Skip to main content

…And Then What Happens?

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
The Feeling of Embodiment
  • 489 Accesses

Abstract

In Chapter 4 Carruthers offers a well-motivated hypothesis to explain the phenomenology of the feeling of embodiment that has received some independent and direct empirical support. But, is this an account of our consciousness of this feeling or just how the content is represented? In this chapter Carruthers considers what Dennett has called the “Hard Question” of consciousness. The account offered in Chapter 4 undoubtedly does a good job of explaining how the representations of our own embodiment are elicited. But, how are we to distinguish conscious and unconscious representations of our own embodiment? Carruthers considers two possible answers to this problem known as vehicle and functionalist accounts of consciousness. The explanation offered so far is classified as a vehicle theory.

This chapter makes use of substantially altered text previously published as: Carruthers, G. (2014).

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

eBook
USD 16.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 16.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 89.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    There are differences between ‘potentially explicit ’ and ‘tacit ’ representations. These differences become important when we consider the kinds of computations being performed within a cognitive system, but won’t play a role in this short statement of O’Brien and Opie’s hypothesis regarding consciousness (indeed O’Brien and Opie argue that a Vehicle Theory could only be true for connectionist systems and that the ‘potentially explicit ’ versus ‘tacit ’ distinction does not apply to such systems).

References

  • Baars, B. J. (1988). A cognitive theory of consciousness. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Block, N. (2007). Consciousness, accessibility, and the mesh between psychology and neuroscience. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 30(5–6), 481–499.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Carruthers, G. (2014). What makes us conscious of our own agency? And why the conscious versus unconscious representation distinction matters. Frontiers in Human Neuroscience, 8, 434. https://doi.org/10.3389/fnhum.2014.00434.

  • Chalmers, D. J. (2002). Consciousness and its place in nature. In D. J. Chalmers (Ed.), Philosophy of mind: Classic and contemporary readings. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Dennett, D. C. (1982). Styles of mental representation. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 83, 213–226.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dennett, D. C. (1991). Consciousness explained. New York: Penguin Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Egly, R., Driver, J., & Rafal, R. D. (1994). Shifting visual attention between objects and locations: Evidence from normal and parietal lesion subjects. Journal of Experimental Psychology: General, 123(2), 161.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gallup, G. G. (1970). Chimpanzees: Self recognition. Science, 167(3914), 86–87.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mack, A., & Rock, I. (1998). Inattentional blindness. Cambridge: The MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Marten, K., & Psarakos, S. (1994). Evidence of self-awareness in the bottlenose dolphin (Tursiops truncatus). In S. T. Parker, R. W. Mitchell, & M. L. Boccia (Eds.), Self-awareness in animals and humans: Developmental perspectives (pp. 361–379). New York, NY: Cambridge University Press. http://dx.doi.org/10.1017/CBO9780511565526.026.

  • Norman, L. J., Heywood, C. A., & Kentridge, R. W. (2013). Object-based attention without awareness. Psychological Science, 24(6), 836–843. https://doi.org/10.1177/0956797612461449.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • O’Brien, G., & Opie, J. (1999). A connectionist theory of phenomenal experience. Behavioural and Brain Sciences, 22, 127–196.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Povinelli, D. J. (2001). The self: Elevated in consciousness and extended in time. In K. Skene & C. Moore (Eds.), The development of the extended self in preschool children: Theory and research. Mahwah: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Povinelli, D. J., & Cant, J. G. H. (1995). Arboreal clambering and the evolution of self-conception. The Quarterly Review of Biology, 70(4), 393–421.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Prinz, J. J. (2000). A neurofunctional theory of visual consciousness. Consciousness and Cognition, 9(2), 243–259.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Prinz, J. J. (2012). The conscious brain: How attention engenders experience. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Prior, H., Schwarz, A., & Güntürkün, O. (2008). Mirror-induced behavior in the magpie (Pica pica): Evidence of self-recognition. PLoS Biology, 6(8), e202.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schwitzgebel, E. (2008). The unreliability of naive introspection. Philosophical Review, 117(2), 245–273.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Glenn Carruthers .

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2019 The Author(s)

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Carruthers, G. (2019). …And Then What Happens?. In: The Feeling of Embodiment. Palgrave Macmillan, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-14167-7_5

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics