, 95–118. Albany: SUNY Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Immerwahr, John. 1992. “Hume’s Revised Racism.” Journal of the History of Ideas 53 (3): 481–486.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kant, Immanuel. 1929. Critique of Pure Reason. Translated by Norman Kemp Smith. New York: St. Martin’s Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kant, Immanuel. 2013. “On the Use of Teleological Principles in Philosophy.” In Kant and the Concept of Race, translated and edited by Jon M. Mikklesen, 169–194. Albany: SUNY Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kelp, Christoph. 2015. “Understanding Phenomena.” Synthese 192 (12): 3799–3816.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kukla, Rebecca, and Laura Ruetsche. 2002. “Contingent Natures and Virtuous Knowers: Could Epistemology be ‘Gendered’?” Canadian Journal of Philosophy 32 (3): 389–418.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kvanvig, Jonathan. 2003. The Value of Knowledge and the Pursuit of Understanding. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Lynch, Michael Patrick. 2016. The Internet of Us. New York: Liveright Publishing.

    Google Scholar 

  • McCullough, David. 2017. The American Spirit. New York: Simon and Schuster.

    Google Scholar 

  • McDowell, John. 1994. Mind and World. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mills, Charles. 1997. The Racial Contract. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mills, Charles. 2007. “White Ignorance.” In Race and Epistemologies of Ignorance, edited by Shannon Sullivan and Nancy Tuana, 13–38. Albany: SUNY Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nussbuam, Martha. 1992. “Human Functioning and Social Justice: In Defense of Aristotelian Essentialism.” Political Theory 20: 202–246.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Outlaw, Lucius T. 2007. “Social Ordering and the Systematic Production of Ignorance.” In Race and Epistemologies of Ignorance, edited by Shannon Sullivan and Nancy Tuana, 197–212. Albany: SUNY Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pritchard, Duncan. 2010. “Knowledge and Understanding.” In The Nature and Value of Knowledge: Three Investigations, co-authored with Alan Millar and Adrian Haddock, 3–90. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Riggs, Wayne D. 2016. “Open-Mindedness, Insight, and Understanding.” In Intellectual Virtues and Education, edited by Jason Baehr, 18–37. New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rosenberg, Jay R. 1981. “On Understanding the Difficulty in Understanding Understanding.” In Meaning and Understanding, edited by Herman Parret, Jacques Bouveresse, 29–43. Berlin: Walter de Gruyter.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ruetsche, Laura. 2004. “Virtue and Contingent History: Possibilities for Feminist Epistemology.” Hypatia 19 (1): 73–101.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Saul, Jennifer. 2013. “Implicit Bias, Stereotype Threat, and Women in Philosophy.” In Women in Philosophy: What Needs to Change? edited by Fiona Jenkins and Katrina Hutchison, 39–60. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Talbert, Bonnie M. 2014. “Knowing Other People: A Second-Person Framework.” Ratio XXVIII: 190–206.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Townley, Cynthia. 2006. “Toward a Reevalaution of Ignorance.” Hypatia 21 (3): 37–55.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tuana, Nancy. 2004. “Coming to Understand: Orgasm and the Epistemology of Ignorance.” Hypatia 19 (1): 194–232.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wittgenstein, Ludwig. 1958. Philosophical Investigations. Translated by G.E.M. Anscombe. New York: Macmillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zagzebski, Linda. 2001. “Recovering Understanding.” In Knowledge, Truth, and Duty, edited by Matthias Steup, 235–251. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Deborah K. Heikes .

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2019 The Author(s)

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Heikes, D.K. (2019). Toward a Genuine Understanding. In: Towards a Liberatory Epistemology. Palgrave Innovations in Philosophy. Palgrave Macmillan, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-16485-0_3

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics