Skip to main content
  • 359 Accesses

Abstract

Russo Krauss summarizes the role played by Wilhelm Wundt in 19th-century scientific psychology, as well as the state of research on this subject. The centennial of the foundation of the laboratory for experimental psychology in Leipzig revitalized the research on Wundt. Edwin Boring and Kurt Danziger retraced the so-called “positivist repudiation of Wundt” by his former pupils—Hermann Ebbinghaus, Oswald Külpe, Edward B. Titchener—that were influenced by the empiriocriticists Ernst Mach and Richard Avenarius. Russo Krauss aims at showing that, since Avenarius was and still is wrongly considered just a pale copy of Mach, his peculiar part in the “repudiation of Wundt” and in the debate on the foundation of psychology has not yet been investigated.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

eBook
USD 16.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 16.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 89.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    An account of Wundt’s—not quite impressive—scientific career up to the time of the publication of the Grundzüge can be found in Diamond (2001).

  2. 2.

    The definition of Wundt as the “psychological pope of the old world” is in a letter that William James wrote to Hugo Münsterberg in 1896 (Perry 1935, 145).

  3. 3.

    On the research conducted in Wundt’s laboratory see Robinson (2001).

  4. 4.

    Wundt tutored 186 students during his stay in Leipzig, but this number does not take into account all the scholars that visited the laboratory for purely scientific reasons (Tinker 1932).

  5. 5.

    The main fruits of this new wave of studies are the collective books by Bringmann and Tweney (1980), and Rieber (1980). This latter also have a new and expanded edition (Rieber and Robinson 2001).

  6. 6.

    On this subject see Blumenthal (1980). Specifically, Blumenthal claims that Boring wrongly attributed to Wundt the following ideas: (1) psychology coincides with physiological psychology; (2) psychology belongs to natural sciences; (3) “scientific” equals “experimental;” (4) introspection is the primary method of psychology; (5) consciousness can be reduced to a sum of elemental sensory contents; (6) mind and body are dualistically opposed; (7) there is no such thing as free agency in mental processes (Blumenthal 1980, 438–42). Similarly, Kurt Danziger stresses that Boring only focused on Wundt’s research on perception, while his main interest was actually the voluntary action (Danziger 2001).

  7. 7.

    For instance: “empiriocritical axiom,” “empiriocritical standpoint,” “empiriocritical finding,” “empiriocritical substitution” (cf. R. Avenarius 1888, 1890, [1891] 1905).

  8. 8.

    On Petzoldt and the Berlin Group see Hentschel (1990), Haller and Stadler (1993), Danneberg et al. (1994), Milkov and Peckhaus (2013).

  9. 9.

    For example, it is revealing how hastily Boring deals with Avenarius: “Titchener seized especially upon Mach and was ever after greatly influenced by him. Külpe , more given to philosophical intricacies, favored the difficult Avenarius. There is no real difference here, for the two men later agreed that they were both saying the same thing though in very different words;” “Richard Avenarius […] was as difficult, uninspiring, and involved a thinker as Mach was simple, dramatic, and clear. He worked without knowledge of Mach , though at the same time, but both men later agreed that their theories were essentially the same ” (Boring 1929, 389, 391).

  10. 10.

    To get a sense of the disproportion between the two: throughout Lenin’s book, Avenarius is mentioned 279 times and Mach 692 times. In 72 of these occurrences, the two are cited together. This means that Mach is cited over three times more than Avenarius (around 620 to 200, excluding the joint citations). Cf. Lenin (1927).

  11. 11.

    Avenarius is cited, next to Mach , by Kusch (1995, 1999). However, he only refers the little that Danziger’s paper said about him. Avenarius is mentioned only once, still alongside Mach , in Woodward and Ash (1982). There is no trace of Avenarius’ name in Mischel (1970), nor in Kardas (2013). Since the list of studies neglecting Avenarius could extend much further, let us concentrate on the few exceptions to this state of affairs. David K. Robinson (1987) reconstructs the relationship between Avenarius and Wundt from archival sources. Yet, being a historian, he does not focus on the philosophical discussion between the two. Katherine Arens (1989) has the merit of talking about Avenarius by making direct reference to his words. Nonetheless, she only focuses on Avenarius’ psychophysical theory, presented in the Kritik der reinen Erfahrung (Critique of Pure Experience), leaving aside his more philosophical works, such as Der menschliche Weltbegriff (The Human Concept of the World) and the Bemerkungen zum Begriff des Gegenstandes der Psychologie (Remarks on the Concept of Object of Psychology ). Not entirely convincing is also Arens’ choice to place Avenarius between Fechner and Wundt, not only because he was actually a follower of Wundt, at least at first, but also because his mature view on psychology can be considered more advanced than the Wundtian one. For this reason, as we hope to demonstrate with this book, it is difficult to agree with Arens’ statement that “the work of Wilhelm Wundt represented the major trend in academic psychology which aided to obscure the systemic analysis proposed by Avenarius” (Arens 1989, 120). Annette Mülberger (2012) deals with the conflict between Avenarius’ and Wundt’s concepts of psychology, but only indirectly, since she analyzes the work of Avenarius’ pupil Rudolf Willy (1899), who had no significant impact on the debate of the time. Lastly, the great reconstruction of Wundt’s intellectual career by Saulo de Freitas Araujo (2015) crosses Avenarius’ path when it comes to the analysis of Wundt’s articles Über naiven und kritischen Realismus (On Naïve and Critical Realism), directed against the immanentism of Wilhelm Schuppe and Robert von Schubert-Soldern, and the Empiriocriticism of Avenarius and Mach . However, given the purpose of Araujo’s book, Avenarius is only watched through Wundt’s eyes.

  12. 12.

    The only evidence of a correspondence between the two is a telegram Mach sent to Wundt for his 70th birthday (Mach to Wundt, August 16, 1902, Wundt Archive, NA Wundt/III/1601-1700/1601/135/355-356). On the other hand, we have almost fifty letters left from the correspondence between Wundt and Avenarius (see Wundt Archive and Avenarius Archive).

References

  • Avenarius Archive, Staatsbibliothek zu Berlin—Preußischer Kulturbesitz, Handschriftenabteilung.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wundt Archive, Psychologischen Instituts der Universität Leipzig—Universitätsarchiv Leipzig. http://home.uni-leipzig.de/wundtbriefe/viewer.htm.

  • Araujo, Saulo de Freitas. 2015. Wundt and the Philosophical Foundations of Psychology: A Reappraisal. Heidelberg: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Arens, Katherine. 1989. Structures of Knowing: Psychologies of the Nineteenth Century. Dordrecht: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Avenarius, Richard. 1888. Kritik der reinen Erfahrung. Vol. 1. 2 vols. Leipzig: Fues.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1890. Kritik der reinen Erfahrung. Vol. 1. 2 vols. Leipzig: Fues.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. [1891] 1905. Der menschliche Weltbegriff. Leipzig: Reisland.

    Google Scholar 

  • Blumenthal, Arthur L. 1980. “Wilhelm Wundt: Problems of interpretation.” In Wundt Studies: A Centennial Collection, edited by Wolfgang G. Bringmann and Ryan D. Tweney, 435–45. Toronto: Hogrefe.

    Google Scholar 

  • Boring, Edwin G. 1929. A History of Experimental Psychology. New York: Century.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bringmann, Wolfgang G., and Ryan D. Tweney, eds. 1980. Wundt Studies: A Centennial Collection. Toronto: Hogrefe.

    Google Scholar 

  • Carstanjen, Friedrich. 1898. “Der Empiriokritizismus: Zugleich eine Erwiderung auf W. Wundts Aufsätze ‘Über naiven und kritischen Realismus’.” Vierteljahrsschrift für wissenschaftliche Philosophie 22: 45–95, 190–214, 267–93.

    Google Scholar 

  • Danneberg, Lutz, Andreas Kamlah, and Lothar Schäfer, eds. 1994. Hans Reichenbach und die Berliner Gruppe. Braunschweig: Vieweg.

    Google Scholar 

  • Danziger, Kurt. 1979. “The Positivist Repudiation of Wundt.” Journal of the History of the Behavioral Sciences 15 (3): 205–30.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1990. “Wilhelm Wundt and the Emergence of Experimental Psychology.” In Companion to the History of Modern Science, edited by Robert C. Olby, Geoffrey N. Cantor, John R. R. Christie, and M. J. S. Hodge, 396–408. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2001. “The Unknown Wundt: Drive, Apperception, and Volition.” In Wilhelm Wundt in History, 95–120. Boston: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Diamond, Solomon. 2001. “Wundt before Leipzig.” In Wilhelm Wundt in History, 1–68. Boston: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fechner, Gustav Theodor. 1860. Elemente der Psychophysik. Leipzig: Breitkopf und Härtel.

    Google Scholar 

  • Haller, Rudolf, and Friedrich Stadler. 1993. Wien, Berlin, Prag: Der Aufstieg der wissenschaftlichen Philosophie. Wien: Hölder-Pichler-Tempsky.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hentschel, Klaus, 1990. Die Korrespondenz Petzoldt—Reichenbach: Zur Entwicklung der “wissenschaftlichen Philosophie” in Berlin. Berlin: SIGMA.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kardas, Edward P. 2013. History of Psychology: The Making of a Science. Boston: Cengage Learning.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kusch, Martin. 1995. Psychologism: A Case Study in the Sociology of Philosophical Knowledge. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1999. Psychological Knowledge: A Social History and Philosophy. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lenin, Vladimir I. 1927. Materialism and Empirio-Criticism. Edited by Alexender Trachtenberg. Vol. XIII. Collected Works of V. I. Lenin. London: Martin Lawrence.

    Google Scholar 

  • Milkov, Nikolay, and Volker Peckhaus, eds. 2013. The Berlin Group and the Philosophy of Logical Empiricism. Dordrecht: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mischel, Theodore. 1970. “Wundt and the Conceptual Foundations of Psychology.” Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 31 (1): 1–26.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mülberger, Annette. 2012. “Wundt Contested: The First Crisis Declaration in Psychology.” Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences 43 (2): 434–44.

    Google Scholar 

  • Perry, Ralph B., ed. 1935. The Thought and Character of William James. Vol II. Philosophy and Psychology. London: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rieber, Robert, ed. 1980. Wilhelm Wundt and the Making of a Scientific Psychology. New York: Plenum Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rieber, Robert, and David Robinson, eds. 2001. Wilhelm Wundt in History: The Making of a Scientific Psychology. New York: Kluwer Academic/Plenum Publishers.

    Google Scholar 

  • Robinson, David K. 1987. “Wilhelm Wundt and the Establishment of Experimental Psychology, 1875–1914: The Context of a New Field of Scientific Research”. PhD dissertation‚ University of California, Berkeley.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2001. “Reaction-Time Experiments in Wundt’s Institute and Beyond.” In Wilhelm Wundt in History, 161–204. Boston: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tinker, Miles A. 1932. “Wundt’s Doctorate Students and Their Theses 1875–1920.” The American Journal of Psychology 44 (4): 630–37.

    Google Scholar 

  • Willy, Rudolf. 1899. Die Krisis in der Psychologie. Leipzig: O. R. Reisland.

    Google Scholar 

  • Woodward, William Ray, and Mitchell G. Ash, eds. 1982. The Problematic Science: Psychology in Nineteenth-Century Thought. New York: Praeger.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wundt, Wilhelm. 1874. Grundzüge der physiologischen Psychologie. 1st ed. Leipzig: Engelmann.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1904. Principles of Physiological Psychology. Translated by Edward B. Titchener. New York: Macmillan.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Chiara Russo Krauss .

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2019 The Author(s)

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Russo Krauss, C. (2019). Introduction. In: Wundt, Avenarius, and Scientific Psychology. Palgrave Macmillan, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-12637-7_1

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics