After this introduction into the relevant basics of normative ethics, let us turn to the status quo of EU law referring to ethics and morality. Following the hierarchy of EU law, let us first have a look at primary EU law.Footnote 1

3.1 Constitutional Perspective: The Status Quo of Morality in Primary EU Law

3.1.1 ‘United in Diversity’

The EU’s approach to ethics can best be described by its motto ‘united in diversity’. On the one hand (‘EU united’), the Treaty on European Union draws inspiration “from the cultural, religious and humanist inheritance of Europe”Footnote 2 and the EU Charter of Fundamental Rights which refers to the Union’s “common values”Footnote 3 and “spiritual and moral heritage”.Footnote 4 On the other hand the CFR requires the EU to respect “the diversity of the cultures and traditions of the peoples of Europe as well as the national identities of the Member States”Footnote 5 (‘EU in diversity’).

Initially, EU integration was an economic vehicle, which developed from coal and steel to an internal market, and finally to a political Union (also safeguarding fundamental rights). The internal market is still a key objective of the EU. Nonetheless, on an exceptional basis, MS are allowed to restrict the free movement of goods based on grounds of “public morality, public policy [and so forth]” (Art 36 TFEU). The term of ‘public morality’ itself is not defined in the Treaties. As a notion of EU law, it is interpreted by the CJEU. The Court leaves it to the MS to apply their understanding of public morality, as long as they do not follow a principle of public double morality.Footnote 6

3.1.2 National Umbrella Philosophy

With the expanding case-law of the CJEU interpreting the fundamental freedoms of the internal market, some MS sought to protect their nationally determined understanding of morality. A look at the timeline exhibits the contemporaneity of a famous Irish abortion caseFootnote 7 (4.10.1991) and the Maastricht TreatyFootnote 8 (signed on 7.2.1992), where one of the protocols to this Treaty provides an umbrella, protecting “Article 40.3.3 [right to life of the unborn] of the Constitution of Ireland”.Footnote 9

When Malta acceded to the EU in 2004, a similar protocol was annexed to the Accession Treaty, stating that “[n]othing […] shall affect the application in the territory of Malta of national legislation relating to abortion”.Footnote 10 Although those two instances operated without explicit reference to public morality, the intention was the same, as in the following examples.

In the very same round of accessions, Poland opted for a similar, yet different approach. This can be qualified as “less” in terms of legal significance, as Poland’s concerns were only taken into account in terms of a Declaration of that acceding state. However, at the same time, it can be seen as ‘broader’, in the sense that the wording states as follows: “nothing […] prevents the Polish State in regulating questions of moral significance, as well as those related to the protection of human life”.Footnote 11

With the entering into force of the Lisbon TreatyFootnote 12 (1.12.2009), the previously only solemnly proclaimedFootnote 13 CFR became legally binding.Footnote 14 In this context, Poland seemed to fear that the CFRFootnote 15 “might be used to challenge its freedom to regulate the availability of abortions, euthanasia and same-sex marriage”.Footnote 16 Therefore, the final act of the 13.12.2007 signed Lisbon Treaty contained a declaration by Poland on the CFR, whereby “[t]he Charter does not affect in any way the right of Member States to legislate in the sphere of public morality, family law, as well as the protection of human dignity and respect for human physical and moral integrity”.Footnote 17 Some MS, those present at the time of accession, were united in a position diverse to the Polish one, by underlying in a joint declaration “that the Declarations attached to this Final Act cannot be interpreted or applied in a way contrary to the obligations of the Member States arising from the Treaty and Act of Accession”.Footnote 18

As we have seen (see also Fig. 3.1), EU primary law does not comprise the term ethics, but ‘public morality’.Footnote 19 This notion is a public one, that is to say a collective one, as it is defined by public authorities, not by individuals. We have seen both implicit (in the context of abortion) and explicit reference to public morality.

Fig. 3.1
figure 1

National umbrella philosophy

Has this term been determined regarding its content in EU primary law? No, there are no explicit definitions, most likely because there seems to be, at least a minimum, consensus and the fact that the term of public morality has already been shaped regarding its content by the CJEU. If not defined, is it used in a way, which provides sufficient clarification (i.e. objective 1 of this book)? Due to the historic background and the context of abortion, this second question can be answered in the affirmative.

Nonetheless, the way in which this term of public morality is used cannot be qualified as very ambitious. Quite the opposite, this approach of the “Masters of the Treaties” can be qualified as an “umbrella philosophy”, trying to establish a “principle of non-interference” of EU law with their nationally determined morality.Footnote 20 However, ethics and morality should definitely be more than a mere substitute for a kind of subsidiarity principle.

3.1.3 Excursus: EU Values

EU valuesFootnote 21 are not of relevance for our topic in terms of direct references to ethics or morality. However, Art 2 TEU, which enshrines the values of the EU, is of utmost importance for our topic in an indirect way. This provision has been inserted by the Lisbon Treaty, which entered into force on 1 December 2009, and reads as follows:

The Union is founded on the values of respect for human dignity, freedom, democracy, equality, the rule of law and respect for human rights, including the rights of persons belonging to minorities.

These values are common to the Member States in a society in which pluralism, non-discrimination, tolerance, justice, solidarity and equality between women and men prevail.

The first sentence states the values which according to the wording are pre-existing (“founded on”), however, does not further define them. The second sentence seems to have a different legal significance, as the wording does not refer to the EU, but to the MS, precisely their society. Perhaps one would expect a plural here, but the second sentence speaks of “a society”. According to Pechstein, this formulation fluctuates between (desirably guided) description and prescription,Footnote 22 and can be seen as ‘less’, as it cannot trigger Art 7 TEU (sanctions in case of violations of values).Footnote 23

Hermerén has emphasized that the common values are “one of several ways of keeping the member states of the European Union together by referring to values they have in common and by pointing out differences between these values and others”.Footnote 24 These general common values of the EU have been applied to two areas (digitalization and non-financial reporting, partly in sports) and further specified in others (health and partly in sports), as can be seen below from Table 3.1.

Table 3.1 EU common values applied and further specified

In 2006, thus three years before the entry into force of the Lisbon Treaty, the EU health ministers declared the health values of “universality, access to good quality care, equity, and solidarity”.Footnote 25 This example is not an application of the general values, but a concretization, resulting in mainly distinct values, where only solidarity is part of both the general and these specific values.Footnote 26 For this example of health values, we can again identify the EU’s motto of ‘united in diversity’, as these Council conclusions of 2006 emphasize “that the practical ways in which these values and principles become a reality in the health systems of the EU vary significantly between Member States, and will continue to do so”.Footnote 27 Unlike the general values, this document sheds further light on the content of these values. Equity, for instance, is determined in the sense that it “relates to equal access according to need, regardless of ethnicity, gender, age, social status or ability to pay”. It is also worth mentioning that “[b]eneath [!] these overarching values, there is also a set of operating principlesFootnote 28, which cover quality, safety, care that is based on evidence and ethics, patient involvement, redress, privacy and confidentiality.

From health, let us now turn to corporate social responsibility (CSR). Based on the EU rules on non-financial reportingFootnote 29 for some large companies, the common good matrix, which lies at the heart of the Common Good Balance Sheet, is based on the values of “human dignity, solidarity and social justice, environmental sustainability, transparency and co-determination”.Footnote 30 This is an example of values having a direct impact on (large) companies, where we find an application of some of the EU’s values, adding other ‘principles’ we know from EU law, such as sustainabilityFootnote 31 and transparency.Footnote 32

An EP resolution on integrity, etc. in sportsFootnote 33 took both the approach of promoting the general EU values (“such as pluralism, tolerance, justice, equality and solidarity”),Footnote 34 but also coined distinct values (“such as respect, friendship, tolerance and fair play”Footnote 35; or “such as mutual respect, tolerance, compassion, leadership, equality of opportunity and the rule of law”Footnote 36). Recently, the 2018 Council conclusions on promoting the common values of the EU through sport mainly refer to distinct values (printed in Italics), when they state that “sport can teach values such as fairness, teambuilding, democracy, tolerance, equality, discipline, inclusion, perseverance and respect that could help to promote and disseminate common values of the EU”.Footnote 37 The same is true, when they state that “[v]alues such as mutual respect, fair play, friendship, solidarity, tolerance and equality should be natural to all those involved in sport”.Footnote 38 As we can see, the majority of those values are not part of Art 2 TEU.

In digitalization, the Ethics Advisory Group established by the European Data Protection Supervisor has referred to dignity, freedom, autonomy, solidarity, equality, democracy, justice and truth, in order to leap from the EU’s general common values to ‘digital ethics’.Footnote 39 As we can see, the majority of values are those from Art 2 TEU (e.g. not comprising the rule of law, non-discrimination, tolerance), while also embracing autonomy, one of the principles from the ‘principlism’ of Beauchamp and Childress.

In terms of the legal status, no example except for the non-financial reporting directive, are legally binding (soft-law). Table 3.1 summarizes these four (non-exhaustive) examples of the EU’s general common values in different specific fields.

These EU’s general common values also have an external perspective. In its relations with the wider world, the EU “shall uphold and promote its values and interests and contribute to the protection of its citizens […,] contribute to peace, security, the sustainable development of the Earth, solidarity and mutual respect among peoples, free and fair trade, eradication of poverty and the protection of human rights”.Footnote 40

3.2 External Perspective: International Agreements, etc.

After the constitutional perspective (EU primary law), let us now turn to the external ethical perspective. Following the hierarchy of EU law,Footnote 41 the following chapter focuses on references to ethics and morality in international agreements (etc.),Footnote 42 before we will then turn to the internal perspective (EU secondary law, etc.) in the next chapter.

The documents identified have been researched in the EU’s EUR-Lex database, searching for the terms ‘ethi*’ and ‘mora*’ (both, in title and text), and in the two sub-categories of ‘international agreements’ and in ‘EFTA documents’.Footnote 43 This research comprises both ‘international agreements’ according to Art 216 TFEU, as well as ‘association agreements’ in the sense of Art 217 TFEU. Moreover, ‘resolutions’, for instance of a Joint (Parliamentary) Assembly, which have been documented in EUR-Lex, have also been taken into account. On the other hand, irrelevant terms have been excluded.Footnote 44

3.2.1 Status Quo of Ethics and Morality

Often, EU law refers to ethics and/or morality in different sensitive fields. This is also the case for one prominent example of an international agreement, the ‘Comprehensive Economic and Trade Agreement’ (CETA) between Canada, of the one part, and the EU and its Member States, of the other part.Footnote 45 In the heated debates, investment protection was one of the main issues. Hence, it is no surprise that the provision on the members of the multilateral investment tribunal is entitled ‘ethics’, emphasizing the importance of the independence of its members and the avoidance of both a direct or indirect conflict of interest.Footnote 46 In addition, the ‘Joint Interpretative Instrument’ stresses that “[s]trict [!] ethical rules for these individuals have been set to ensure their independence and impartiality, the absence of conflict of interest, bias or appearance of bias”.Footnote 47

This example of CETA investment protection referring to ethics concerns a very sensitive issue, which is key for the trust of citizens in order to alleviate fears of big companies being able to ‘buy justice’. In terms of determination of content, it is quite clear what the reference to ethics should stand for (independence and avoidance of conflict of interest). Apart from investment protection, we can also find a reference to ethics in the context of the recognition of professional qualifications.Footnote 48

References in CETA to ‘morality’ follow a common pattern, which we have already seen in EU primary law (Art 36 TFEU: ‘public morality’), where the concept of ‘public morals’ is one of the exceptions (or: ‘reasons of justification’), besides ‘public order’ and ‘public safety’, to name but a few.

Another example comprising several references to ethics is the Korea agreement.Footnote 49 This agreement is also about trust based on ethics in a sensitive field. Here, ‘ethical business practices’ have to be set in place in order to avoid improper inducements by manufacturers and suppliers of pharmaceutical products or medical devices to health care professionals or institutions for the listing, purchasing or prescribing of pharmaceutical products and medical devices eligible for reimbursement under health care programmes.Footnote 50

After those two representative examples of such international agreements referring to ethics, let us take a more detailed look at this issue and especially at the question of the determination of content (objective 1) of international agreements referring to ethics. Often we can find almost identical approaches in various agreements, as in some of the following examples referring to the Georgia agreement, the references could also have been indicated with regard to the Ukraine association agreement,Footnote 51 to name but one.

  • In the context of trade and customs legislation, we can find the situation, not of ethics being determined by reference to other notions such as avoidance of conflicts of interest, independence, etc., but on the contrary the opposite situation. The association agreement with Georgia refers to the ‘Blueprint on Customs ethics’ in order to determine “the highest standards of integrity” in this regard.Footnote 52 In a similar way, the agreement with Indonesia refers to the ‘World Tourism Organisation’s Global Code of Ethics for Tourism’ in order to “ensure balanced and sustainable development of tourism”.Footnote 53

  • In the Georgia agreement, we can find one example, where the meaning of ethics can be traced in a systematic interpretation, when in the context of ‘trade and investment promoting sustainable development’, Art 231 refers to “voluntary sustainability assurance schemes such as fair and ethical trade schemes and eco-labels”. Similar examples can be found in the context of tourism (“promote ethical standards in tourism by introducing a certified European Fair Trade Tourism label”).Footnote 54

  • Another common field of ‘ethicalization’ are references to ‘professional ethics’ both in the private, as well as in the public field. Such rules can even apply after leaving the job.Footnote 55

    • For lawyers providing legal services in respect of public international law and foreign law, the Georgia agreement refers to “compliance with local codes of ethics”.Footnote 56 This approach makes sense, if the legal rules in this area are also located at national level.

    • Professional ethics in the public field can be found in the Moldova agreement.Footnote 57 This agreement foresees rules on cooperation, with the aim of fostering efficient and accountable public administration in Moldova, and to support the implementation of the rule of law. This cooperation shall, amongst others, also cover “the promotion of ethical values in the civil service”.Footnote 58 It is interesting to see the link between ethics and values, although the detailed content remains somehow vague.

    • In another private field, the agreement with Central America states that cooperation on microcredit and microfinance shall also address the “exchange of experiences and expertise in the area of ethical banking”.Footnote 59 The same statement with regard to the determination of ethics applies here.

    • Although training is an important element for ethical behaviour,Footnote 60 the following example is completely undetermined. This agreement states that elements of a training programme for port State inspectors should include, amongst others, “[E]thics”.Footnote 61 Maybe this lacking determination is less of a problem, as ‘ethics’ here can be read in terms of the title of a subject of this training programme.

  • In the field of healthcare, we have already seen the example of the Korea agreement, referring to ethical business practices of improper inducements by manufacturers and suppliers of pharmaceutical products or medical devices to health care professionals or institutions.Footnote 62

    • Another provision of the same Annex on pharmaceutical products and medical devices confirms the shared principles of the contracting parties with regard to “ethical practices by manufacturers and suppliers of pharmaceutical products and medical devices and by health care providers on a global basis in order to achieve open, transparent, accountable and non-discriminatory health care decision-making”.Footnote 63 As the telosFootnote 64 is clearly stated, we have a strong guidance towards the determination of the meaning of ethics in this regard. This example is reminiscent of consequentialism (‘in order to’), however, at the same time exhibits some elements of principlismFootnote 65 (transparency, non-discrimination, etc.).

    • Another example in cross-border healthcare deals with a kind of ‘circumvention tourism’.Footnote 66 This resolution “[c]alls on all States to ensure the ethics of transplantation by adopting measures to eliminate ‘transplant tourism’”.Footnote 67 Here, too, we have a strong guidance with regard to the determination of the content of ethics, as the telos is clearly stated.

  • In another field, which we can entitle with ‘ethics and society’, we find a reference to “the ethical, cultural and social values of the society” to which children belong and which shall not prejudice the right of the child to a loving family.Footnote 68 Although ethics is not determined in this document itself, we can read it as a reference to the national or regional level of the relevant society.

After ethics, let us now turn to references to morality. The introductory example of CETA is representative in the sense that in the majority of cases, ‘public morality’Footnote 69 is used as an exception clause.Footnote 70 Besides public security or public order, ‘public morals’ can be such a reason of justification (‘exception’), provided that such measures are not applied in a manner which would constitute a means of “arbitrary or unjustifiable discrimination between countries where like conditions prevail, or a disguised restriction on establishment or cross-border supply of services”.Footnote 71 This is an approach, which we already know from inside of the internal market.

A slightly different version of an exception clause can be found in the Ukraine Agreement, where one of the grounds for refusal or invalidity of a trademark registration are trademarks, which are contrary to ‘public policy’ or “to accepted principles of morality”.Footnote 72 While this concept is undetermined, a similar provision on patents (protection of biotechnological inventions) is more precise, as it states examples of what is considered un-patentable: processes for cloning human beings, or modifying their germ line genetic identity, as well as uses of human embryos for industrial or commercial purposes.Footnote 73

In the field of development aid, we find examples of morality used as an argument supporting a certain position. A resolution on climate change states that industrialised countries “have a historical responsibility for climate change and are morally obliged to assist ACP countries”.Footnote 74 Another one notes the “moral and sovereign rights of affected Southern African states to accept or reject GMOs coming as food aid”,Footnote 75 as well as the “eradication of poverty to be a moral and political imperative”.Footnote 76 This phenomenon causes no major challenges, if a legal provision ‘only’ refers to moral (or ethical) considerations as a supporting argument.Footnote 77

This is more difficult with the following example, as it is not quite clear, what is meant by the “moral, political and economic support [that] should be offered to the Burundian people”.Footnote 78 How does a moral support look like, is there a right to moral support, etc.?

  • An interesting example can be found in the following resolution on embargoes: “Points out that, whilst the overt reason for imposing sanctions is normally to bring about a change of regime in a particular country, or at least a major change in the policy of that country’s government, their imposition may also serve simply as an expression of moral condemnation”.Footnote 79 While besides other hard-facts morality also seems to be important, we can see this as a minimum approach (‘at least’ moral support).

  • The wording “every child has a right to a standard of living adequate for the child’s physical, mental, spiritual, moral and social development”Footnote 80 is reminiscent of Art 32 CFR, which addresses the “physical, mental, moral or social development” of young people at work.

  • The following example concerning the appointment of arbitrators reminds us of the members of the multilateral investment tribunal in CETA: “appointment of an independent and impartial arbitrator of a nationality other than the nationalities of the parties, and of high moral standing.”Footnote 81 The content of this moral standing remains undetermined.

  • The same applies for the last example in this regard: “The salary and social contributions of observers shall be borne by the competent authorities of the Gabonese Republic. Captains shall do everything in their power to ensure the physical and moral safety of observers carrying out their duties.”Footnote 82

Finally, we do not only find examples relating to human beings, in the context of animal transport, the preamble of this Convention holds that “every person has a moral obligation to respect all animals and to have due consideration for their capacity for suffering”,Footnote 83 and another one with a similar wording referring to “their capacity for suffering and memory”.Footnote 84 Hence, two references to moral obligations, which can be seen as supporting arguments.

After international agreements, let us now turn to documents of the ‘European Free Trade Area’ (EFTA), which are displayed here in a separate way due to three reasons. First, because of the significance of this agreement, second, because they are also separately documented in the EUR-Lex database, and finally, because they occur in a different context. EFTA comprises Norway, Iceland, Liechtenstein and Switzerland, where all of these countries, except for Switzerland, are linked to the EU via the European Economic Area (EEA).Footnote 85

There are two examples of EFTA documents referring to ethics, both from the EFTA Surveillance Authority (ESA), which is the equivalent to the EC in terms of monitoring and enforcing the relevant rules. In the context of the financial crisis, a global reduction in liquidity, and various other complex reasons led to the collapse of the three main Islandic banks. An essential part of the Icelandic financial sector “was the restructuring of household and corporate debt”, which was qualified to be “a complex and sensitive issue with a number of financial, economic and ethical considerations”.Footnote 86 Some of the “most relevant changes” addressed in terms of restructuring aid granted to the Landsbankinn banks was “revised risk management and a greater significance of corporate responsibility and compliance with high ethical standards”.Footnote 87

What we can see here is another example of referring to ethics in a sensitive field. The first example exhibits a general awareness for ethics,Footnote 88 while the second is not determined regarding its content. How should those standards look like, where could they be found? Such ethical rules should be further determined, especially in the banking sector.

Both ESA decisions also address the issue of ‘moral hazard’, which is a term of microeconomics. “In general, moral hazard occurs when a party whose actions are unobserved affects the probability or magnitude of a payment”.Footnote 89 This can occur in case “of workers who perform below their capabilities when employers cannot monitor their behavior (‘job shirking’)”,Footnote 90 or in case of banks shifting risk to the general tax-paying public. Both decisions address moral hazard in the context of burden sharing in the sense that “aid should be limited to the minimum necessary and an appropriate own contribution to restructuring costs should be provided by the aid beneficiary”.Footnote 91 These examples of referring to a non-legal term are less of a problem. First, we deal with a reference to a determined concept (here not of practical philosophy, but of economics), and the consequences are clearly stated. Hence, we could qualify this reference as a supporting argument, as we have already seen.Footnote 92

In terms of morality, we can find an example of referring to moral obligations in a situation, where no legal obligation exists. In the discussion of adjusting the EEA agreement in terms of higher contributions in the context of the EU enlargement, one argument used was “the EEA EFTA States’ obligation to provide (moral) support in connection with the enlargement of the EU”. This was stated, because under the EEA Agreement, “the EU has no legal entitlement to demand a sharp increase in the previous level of payments”.Footnote 93

3.2.2 Conclusion

As of 1993, we can trace the first references to ethics in international agreements, with the majority of relevant documents since the turn of the millennium.Footnote 94 This roughly corresponds with the general ‘ethicalization’ in terms of the founding of ethics advisory bodies at EU level in 1991 and 1997 respectively.Footnote 95

We have seen references to ethics in several sensitive fields, such as investment tribunals, influence of the pharma industry on doctors, etc., or the supporting of private banks with taxpayers’ money. What these examples have in common is the fact that ethics is always a means of strengthening citizens’ trust in these areas.

Often we have seen similar approaches in different agreements, as well as a link between concepts such as integrity and ethics. The key question, which is the determination of content of both ethics and morality (i.e. objective 1) has to be answered in a differentiated way: sometimes, it was possible to trace the meaning of these references to ethics and morality, but at times, this was not the case. In some of the numerous references in the context of professional ethics, the task of determining the content was one of the national level, as this level was also in charge of the legal perspective. The notion of morality has mainly been used as an exception clause, besides self-standing notions such as ‘moral hazard’. The beneficiaries of ethical behaviour have mainly been humans, but some examples also covered animals. Some of these documents also referred to related concepts such as values.Footnote 96 This is true for CETA, which “reflects the strength and depth of the EU-Canada relationship, as well as the fundamental values that we cherish”.Footnote 97 No references to ethics or morality can be found in the recent EU Japan agreement published in July 2018.Footnote 98

3.3 Internal Law Making Perspective

3.3.1 A ‘Gouvernement Des Juges’?

EU law also comprises case-law and the CJEU case-law has played a paramount role in shaping the EU acquis. Therefore, let us now turn to ethics and morality in case-law and analyse the CJEU’s approach in this field. In EU integration in general, the CJEU has often been criticized for its pro-active role.Footnote 99 As already mentioned, this chapter shall answer the question, if we can observe a ‘gouvernement des juges’, or if the CJEU rather takes a more reluctant approach, a so-called ‘judicial self-restraint’ (i.e. objective 3)?

3.3.1.1 The CJEU’s Judicial Self-restraint

Analysing the case-law of the CJEU, one has to be aware of cases where the judgment merely quotes EU legislation (as this will be covered separatelyFootnote 100), international or national law. In addition, ethics and morality used as arguments of the parties of a case (EC, other EU institutions, or MS) have to be seen in a different light, the same applies for questions of a national court in a preliminary ruling procedure. Finally, one has to separate arguments of an Advocate General, and the binding judgment of the Court of Justice.

EU law affects almost every aspect of national law, thus also some very sensitive areas. As the Court has held, there are areas “in which there are significant moral, religious and cultural differences between the Member States. In the absence of [EU] harmonisation in the field, it is for each Member State to determine in those areas, in accordance with its own scale of values, what is required in order to ensure that the interests in question are protected”.Footnote 101 This is the case in the following fields: various games of chance,Footnote 102 the import of “articles having an indecent or obscene character”,Footnote 103 protection of children from immoral media,Footnote 104 prostitution,Footnote 105 or abortion.Footnote 106

We have already seen the notion of ‘public morality’, as one of the reasons of justification in the context of the fundamental freedoms of the internal market, where a similar approach was taken in international agreements. Interpreting this reason of justification, the Court held that “in principle it is for each Member State to determine in accordance with its own scale of values and in the form selected by it the requirements of public morality in its territory”.Footnote 107 Hence, it is not the EU to determine this notion, nor a majority of MS, but each single MS. Reference is also made to the national values, although one should take into account that this statement (1986) was given roughly 20 years before the Lisbon Treaty inserted Art 2 TEU on the common values.Footnote 108 The limitation stated in this case was the one of ‘double morality’, where goods legal in the home country cannot be qualified as obscene, if imported from another MS.Footnote 109

‘Ethics’ was an issue for instance in an Austrian case on the protection of pregnant workers against dismissal from work.Footnote 110 The question was on the beginning of pregnancy in case of in vitro fertilisation (IVF): either already at the time of fertilization of her ova by her partner’s sperm cells, or at the time of transfer into her uterus. Before providing an answer on the details of this case, the Court gave a very important general statement:

artificial fertilisation and viable cells treatment is a very sensitive social issue in many Member States, marked by their multiple traditions and value systems, the Court is not called upon, by the present order for reference, to broach questions of a medical or ethical nature, but must restrict itself to a legal interpretation of the relevant provisions of [EU law].Footnote 111

At the time of this judgment, the Lisbon Treaty had already been signed (2007), although not yet entered into force (2009). Still, the Court referred to the “multiple traditions and value systems”. This Grand Chamber judgment clearly demonstrates the Court’s judicial self-restraint, comprising various dimensions: a vertical one, whereas these questions have to be determined at a national level, as well as a horizontal one, according to which it is for the legislature and not for the courts, to decide on these “sensitive social issue[s]”. As the Court has held in other cases concerning ‘morality’, “[e]ven if the morality of lotteries is at least questionable, it is not for the Court to substitute its assessment for that of the legislatures of the Member States”.Footnote 112 Even if the Court, in the following, decides this IVF case solely by interpreting the relevant provisions of EU law (i.e. beginning of pregnancy only as of transfer into uterus), in the end this legal interpretation of legal norms will have an indirect impact on the ethical nature of this topic. Moreover, although it is for the MS to take these decisions, the legal interpretation takes place at EU level. Based on this analysis, it is also not really a necessity for the CJEU to determine the content of the concept of ‘ethics’, as this perspective has been clearly excluded for the procedure of solving this case.

Three years later, the Court (again, Grand Chamber) had to decide another case in the field of bioethics, namely on the patentability of neural precursor cells and the processes for their production from embryonic stem cells. This case was about the Directive on biotechnological inventions, which, amongst others, excludes the patentability of “uses of human embryos for industrial or commercial purposes”.Footnote 113 The key challenge, thus, centred on the interpretation of the notion of ‘human embryo’. The Court confirmed its statement in Mayr, not to decide questions of ethical nature in very sensitive fields, which are marked by MS’s “multiple traditions and value systems”, such as the definition of human embryo.Footnote 114 However, it took a different approach, as this statement would suggest. The Court lifted the interpretation of this notion form the MS level at EU level, when stating that the notion of ‘human embryo’ is “an autonomous concept of European Union law which must be interpreted in a uniform manner throughout the territory of the Union”.Footnote 115 While there are good reasons that notions, which are decisive for the internal market are defined at EU level,Footnote 116 a consistent application of the ‘multiple value systems’ approach should have led to a definition at national level, only constrained by the limitation of ‘double morality’.Footnote 117

Based on the concept of ‘human dignity’, which was mentioned in the Directive as a reason to exclude patentability,Footnote 118 the Court held “that the concept of ‘human embryo’ within the meaning of Article 6(2)(c) of the Directive must be understood in a wide senseFootnote 119 and came to the following solution for fertilised and non-fertilised ova.

Accordingly, any human ovum must, as soon as fertilised, be regarded as a ‘human embryo’ within the meaning and for the purposes of the application of Article 6(2)(c) of the Directive, since that fertilisation is such as to commence the process of development of a human being.Footnote 120

That classification must also apply to a non-fertilised human ovum into which the cell nucleus from a mature human cell has been transplanted and a non-fertilised human ovum whose division and further development have been stimulated by parthenogenesis. Although those organisms have not, strictly speaking, been the object of fertilisation, due to the effect of the technique used to obtain them they are, as is apparent from the written observations presented to the Court, capable of commencing the process of development of a human being just as an embryo created by fertilisation of an ovum can do so.Footnote 121

It is important to stress, from where the Court got this ‘natural science’ related information. Here, in Brüstle, the Court relied on information presented by the parties of this case, in MayrFootnote 122 the relevant information was provided by the Commission.

Three years later, in another Grand Chamber judgment, the Court partly had to revoke the approach it took in Brüstle, when interpreting the same legal provision. This case was about unfertilised human ovum (second quotation mentioned above) whose division and development to a certain stage have been stimulated by parthenogenesis. Although in this case the Court itself did not refer to the terms ethics or morality, this judgment is highly relevant to our issue. The Court emphasized that the legal solution in Brüstle had been based on “the written observations presented to the Court”.Footnote 123

However, in the present case, the referring [N.B. national] court […] stated in essence that, according to current scientific knowledge, a human parthenote, due to the effect of the technique used to obtain it, is not as such capable of commencing the process of development which leads to a human being. That assessment is shared by all of the interested parties who submitted written observations to the Court.Footnote 124

In the following, the Court did not take the final decision itself, but left it to the national court “to determine whether or not, in the light of knowledge which is sufficiently tried and tested by international medical science […], human parthenotes, such as those which are the subject of the applications for registration in the case in the main proceedings, have the inherent capacity of developing into a human being”.Footnote 125

What we can take away from this case is the fact that the Court’s approach in Brüstle, to shift the solution of a “very sensitive” issue at EU level, was a ‘flash in the pan’. It is difficult to verify or falsify the statement that the CJEU’s interpretation of human dignity in Brüstle was “motivated by (covert) religious motives”.Footnote 126 However, we can clearly state that nowadays it is more likely that the CJEU would decide a case such as Brüstle in a more reluctant way, that is to say, not to lift such interpretations of key terms (such as ‘human embryo’) to EU level. The Court also made clear that its statements are “limited to the patentability of biotechnological inventions”.Footnote 127 In other words, the CJEU did not want to decide the issue of the beginning of human life in general. This sectoral approach is also important insofar as otherwise we would have a contradiction between Mayr (transfer into uterus) on the one hand, and Brüstle (human embryo, as soon as fertilised) as well as ISC (“capacity to develop into a human being”Footnote 128), on the other.

Another example of the Court’s more reluctant approach in a sensitive field is ‘surrogacy’, a phenomenon, which, according to the EP, “undermines the human dignity of the woman since her body and its reproductive functions are used as a commodity”.Footnote 129, Footnote 130 In two judgments, both given nine month before the ISC case, the Court had to decide technical questions of non-discrimination based on genderFootnote 131 and disability.Footnote 132 Although surrogacy can easily be qualified as a “very sensitive social issue” as stated in MayrFootnote 133 and Brüstle,Footnote 134 the Court (again, Grand Chamber) neither referred to ethics nor morality, and solved this case at a legal level in a very technical way. One explanation could be that the relevant provisions of EU law did not refer to these terms of ‘ethics’ or ‘morality’, which is why the Court saw no necessity to ‘leave the legal turf’.

After these examples related to different EU directives, let us turn back to the fundamental freedoms. Here we have seen the Court’s reluctant approach, leaving more discretion to the MS, which corresponds with the ‘post-Brüstle approach’. The key limitation we have seen there was a prohibition of ‘double morality’.Footnote 135 Apart from this, the CJEU has developed another very acceptable solution to deal with ethically sensitive issues, which is a ‘more generous’ proportionalityFootnote 136 review. This has been qualified as a “procedural” review by de Witte in his seminal paper “Sex, drugs & EU law”,Footnote 137 or as a “minimal proportionality control” by Hatzopoulos.Footnote 138 This can be seen as a ‘golden mean’ between either deciding these questions at national level in terms of diversity of moral and ethical choices (argument from self-determinationFootnote 139), and the decision of such issues at EU level by “the transnational judiciary” (argument from containmentFootnote 140). This means that the CJEU intervenes less substantively in the national regulation by means of the proportionality test, or as de Witte puts it:

It is argued that a procedural proportionality test that respects the substance of national moral and ethical choices, and that instead focuses on teasing out discriminatory or protectionist biases, must only assess the normative coherence of national policies, the consistent application of sanctions, and legislative transparency.Footnote 141

The CJEC would therefore not require a Member State to follow the approach of another Member State. As long as the Member State concerned does not act in contradictory ways within its own legal system, the CJEC will not ‘interfere’. This approach also entails the prohibition of ‘double morality’, as mentioned above.

In this context, the CJEU has also made an important clarification in the famous Omega case. The question centred on the number of MS that have to adopt a certain position based on ethical or moral grounds. In an earlier judgment on gambling, the Court has held as follows:

First of all, it is not possible to disregard the moral, religious or cultural aspects of lotteries, like other types of gambling, in all the Member States. The general tendency of the Member States is to restrict, or even prohibit, the practice of gambling and to prevent it from being a source of private profit. […]Footnote 142

The necessary number of MS having to share a similar view was clarified as follows:

It is not indispensable in that respect for the restrictive measure issued by the authorities of a Member State to correspond to a conception shared by all Member States as regards the precise way in which the fundamental right or legitimate interest in question is to be protected. Although, in paragraph 60 of Schindler [N.B. see supra], the Court referred to moral, religious or cultural considerations which lead all Member States to make the organisation of lotteries and other games with money subject to restrictions, it was not its intention, by mentioning that common conception, to formulate a general criterion for assessing the proportionality of any national measure which restricts the exercise of an economic activity.Footnote 143

Omega was not only an important case in terms of the extent of a consensus between MS, it can also be seen as a landmark case in terms of addressing values,Footnote 144 three years before the signing of the Lisbon Treaty. This case was about the possibility to restrict the fundamental freedoms based on “a fundamental value enshrined in the national [i.e. German] constitution, namely human dignity”.Footnote 145 The Court allowed this national value, now an EU value, to enter the fundamental freedoms via the notion of ‘public order’, despite the high requirements in this context: first, ‘public policy’ “must be interpreted strictly” and, second, there has to be a “genuine and sufficiently serious threat to a fundamental interest of society”.Footnote 146 The strong content-related link between ‘public policy’ as a legal reason of justification and morality also becomes obvious, when the Court states that “the concept of public policy may vary from one country to another and from one era to another”Footnote 147; thus, also the regional and evolutionary character, we have already seen for ‘public morality’.

Another sensitive area is genetically modified organisms (‘GMOs’). In this context, a directive emphasizes the importance of “ethical principles recognised in a Member State”, which allows them to “take into consideration ethical aspects when GMOs are deliberately released or placed on the market as or in products”.Footnote 148 This might have inspired Poland to argue with ethical principles for defending non-compliance with this Directive, precisely the argument that “the adoption of the contested national provisions was inspired by the Christian and Humanist ethical principles adhered to by the majority of the Polish people”.Footnote 149 In this regard, Poland put forward the following arguments:

a Christian conception of life which is opposed to the manipulation and transformation of living organisms created by God into material objects which are the subject of intellectual property rights; a Christian and Humanist conception of progress and development which urges respect for creation and a quest for harmony between Man and Nature; and, lastly, Christian and Humanist social principles, the reduction of living organisms to the level of products for purely commercial ends being likely, inter alia, to undermine the foundations of society.Footnote 150

This case would have allowed the CJEU to broach intriguing questions of the relationship of EU law and ethics. However, the Court did not enter into a substantive analysis. By stating that Poland, “upon which the burden of proof lies in such a case, has failed, in any event, to establish that the true purpose of the contested national provisions was in fact to pursue the religious and ethical objectives relied upon”,Footnote 151 it is consequently “not necessary to rule on the question whether—and, if so, to what extent and under which possible circumstances—the Member States retain an option to rely on ethical or religious arguments in order to justify the adoption of internal measures which […] derogate from [EU law]”.Footnote 152 While it is not surprising that the Court did not allow a MS to deviate from legal obligations of an EU Directive, this statement at least leaves open the possibility of a MS, which is able to comply with this burden of proof, to rely on ethical grounds. This case is also interesting because it does not only address the relationship of EU law and ethics, but also of ethics and religion, precisely, one religion (Christianity), and of humanism.

It is also worth mentioning that Poland has positioned ethics as an argument at different levels, in order to defend its position. Poland referred to both the Polish society which “attaches great importance to Christian and Roman Catholic values”, as well as to the members of the Polish parliament.Footnote 153 It is no surprise, that the Court clearly rejected this possibility by stating “a Member State cannot rely in that manner on the views of a section of public opinion in order unilaterally to challenge a harmonising measure adopted by the [EU] institutions”.Footnote 154

3.3.1.2 Conclusion

Based on the analysis of this case-law the above-mentioned question can clearly be addressed in the sense of a judicial self-restraint. This is true both with regard to ethics and morality, thus in either case, the Court saw no necessity to determine the content of these concepts, as this decision was left to the MS, acting according to their values. This holds true for the above-mentioned sensitive fields, where the Court has observed “significant moral, religious and cultural differences”. However, on a timeline, today, one would have to add the EU’s common values. As stated in Omega, a consensus amongst the MS is no necessity and the Court accepts aspects that are specifically important for a country, such as human dignity for Germany, or for Italy, rejecting the mafia. In the latter situation, the General Court recently has accepted the non-registration of a figurative trademark “La Mafia” emphasizing “accepted principles of morality are not the same in all Member States, inter alia for linguistic, historic, social and cultural reasons”.Footnote 155

The Court’s technical legal approach can be welcomed as it leaves these decisions to the national level and to the citizens’ representatives. However, one should not disregard the fact that in an indirect way also the legal approach will determine a medically or ethically sensitive topic. Due to this judicial self-restraint, the Court only provides sectoral solutions, thus no general statement with regard to the beginning of life.Footnote 156

The limitations to this national discretion are the prohibition of double morality and the requirements of coherence and legislative transparency, or in other terms, a reduced (or ‘procedural’) proportionality review.

The relationship between law and ethics concerns similar issues, as the one of law and religion. In this context, there would have been very interesting topics in this GMO case, which in the end have not been answered, since Poland has not been able to prove its point of view.

After this qualitative analysis, let us have a brief look at some quantitative findings of analysing the terms of ‘ethics’ and ‘morality’ in CJEU case-law from 1961–2015.Footnote 157 Focusing on those cases, where the Court itself has refereed to these terms (thus, excluding quotations of EU law or mere statements of parties, referring to these key terms), this research has revealed that more than 70% of cases have been decided since 1998,Footnote 158 with 29% references to ethics, 67% to morality, and 4% to both terms.Footnote 159 This roughly corresponds with general ‘ethicalization’ since the 1990s.

3.3.2 Ethics in Law Making: Ethics Rules on Lobbying

After EU primary law (the constitutional perspective) and international agreements (the external perspective), before turning to EU secondary (and tertiary) law (the internal legislative perspective, in terms of the output), we need to shed some light on the decision-making procedure itself. Lobbying is a much-contested topic, especially because of asymmetries regarding information, but also regarding resources in general. A lack of transparency often leads to mistrust, as we have seen in case of CETA. Similar to CETA and the fear of the possibility to ‘buy justice’ in the context of investment protection tribunals, lobbying is very much about the fear of citizens that large companies can simply ‘buy legislation’.

None of the three decision-making powers of the EU, the EC, the EP nor the Council of the EU, mention either ethics or morality in their Rules of Procedure,Footnote 160 and the same is true for the EU staff regulations.Footnote 161 Thus, as mentioned above,Footnote 162 for this chapter also implicit references will be taken into account, as there is no explicit mentioning of ‘ethics’ or ‘morality’. Tracing these implicit references shall make it possible to answer the question, if the EU provides for ‘ethical lobbying’, and how the determination takes place.Footnote 163

These implicit references occur in terms of principles such as integrity, diligence, honesty and accountability, which can refer either to the targets, or to the actors of lobbying. The majority of documents of this ‘acquis légal & éthique’ concerns targets.Footnote 164 Hence, we will start analysing the rules on these targets (comprising both political actors, as well as administrative staff), before moving to the actors, i.e. consultants and lobbyists, as well as experts.

3.3.2.1 Rules on Targets

Besides a general negative conception of lobbyingFootnote 165 and information asymmetries,Footnote 166 the most common challenges with regard to targets of lobbying are conflicts of interest, acceptance of gifts and corruption,Footnote 167 and finally the revolving doors phenomenon. They can be overcome by transparency, other general ‘guiding principles’ on ‘ethical behaviour’, rules on independence and accountability towards citizens and one’s institution, and finally rules on post term-of-office.

Transparency plays a key role for lobbying and can contribute to more ethical lobbying in manifold ways.Footnote 168 For instance, it can help to overcome information asymmetries, by enabling more equal access to information. At the same time, it can improve the quality of decisions taken, if these decisions (plus corresponding background information) can be known by others, and therefore be challenged. Transparency is an important principle of EU law, which is enshrined in Art 1 TEU and 10 TEU and in Art 15 TFEU. According to the CJEU, it “enables citizens to participate more closely in the decision-making process and guarantees that the administration enjoys greater legitimacy and is more effective and more accountable to the citizen in a democratic system”.Footnote 169

In terms of ‘guiding principles’, the EP provides most principles in its Code of Conduct (EP CoC)Footnote 170; these are: “disinterest, integrity, openness, diligence, honesty, accountability and respect for Parliament’s reputation”.Footnote 171 Integrity is also the principle that plays a key role for the independence of the Commission, whereas its members shall “behave with integrity and discretion”Footnote 172 with regard to appointments or benefits, after they have ceased to hold office. In literature, integrity has been defined as “the quality of being honest and morally upright”.Footnote 173 In January 2018, the EC adopted a new Code of Conduct (EC CoC), which requires members to “behave and perform their duties with complete independence, integrity, dignity, with loyalty and discretion”, as well as to “observe the highest standards of ethical conduct”.Footnote 174 The fact that these ‘ethical standards’ are not directly determined is less of a problem, as the principles mentioned before will very much contribute to the determination of these ethical standards. Integrity seems to be an important principle in this regard, as it is further determined in Art 6 CoC. This includes the requirement to manage the material resources of the EC in a “responsible manner”, reluctance in the context of free travel offered by third parties and hospitality, not to accept gifts worth more than € 150,Footnote 175 as well as notification of any decoration, prize or honour awarded to them. For ‘officials of the Union’, i.e. the staff of EU institutions, several principles are addressed. These comprise objectivity, impartiality and loyalty to the EU,Footnote 176 independence and avoidance of “actual or potential conflict of interest”,Footnote 177 “integrity and discretion” after leaving the service,Footnote 178 as well as requirements for recruitment, “highest standard of ability, efficiency and integrity”.Footnote 179 In addition, for the Commission’s staff the relevant document also mentions objectivity and impartiality as key principles, besides the ‘general principles’ of lawfulness, non-discrimination and equal treatment, proportionality and consistency.Footnote 180 Although not a target of lobbying, also the CJEU in its recent code of conduct does not refer to ethics or morality as such, but operates based on principles, such as independence, integrity, dignity, impartiality, loyalty, discretion, and avoidance of a conflict of interest.Footnote 181

Regarding its content, unethical behaviour very often can be explained in terms of a conflict of interest, which occurs in situations, where a person is faced with a clash of a personal interest and the public interest, this person has to represent. According to the EC Code of conduct, “[a] conflict of interest arises where a personal interest may influence the independent performance of their duties”, or negatively defined, a conflict of interest does not exist if a member is only concerned as a member of the general public or of a broad class of persons.Footnote 182 Transparency also plays a role here, in the avoidance of conflicts of interest, by means of disclosure obligations with regard to certain financial interests (occupation, board membership, company holdings, etc.).Footnote 183

The phenomenon of ‘revolving doors’ refers to situations, where former public officials start working in the private sector in jobs which target their former field of profession, or where individuals join an EU institution from the private sector.Footnote 184 This can result in privileged access of certain interest groups to decision makers. According to the European Ombudsman, implementing rules on this phenomenon “is central to maintaining high ethical standards in public administrations”.Footnote 185 Based on recent scandals (e.g. ‘Barrosogate’Footnote 186), the EC CoC has strengthened the rules on ‘post term of office activities’, whereby the members continue to be bound by their duty of integrity and discretion (‘cooling-off period’).Footnote 187 This comprises, amongst others, the prohibition for former Commissioners to lobby members or their staff “on matters for which they were responsible within their portfolio for a period of two years after ceasing to hold office”.Footnote 188 In case of the president, this period is even three years.Footnote 189 The EP has softer rules on lobbying, as former members of the EP (MEPs) just have to inform the EP and may not benefit from facilities granted to former MEPs, but lobbying as such is not prohibited.Footnote 190 While the only possible argument could be seen in the bigger number of former MEPs, this topic is clearly a possibility for the EP to increase citizens’ trust by strengthening these post-term rules. In terms of EU staff, “appointing authority shall, in principle, prohibit them, during the 12 months after leaving the service, from engaging in lobbying or advocacy vis-à-vis staff of their former institution”.Footnote 191

All these substantive rules have to be accompanied by procedural safeguards. The EP has established an Advisory Committee on the Conduct of Members (‘the Advisory Committee’), which shall make recommendations in the event of possible breaches of the EP’s code of conduct.Footnote 192 The requirements for qualification of its five membersFootnote 193 are not very ambitious, since it only requires “taking due account of the Members’ experience and of political balance”.Footnote 194 Requested by the president of the EP, the Advisory Committee shall examine the circumstances of the alleged breach, and may hear the MEP concerned. Based on its findings, the Advisory Committee makes a recommendation to the EP president concerning a possible decision.Footnote 195 The Committee also has an important preventive function. If a possible conflict of interest occurs, in case of ambiguity a MEP may seek advice in confidence from the Committee.Footnote 196

The Commission clearly has set higher demands for the members of its ethics committee. The requirements for becoming a member of the ‘Independent Ethical Committee’ (IEC) are “competence, experience, independence and professional qualities”, in addition to “an impeccable record of professional behaviour as well as experience in high-level functions in European, national or international institutions”; moreover, they have to sign a declaration on the absence of conflicts of interest.Footnote 197 The IEC shall advise the EC on “any ethical question” related to the EC CoC and provide general recommendations to the Commission on ethical issues in this regard.Footnote 198 Unlike the EP’s committee, the IEC can also include a “dissenting point of view” in its opinion.Footnote 199 In case of the EC and a possible conflict of interest, it is not a member (as in case of the EP), but the EC president, who can consult the IEC,Footnote 200 in a similar way as in cases of post term of office activities,Footnote 201 with the possibility to make public the IEC opinion.Footnote 202

3.3.2.2 Rules on Actors

As the EC nowadays often relies on outside expertise, rules on experts play an important role for ethical lobbying and can be positioned at the interface of targets and actors of lobbying. In fact, nowadays, it is a huge challenge to determine if in the context of decision-making, information is provided from a true expert, or from a ‘disguised lobbyist’. That is why the EC has established horizontal rules on the creation and operation of EC expert groups, which strive for a balanced composition of expert groups and comprise rules on conflict of interest, in order to “ensure the highest level of integrity of experts”.Footnote 203

The EP and the EC have set up a transparency register and a code of conduct for lobbyists, which, unfortunately, is only voluntary.Footnote 204, Footnote 205 The European Council and the Council of the EU have been invited to join the register, but have not done so far. This code of conduct is more concrete and foresees 14 quite detailed obligations for lobbyists, addressing lobbyists’ behaviour with regard to the EU institutions, their members, officials and other staff. It also entails transparency, operates less based on principles for ethical behaviour, and just mentions ‘honesty’ in the context of how information or decisions are obtained.

3.3.2.3 Conclusion

The overall approach in the context of decision-making is not one as we have seen it so far, i.e. referring to terms of ethics and morality. Rather, the relevant documents refer to certain principles, which are important to attain the same objective, that is to say ethical behaviour of either side, of both actors and targets of lobbying, as well as of ‘true’ experts. One key principle is also to avoid a situation of an actual or potential conflict of interest. Other principles comprise accountability, dignity, diligence, discretion, disinterest, honesty, impartiality, independence, integrity, loyalty, objectivity, openness, responsibility, and transparency. These principles (among which especially transparency) are of utmost importance to (re-)gain citizens’ trust. Intransparent decision-making as well as unethical behaviour will further widen the gap between the EU and its citizens. The already mentioned CETA agreement was a clear example of decreasing trust by not providing sufficient transparency. The Commission seemed to have learned from this example, as the Brexit negotiations are more open and documents more easily accessible.

These principles have to apply both during, and partially also after holding a certain office. Moreover, these substantive rules have to be accompanied by procedural rules, as is the case for the two committees of the EP and the EC. These committees not only play an important role in a concrete situation, but also have an important preventive function. Comparing these two committees, the EC’s IEC is clearly more ambitious with regard to the requirements of becoming a member, and allows for dissenting opinions, where an opinion is not adopted unanimously. Beside this, every ethics or expert committee ideally should strive for a balanced composition of its qualified members. With regard to the legal quality of these documents, we have seen both examples of hard law (e.g. the regulation on EU staff), as well as soft-law documents.

3.3.3 Ethics and Morality in EU Secondary (and Tertiary) Law

Following the vertical hierarchy of EU law, we now turn to EU secondary law, mainly enacted by the EP and the Council, as well as some examples of tertiary EU law, enacted based on the former. Not surprisingly due to the number of EU legal documents in this field, also the largest number of documents referring to ethics and/or morality can be found here. As it has been mentioned in the introduction, the objective of this book is not to create an inventory of all the examples of EU law, which refer to ethics and/or morality. Hence, in the following, the essence of this research conducted in two waves will be presented by means of some noteworthy examples.Footnote 206

This chapter starts with some examples of consequences of unethical behaviour, remarks concerning the requirement of legal certainty (Sect. 3.3.3.1). This research was mainly conducted in English, also taking into account other languages. That is why in a next step, some language inconsistencies will be highlighted (Sect. 3.3.3.2), before turning to the main part of categorizing the way how ethics and morality are determined regarding their content in EU secondary (and tertiary) law (Sect. 3.3.3.3).

3.3.3.1 Consequences of Unethical Behaviour, as Well as Legal Certainty (Continued)

The consequences of (non-)compliance with ethics, if mentioned in an EU legal document, can be seen from various examples. EU rules on authorisation and supervision of genetically modified food and feed require, amongst others “a reasoned statement that the food does not give rise to ethical or religious concerns”.Footnote 207 In addition, the EU regulation on clinical trials requires prior authorisation, whereby a “clinical trial shall be subject to scientific and ethical review”.Footnote 208

Moreover, we can see the consequences of unethical behaviour in the context of Horizon 2020, where “[r]esearch and innovation activities supported by Horizon 2020 should respect fundamental ethical principles”.Footnote 209 A “proposal which contravenes ethical principles […] may be excluded from the evaluation, selection and award procedures at any time”Footnote 210; in addition the Commission “shall systematically carry out ethics reviews for proposals raising ethical issues”,Footnote 211 and the grant agreement has to acknowledge “the right of the Commission to carry out an ethics audit by independent experts”.Footnote 212 Based on what we have seen in the chapter on the CJEU’s case-law on stem cell patentability,Footnote 213 it is no surprise that “[t]he use, if any, of human stem cells, be they adult or embryonic, […] is subject to stringent ethics review”.Footnote 214

Although only soft-law, the ‘European Charter for Researchers’ states that “[r]esearchers need to be aware that they are accountable towards their employers, funders or other related public or private bodies as well as, on more ethical grounds, towards society as a whole.”Footnote 215 In the context of fishery, we find a responsibility for the “correct and appropriate use of the data with regard to scientific ethics”.Footnote 216

In cross-border healthcare, EU patient mobility rights are limited according to the corresponding directive insofar as these rights may not be used in a way which “undermin[es] the fundamental ethical choices of Member States”.Footnote 217 Nevertheless, which kind of medical, health, or related treatmentFootnote 218 should be qualified as unethical?Footnote 219 These are only some examples that raise a number of important questions: Is there a definition or at least a certain form of understanding as to what has to be understood by ‘ethical’?

As mentioned above, as part of EU’s common values,Footnote 220 the ‘the rule of law’,Footnote 221 according to the EC’s recent communication,Footnote 222 also entails legal certainty. According to the CJEU, this requires that “legislation must be clear and predictable for those who are subject to it”.Footnote 223 Thus, one might wonder, if EU legislation referring to ethics and morality is clear and predictable and “formulated with sufficient precision to enable the individual to regulate his or her conduct”,Footnote 224 or whether it remains undetermined in the end?

This might be less of a problem, if legal documents refer to “minor’s physical, mental, spiritual, moral and social development”,Footnote 225 the “physical, mental and moral integrity”Footnote 226 of victims of crime, or the “morals of young persons”.Footnote 227 In the other cases mentioned above, the missing determination of unethical behaviour can have important consequences.

However, before we turn to the determination of content, let us take a closer look at the different language versions of EU documents referring to ethics and morality.

3.3.3.2 Language Inconsistencies

In the context of a Union with 24 different languages,Footnote 228 it is important to follow a linguistically holisticFootnote 229 approach. As we have just seen, ethics and morality, in theory, have a different meaning and therefore it is astonishing that they are used differently in different language versions. What reads “[c]onsumers in the [EU] would […] find it morally unacceptable that their increased use of biofuels could have the effect of destroying biodiverse lands”Footnote 230 in the English version,Footnote 231 refers to ethics (“ethisch inakzeptabel”) in the German version.Footnote 232 However, as those terms are generally distinguished, we can assume that this wording is based on imprecise translation and without further significance.

The same might hold true for the case of the already mentioned Directive Biotech,Footnote 233 which refers to the “ethical or moral principles recognised in a [sic!] Member State”,Footnote 234 whereas the German version uses the plural (“in den Mitgliedstaaten”).Footnote 235 As mentioned above in the context of human dignity, the number of MS sharing a certain conception can play an important role in case of authorities of a MS issuing a restrictive measure.Footnote 236

Although this will be the compelling solution, it might sound funny if only the English version of a code of conduct (relating to transactions in transferable securities) declares the code’s objective as “to establish standards of ethical behaviour on a Community-wide basis”, whereas the other language version examined only refer to loyal behaviour (for example, FR: “comportement loyalFootnote 237).Footnote 238

There are other examples of differences in translation which can be clustered into a less problematic category, where the term ‘ethical’ is just explicitly missing—but to some degree implicitly included—in another language version.

A first example refers to the degree to which substances can be tested on animals.Footnote 239 Here, only the German version refers to ethics,Footnote 240 whereas a similar idea is worded in different ways in English (“can humanely be allowed” similarly in ES), and the French (and IT) version referring to the degree of pain suffered by the animal (FR: “sans que cela fasse trop souffrir l’animal”).

A second example refers to doping, where the use of drugs in sport is denounced as “unsporting behaviour” in the English version, whereas all the other examined versions refer to the ethics of the sport (for example, ES: “contrario a la ética deportiva”).Footnote 241 Therefore, in both cases, the result might be the same, but the wording is different.

The same is true, if the term code of conduct (“Verhaltenskodex”) is used in one version (DE), whereas the other languages examined use the term code of ethics, and so on.Footnote 242 In a similar way, concerning ethical rules of a professional nature, one has to be aware of the fact that often professional rulesFootnote 243 in one language version (DE: “standesrechtlichen Regeln”) correspond to “rules of professional ethics” in other versions.Footnote 244

To sum it up, we can say that the general EU rule to take into account not only one language version of course also helps in case of the language inconsistencies in our context. However, in case of fundamental concepts like ‘ethics’ or ‘morality’, more “clarity and consistency”Footnote 245 would be desirable. Still, it can also rest unclear if the language versions that are ‘united in diversity’ are due to imprecise translations (for example, somewhere in a very comprehensive annex), or are the result of debates on principles.

3.3.3.3 Status Quo of Ethics and Morality

In EU primary law, we have seen ‘morality’ used as an umbrella to protect MS from EU interference in sensitive fields.Footnote 246 We can find a similar [1.] ‘protection shield’-approach in EU secondary law. As we have already seen in the context of Horizon 2020, the use of human stem cells is “subject to stringent ethics review”; this provision continues by stating that “[n]o project involving the use of human embryonic stem cells should be funded that does not obtain the necessary approvals from the Member States”.Footnote 247

The wording is even stronger in case of genetically modified food and organisms, where reference is made to “competence [sic] of Member States as regards ethical issues.”Footnote 248

The example of EU patient mobility has already been mentioned in terms of consequences of unethical behaviour. According to this directive, patients’ rights are limited insofar as these rights may not be used in a way which “undermin[es] the fundamental ethical choices of Member States”.Footnote 249 This reference to the term ‘ethics’ in this EU legal document is clearly motivated by the fear that a broad interpretation of the term “health services” could entitle EU citizens to use certain sensitive health services abroad.Footnote 250 Thus, ethics, again, serves as a protection shield against EU interference.

Moreover, we have also already seen the example of Directive Biotech, which, amongst others, excludes the patentability of “uses of human embryos for industrial or commercial purposes”.Footnote 251 The TRIPs Agreement foresees the possibility to exclude inventions from patentability, if they are against ordre public or morality.Footnote 252 When making use of this possibility, the directive makes clear that “ordre public and morality correspond in particular to ethical or moral principles recognised in a Member State”Footnote 253; hence, not at EU level. Further examples of referring to the national level for the determination of ethics can be found in the field of research.Footnote 254

After this category of ethics being used as a ‘protection shield’, we find another category, where ethics (or moralityFootnote 255) is used as [2.] a supportive argument for a certain legal solution. Here, it is less of a problem, if the content of ethics is not determined, as the legal solution itself might fulfil the requirements of legal certainty. This is the case for the statement that consumers in the EU would “find it morally unacceptable that their increased use of biofuels could have the effect of destroying biodiverse lands”,Footnote 256 or that “[c]onsumers’ choices can be influenced by, inter alia, health, economic, environmental, social and ethical considerations”.Footnote 257 In another example, the killing of seals is qualified as morally problematic as such, beside commercial killing being qualified as more problematic than traditional hunting by Inuit.Footnote 258

In context of ‘novel food’, we find a supportive argument to contribute to animal welfare and ethics: “[…] tests on animals should be replaced, reduced or refined. Therefore, […] duplication of animal testing should be avoided, where possible. Pursuing this goal could reduce possible animal welfare and ethical concerns with regard to novel food applications”.Footnote 259

Apart from ethics used as a supportive argument, we can further identify references in order to create [3.] a parallel ethical assessment beside the legal one. In this category, we can identify coexistence of law and ethics (that is to say, a parallel system), with Directive Biotech stating that “substantive patent law cannot serve to replace or render superfluous […] compliance with certain ethical standards”Footnote 260 and that “ethical or moral principles supplement the standard legal examinations under patent law”.Footnote 261 The same holds true in the field of protection of the EUs financial interests, where the definition of ‘professional misconduct’ “means violation of laws or regulations or of ethical standards of the profession to which the person belongs.Footnote 262

In the field of transferable securities, we find a noteworthy statement of the European Commission concerning the relationship of EU harmonization and ethics. “This code of conduct, to be issued in the form of a Commission recommendation, must be seen separately from the Commission’s other harmonization work in this sector […] because the ethical approach has been given priority over the legislative approach”.Footnote 263

A similar parallelism can be found in case of staff responsibility (of the EU Institute for Security Studies): “Employees shall abstain from any public action or statement or publication if such action, statement or publication is incompatible with the duties or obligations of an international civil servant or liable to involve the moral or material responsibility of the Institute.”Footnote 264

In addition to the parallelism of law and ethics, a similar relation can be addressed between science and ethics. In the context of Registration, Evaluation, Authorisation and Restriction of Chemicals (REACH), we find several references to the requirement of being both “scientifically and ethically justified”.Footnote 265, Footnote 266

These parallel situations are extended to a more holistic view in case of the EC proposal on health technology assessment (HTA), which refers to economic, medical, organisational, social, legal and ethical issues.Footnote 267

After ethics only serving as a ‘protection shield’, or being used as a ‘supportive argument’, we have now seen ethics in terms of a parallel assessment of legal as well as ethical requirements. Already the last category requires a substantive determination, of what is meant by (un-)ethical behaviour. This leads us to our next (and very important) category, of [4.] ethics being determined by ‘ethics committees’. There are committees, which focus exclusively on ethics, or others, where ethics is one of the aspects to be covered.Footnote 268 These committees can be installed either at [a.] EU or at [b.] national level and can take various forms. The underlying idea of all these committees is to outsource this ethical assessment, in order to achieve independent, objective and good quality opinions.

However, there are also examples where the ECFootnote 269 itself is tasked with the assessment at [4.a.] EU level. In Horizon 2020 the EC “shall systematically carry out ethics reviews for proposals raising ethical issues” by verifying “the respect of ethical principles and legislation”.Footnote 270 From a procedural perspective, this “process of the ethics review [has to be] as transparent as possible and […] carried out in a timely manner”.Footnote 271 The “grant agreement shall, where appropriate, contain provisions ensuring the respect of ethical principles, including the establishment of an independent ethics board and the right of the Commission to carry out an ethics audit by independent experts”.Footnote 272, Footnote 273

Due to its importance for our topic, the already mentioned EGE will be covered in a distinct chapter.Footnote 274 However, it has also been tasked by different legal documents with ethical assessments. One year after the EGE’s establishment in 1997, Directive Biotech provided that the EGE “evaluates all [sic!] ethical aspects of biotechnology”.Footnote 275 In the field of GMOs, the already mentioned Directive on the deliberate release into the environment,Footnote 276 provides that “the Commission shall, on its own initiative or at the request of the [EP] or the Council, consult any committee it has created with a view to obtaining its advice on the ethical implications of biotechnology, such as [EGE], on ethical issues of a general nature”.Footnote 277 Such consultation has to be “conducted under clear rules of openness, transparency and public accessibility”.Footnote 278 Always keeping in mind the fact that EGEs opinions are not legally binding, the wording in ‘Regulation GM food’ is alleviated, as the “Commission, on its own initiative or at the request of a Member State, may consult [EGE] or any other appropriate body”.Footnote 279 Not as regards the procedure (consultation), but to the output, it is stated that the opinions have to be made “available to the public”.Footnote 280

Apart from the EGE, there are several other institutional ethics committees, notably in the financial field. The European Investment Bank (EIB) follows a combined institutional and substantive approach, by having established an ‘Ethics and Compliance Committee’, which “shall rule on any potential conflict of interest” based on legal—not ethical—provisions.Footnote 281 Recently, the EIB has strengthened the role of this Committee “by introducing the possibility for this Committee to provide opinions on any ethical matter concerning a member of the Management Committee or of the Board of Directors”.Footnote 282 In addition, the European Central Bank (ECB) follows a combined approach for the TARGET2-Securities Board, consisting of a code of conductFootnote 283 and an ‘Ethics Officer’.Footnote 284 Members can contact the Ethics Officer in order to seek advice on an ad hoc basis.Footnote 285 The ECBFootnote 286 itself has established an ‘Ethics Committee’, due to the “increased level of public awareness and scrutiny [which] requires the ECB to have in place, and strictly adhere to, state-of-the-art ethics rules in order to safeguard the ECB’s integrity and avoid reputational risks”Footnote 287; it shall provide advice on questions of ethics based on individual requests.Footnote 288

Finally, in a similar way as the EGE advises the EC, the ‘European Data Protection Supervisor’ has appointed an ‘Ethics Advisory Group’ as an “external advisory group on the ethical dimensions of data protection”.Footnote 289 One reason for the establishment of this Body is technological advancement (big data computing and machine learning), which allows for the collection and usage of personal data “in increasingly opaque and complex ways, thus posing significant threats to privacy and human dignity”.Footnote 290

Apart from ethics committees at EU level, there are also examples of ethics committees at [4.b.] national level.

A combined approach of both EU (the role of the EC has already been described) and national ethical scrutiny can be found in Horizon 2020. There participants are not only obliged to “comply with national legislation, regulations and ethical rules in the countries where the action will be carried out”, but also “[w]here appropriate, [to] seek the approval of the relevant national or local ethics committees prior to the start of the action”.Footnote 291

Also in the field of the research fund for coal and steel, participants shall, where appropriate, “seek the approval of the relevant national or local ethics committees prior to the start of the action”.Footnote 292

It is again Directive GMOs, which states “Member States should be able to consult any committee they have established with a view to obtaining advice on the ethical implications of biotechnology”.Footnote 293 This statement stands beside the above-mentioned possibility of the EC, to consult the EGE “on ethical issues of a general nature”.Footnote 294 Evaluation by and consultation with national or local ethics committees is also foreseen for nanosciences and nanotechnologies research,Footnote 295 or in the case of ionizing radiation.Footnote 296

In the field of ‘clinical trials’,Footnote 297 ‘medical devices’Footnote 298 and ‘in vitro diagnostic medical devices’,Footnote 299 the three corresponding regulations all operate based on the same following definition of an ethics committee. “‘Ethics committee’ means an independent body established in a Member State in accordance with the law of that Member State and empowered to give opinions for the purposes of this Regulation, taking into account the views of laypersons, in particular patients or patients’ organisations”.Footnote 300 The ethical review performed by this national ethics committee is a requirement for prior authorisation, where a “clinical trial shall be subject to scientific and ethical review”Footnote 301; similar rules apply for the two other examples mentioned above.Footnote 302

Hence, as we have seen, ethics committees cannot only issue opinions on request or on their own initiative (for example, EGE), but can also play a decisive role in authorization procedures, not only for research grants, but also for manufacturing processes.

One task of ethics committees can also be to issue codes of conduct. Codes of conduct have the clear advantage that they are more detailed than just a general reference to ethical standards. These [5.] codes of conduct can be located both at [a.] EU or at [b.] national level.Footnote 303

At [5.a.] EU level we find the already mentioned “Code of Conduct for responsible nanosciences and nanotechnologies research”.Footnote 304 This code is quite detailed, comprising, amongst others, the principles of comprehensibility, respect of fundamental rights, the well-being of individuals and society, sustainability, the precautionary principle, inclusiveness (openness, transparency, and access to information), excellence, innovation, and accountability.Footnote 305 Hence, ethics is only part of the general principles mentioned therein.

In the case of ‘Directive Services’, we find a provision, which encourages “the setting up of codes of conduct, in particular, by professional bodies, organisations and associations at [EU] level”. Similar to the case of the example of nanosciences, this code of conduct is also not only about (professional) ethics.Footnote 306

Again at EU level, we find a non-binding recommendation, the already mentioned European Charter for Researchers, which, apart from referring to recognized ethical principles and so forth, also requires researchers to “adhere to […] ethical standards as documented in the different national, sectoral or institutional codes of ethics”.Footnote 307 It therefore does not create a code of conduct, but just refers to existing ones, also [5.b.] at national level.

Besides examples of non-binding recommendations, we also find an obligation for the MS regarding the transposition of EU directive against child pornography, according to which MS have to undertake preventive action “such as the drawing up and reinforcement of a code of conduct and self-regulatory mechanisms in the tourism industry, the setting-up of a code of ethics” and so forth.Footnote 308 Although the transposition of the directive into national law is binding in itself, thus the MS enjoy some flexibility as regards the form and methods of achieving this goal.

After ethics committees and codes of conduct, the substance of a reference to ethics can also be determined via references to [6.] other (international) documents.

In the context of the already mentioned three related examples of ‘clinical trials’,Footnote 309 ‘medical devices’Footnote 310 and ‘in vitro diagnostic medical devices’,Footnote 311 reference is made to “the most recent version of the World Medical Association Declaration of Helsinki on Ethical Principles for Medical Research Involving Human Subjects”.Footnote 312 This Helsinki DeclarationFootnote 313 has the advantage not only of having been elaborated at a ‘worldwide’ basis, but also of providing relatively detailed rules as regards ethical behaviour. Of course, it has to be acknowledged that EU law can only refer to such detailed guidelines if they exist and have been elaborated by an acknowledged body in the relevant field.Footnote 314

‘Regulation in vitro medical devices’ replaces the previous directive in this field, which for ethical requirements in the context of the removal, collection and use of tissues, cells and substances of human origin, has referred to the Council of Europe’s Oviedo convention.Footnote 315, Footnote 316

It is also worth mentioning the example of the directive on statutory audits, which requires adherence to “highest ethical standards”.Footnote 317 In this context, it is the Commission’s task to “adopt implementing measures on professional ethics as minimum standards [and when] doing so, it might consider the principles contained in the International Federation of Accountants (IFAC) Code of Ethics”.Footnote 318 Thus, the Commission is invited to consider this international code.

Finally, yet importantly, there is also one example, where in the context of biocidal products reference is made to “internationally accepted ethical standards”, without further guidance of how these standards are defined.Footnote 319

After ethics committees, codes of conduct, and the determination via references to other (international) documents, we finally come to a category, where some information concerning the content or understanding of ethics can be found [7.] in the relevant legal document itself.

In the field of statutory audit, when mentioning “ethical and independence requirements”, etc., the relevant provision on quality assurance of this regulation refers both to other chapters of the same regulation (as well as to another legal documentFootnote 320).Footnote 321

Another example of determination of content in the relevant legal document itself can be found in the field of mining. While “ethical mining” is not explicitly defined, a systematic interpretation of the whole directive on supply chain due diligence obligations clearly refers to the affected region (“in particular in the African Great Lakes Region”), to the goods of import in question (gold, etc.), as well as the reasons of concern (conflicts, child labour, sexual violence, the disappearance of people, etc.). All this exhibits why the mining of these goods in these circumstances is deemed wrong.Footnote 322

In the context of placing of proprietary medicinal products on the market, we find an example of a clear statement what is seen as unethical and what should be the consequences. “Since a full placebo comparison will not often be feasible or ethically acceptable in convulsive epilepsy, it is important in the later phases of evaluation to carry out controlled (randomized) clinical trials […]”.Footnote 323

In addition, in the field of medicinal products for human use we find some thoughts on the treatment of control groups against the background of ethical considerations. “[T]hus it may, in some instances, be more pertinent to compare the efficacy of a new medicinal product with that of an established medicinal product of proven therapeutic value rather than with the effect of a placebo”.Footnote 324 The same directive also exempts applicants from certain documentation if “it would be contrary to generally accepted principles of medical ethics to collect such information”.Footnote 325

In Horizon 2020 actions, falling within the scope of ‘Regulation participation Horizon 2020’ should “be in conformity […] with ethical principles, which include avoiding any breach of research integrity”.Footnote 326 In addition, Art 19 (entitled “Ethical principles”) of ‘Regulation establishing Horizon 2020’, after stipulating that “[a]ll the research and innovation activities carried out under Horizon 2020 shall comply with ethical principles [and human rights]”, excludes the following fields of research from funding: “human cloning for reproductive purposes”, “genetic heritage of human beings”, as well as “research activities intended to create human embryos solely for the purpose of research or for the purpose of stem cell procurement, including by means of somatic cell nuclear transfer”.Footnote 327 This can be seen as a European consensus with regard to bioethics, although one could argue that this provision is ‘only’ about funding and not about the legality of these activities.

Although this book is based on a broad understanding of bioethics, the examples mentioned so far always referred to humans. Nonetheless, there are also examples where the beneficiaries of ethical or moral principles are not humans, but animals, plants or the environment.Footnote 328 Especially animals are protected by ethical principles in different fields.

Bearing some resemblance to human dignity, the directive on the protection of animals used for scientific purposes asserts that animals “have an intrinsic value which must be respected”.Footnote 329 As a practical consequence arising from this approach, “animals should always be treated as sentient creatures and their use in procedures should be restricted to areas which may ultimately benefit human or animal health, or the environment”, and their use “for scientific or educational purposes should therefore only be considered where a non-animal alternative is unavailable”.Footnote 330 This directive provides even more detailed statements with respect to the practical consequences of the ‘intrinsic value’ of animals, as there are restrictions for the use of non-human primates.Footnote 331 Due to ethical considerations, the directive also sets a maximum threshold of permissible pain and therefore prohibits “the performance of procedures that result in severe pain, suffering or distress, which is likely to be long-lasting and cannot be ameliorated”.Footnote 332

Apart from this directive, ethical considerations concerning animals are also the reason why mass slaughtering has been declared as being, amongst other things, “ethically questionable”,Footnote 333 or, why there can even be “an ethical duty to kill productive animals which are in severe pain where there is no economically viable way to alleviate such pain”.Footnote 334

After a mere declaration annexed to the Maastricht TreatyFootnote 335 and a protocol annexed to the Amsterdam Treaty,Footnote 336 Art 13 TFEU now entails a horizontal clause according to which both the EU and the MS shall “pay full regard to the welfare requirements of animals”, because animals are “sentient beings”.Footnote 337 In Horizon 2020, this Art 13 TFEU is addressed in the context of respect for “fundamental ethical principles” with the practical consequence that “the use of animals in research and testing should be reduced, with a view ultimately to replacing their use”.Footnote 338

Leaving the field of bioethics, the already mentioned directive on statutory audits provides another example pertaining to this category where some understandings of the practical consequences of ethics are provided. After stating that statutory auditors should adhere to “the highest ethical standards”, the directive provides that they should be “subject to professional ethics, covering at least their public-interest function, their integrity and objectivity and their professional competence and due care”Footnote 339; further details have to be implemented by the MS.Footnote 340

In the following example, ethics is not determined by the EU, MS and so forth on a collective basis, but by a single business entity. According to the Regulation on European social entrepreneurship funds, so called “[q]ualifying social entrepreneurship funds should invest in a manner consistent with their ethical investment strategy, for instance they should not undertake investments that finance the weapons industry, that risk breaches of human rights or that entail electronic waste-dumping”.Footnote 341

The combined approach of the ECB, that is to say an Ethics Officer plus principles (such as avoidance of conflicts of interest, confidentiality, transparency and openness, etc.) contained in a code of conduct, has already been mentioned.Footnote 342 Likewise, the European Anti-Fraud Office (OLAF) merely follows a substantive approach for their Supervisory Committee. Art 4, entitled ‘ethics’, requires the members to act independently, neither seeking nor taking instructions from others, not to deal with matters where they have a personal interest, to demonstrate confidentiality, and to adhere to an obligation of notification if any such situation occurs.Footnote 343

In an indirect way, we can also add examples, where reference is made to notions that have a pre-determined meaning from another field, such as public morality,Footnote 344 which has been shaped by the CJEU,Footnote 345 or moral hazard,Footnote 346 as a notion of microeconomics.Footnote 347 The example of moral hazard also derives from the financial crisis, where the Commission’s banking communication refers several times to ‘moral hazard’.Footnote 348 In a similar way as for international agreements, moral hazard is addressed in the context of burden sharing.Footnote 349 This concept can be explained by referring to a situation caused by the immoral behaviour of a single body that is dangerous for a bigger group (society). Most people would agree to qualify the risky behaviour of certain banks to the detriment of taxpayers (whereas bonuses would still be paid, maybe also with the help of those taxpayers’ subsidies) as immoral.Footnote 350

After having seen determination by ethics committees, codes of conduct, references to international documents and further information provided by EU law itself, we finally arrive at the last category, that is, EU law, where ethics [8.] remains undetermined.

The example of patient mobility has already been mentioned in the category of ‘non-interference’, where patients do not have a right to cross-border healthcare because the directive shall not “undermine the fundamental ethical choices of Member States”.Footnote 351 This undetermined provision can have a significant impact on patients seeking cross-border healthcare. In fact, some MS feared the application of this directive to sensitive issues “like euthanasia, DNA-testing or IVF”.Footnote 352 Contrary to what one would expect, it was not the Council of Ministers but the EP that at a very early stage of the legislative procedure, proposed amendments making clear that “[n]o provision of this Directive should be interpreted in such a way as to undermine the fundamental ethical choices of Member States”.Footnote 353 This was strengthened by emphasizing that “[n]otwithstanding those common values it is accepted that Member States take different decisions on ethical grounds as regards the availability of certain treatments and the concrete access conditions [and that this] Directive is without prejudice to ethical diversity”.Footnote 354 The question remains, as to whether this provision has to be interpreted in a narrow sense, as it requires ‘fundamental’ ethical choices. Moreover, only the legal materials help to shed more light on the void of this undetermined concept.

While this example refers to the MS to determine ethics in this regard, the following examples provide no information whatsoever on the understanding behind the term of ethics used in those documents, of both a binding and non-binding nature.

One example of a binding nature is about food law, where it has been acknowledged that scientific risk assessment alone might not provide all necessary information for, but where also “societal, economic, traditional, ethical and environmental factors” have to be considered.Footnote 355 The reference to ethics might be very general (one factor amongst others to be taken into account), but does not mitigate the fact that the concept of ethics remains undetermined.

Other examples of non-determined references to ethics are as followsFootnote 356: “scientific ethics”,Footnote 357relevant ethical principles”,Footnote 358business ethics standards”,Footnote 359professional ethics”,Footnote 360 “ethical principles, which include avoiding any breach of research integrity”,Footnote 361 or “environmental and ethical considerations”.Footnote 362 In another reference to “ethical or environmental reasons”,Footnote 363 this regulation further refers to another document,Footnote 364 but without further clarification on the determination of ethics. In addition, the new General Data Protection Regulation (GDPR)Footnote 365 refers to “recognised ethical standards for scientific research”,Footnote 366 as well as “ethics for regulated professions”.Footnote 367 Besides ethics, in the field of trademark, we find a reference to “accepted principles of morality” in both the corresponding EU directiveFootnote 368 and regulation.Footnote 369, Footnote 370

Another example refers to the European Council,Footnote 371 which expressed in its Stockholm presidency conclusions from 2001 the need to “strengthen the European biotechnology sector’s competitiveness”, while ensuring that this is “consistent with common fundamental values and ethical principles”.Footnote 372 Some could take the view that there is no need for a (purely) political document to provide detailed statements, nonetheless, also in this case we lack further guidance as to the understanding of ethics.

The Council (of Ministers) resolution concerning fundamental health policy choices is another example of a non-binding document, taking ‘only’ note of some topics, “which warrant joint consideration”, such as “revision of medical studies syllabuses in order to incorporate the relevant economic, legal, ethical and social aspects necessary to ensure that practitioners dispense adequate health care”.Footnote 373 This example is comparable to the one of port State inspectors, where the content of ethics as part of a training programme is not determined.Footnote 374 Although there is no further information on what constitutes an ethical syllabus, the MS competenceFootnote 375 for both education and health might be the legally based reason why this non-legal term should be defined by the MS.

The same idea can hold true for other health related (non-binding) documents in the context of cancer screeningFootnote 376 and hereditary illnessesFootnote 377 on the one hand, and for lifelong learningFootnote 378 on the other.

Within the shared competence of the internal market,Footnote 379 we find one example of a task in the public interest, which is about “doctors or veterinary bodies ensuring that their members conform to ethical or sanitary rules”.Footnote 380 This example adds up to our list of undetermined references to ethics, where a possible solution could be to see those bodies in charge of defining those ethical rules.

3.3.3.4 Conclusion

Unethical behaviour can have an impact, both when seeking an authorisation or in the context of research funding. Given the amount of documents that have to be published in the 24 official languages, the inconsistencies identified in this chapter are a minor issue. Nevertheless, it makes a difference whether a document refers to ethics or morality (Directive greenhouse gas emissions), or to ethical or moral principles recognised in one or more MS (Directive Biotech).

Beneficiaries have mainly been humans, however, also animals are protected due to arguments reminding us of ‘human dignity’. In order to achieve ethical behaviour, training plays an important role. Therefore, it is no surprise, that also in case of ‘EU reference centres for animal welfare’ we find the requirement of “suitably qualified staff with adequate training […] in ethical issues related to animals”.Footnote 381 In a completely different field, the importance of “[i]ncreased awareness of […] ethical issues among students and their teachers”Footnote 382 is also emphasized.

Concerning humans, special groups that have not been mentioned so far, are incapacitated subjectsFootnote 383 in respect of clinical trials on medicinal products for human use, as well as children,Footnote 384 where specific ethical concerns might arise and should be addressed.

The numerous EU documents referring to ethics and morality can be clustered in the above-mentioned, inductively developed, categories. It has to be emphasized that some examples are overlapping and, hence, could fall in various categories.

The category of ethics serving as a [1.] ‘protection shield’ clearly is not a very ambitious approach. Using ethics as [2.] a supportive argument is clearly less of a problem, as the legal situation (which it defends) should be able to be self-standing. It is also less of a problem, when ethics is determined by [4.] an ethics committee or via a [5.] code of conduct, in either category either at EU or at national level. Sufficient clarification with regard to the content of references to ethics can also be guaranteed via references to [6.] other (international) documents, such as the Helsinki declaration or the Oviedo convention, or if further information [7.] is provided in the relevant EU document itself.

From the perspective of legal certainty, a [3.] parallel ethical and legal assessment (e.g. Directive Biotech), can be problematic if the criteria for this ethical assessment are not clearly stated, which finally leads us to category [8.], where ethics remains undetermined.

The examples we have seen in the category of ethics committees clearly displays that ethics plays a role in sensitive fields: this is the case for ‘science and new technologies’ (EGE), in the financial field, in data protection and digitalization, or in the health sector (e.g. clinical trials, medical devices and in vitro diagnostic medical devices). Further recent examples of sensitive fields referring to ethics can be found in the context of ‘health in the digital society’,Footnote 385 ‘artificial intelligence’,Footnote 386 ‘robotics’,Footnote 387 and ‘digital ethics’.Footnote 388

3.3.4 The Ethical Spirit in Implementing EU Directives

Some of these documents of EU secondary and tertiary law are EU directives, which need to be implemented into national law.Footnote 389 The national provisions implementing these directives in the various MS, are well documented in EUR-Lex, respectively in the relevant national legal databases.Footnote 390

This chapter is related to objective 2, i.e. the question how selected MS have dealt with ethics and morality in the way they have implemented these directives. More precisely: how have these countries implemented the selected EU-Directives regarding ethics and/or morality into national law? In implementing these directives, have they also referred to ethics and/or morality, respectively to similar concepts and related terms, such as EU values and human or fundamental rights? Finally, can we conclude on an ‘ethicalization’ of national law via EU law?

The countries examined are, in alphabetical order, Austria, the Czech Republic, France, Germany, Ireland, Italy, Slovakia, Spain, and the United Kingdom. While not all 28 Member States could be covered, this chapter covers the biggest Member States, plus taking into account different legal systems (common law, e.g. in the UK and Ireland; civil law system), old and new Member States, from Northern and Southern Europe, as well as from Western and Eastern Europe).

This chapter is based on a research project, which was conducted in two waves, based on a research design developed, as well as the project itself directed by the author, with several students involved. The first round in 2016 covered Austria and Germany,Footnote 391 France,Footnote 392 Ireland and the United Kingdom,Footnote 393 as well as Spain,Footnote 394 the second round, in 2017, ItalyFootnote 395 as well as the Czech Republic and Slovakia.Footnote 396 Space precludes a discussion of the numerous findings of these two rounds. Therefore, the most important results are summarized in the following.

The 28 directives identified for this project mainly pertain to the field of health (see Table 3.2), addressing issues of bioethics. Therefore, the majority of references to these concepts can be found in the field of health, mainly referring to ‘ethics’, less to ‘morality’.

Table 3.2 EU ‘ethics directives’, time frame and areas

As can also be seen from Fig. 3.2, the majority of these 28 directives analysed have been adopted since 2001, which has to be seen against the background of the creation of the EGE in December 1997.Footnote 397 While the first directives pertain to the field of health (which, in total, comprises more than half of these directives), since 2001 we can observe an expansion also to other areas.

Fig. 3.2
figure 2

Source Pacey (2016, p. 38)

EU ‘ethics directives’, timeline and areas (total numbers).

These directives have been analysed with regard to the key terms of ‘ethics’, ‘morality’ and related terms. These terms plus the different areas, where they occur, can be seen below from Fig. 3.3. ‘Ethics’ and related terms occur most frequently, especially in the field of ‘health’, while ‘professional ethics’ pertains to the field of ‘employment’, as well as ‘accounting & finance’. This is followed by the concept of ‘integrity’, which primarily occurs in the area of ‘accounting & finance’. As mentioned above, the term of morality (primarily only in the field of ‘technology’) plays a minor role.

Fig. 3.3
figure 3

Source Pacey (2016, A11)

EU ‘ethics directives’, key terms in different areas (total numbers).

When taking a closer look at the term ‘ethics’ in its various breakdowns, one can see the following picture (see Fig. 3.4), which clearly exhibits, first of all, that the term ‘ethics committee’ prevails, and, second, that this term clearly pertains to the health field.

Fig. 3.4
figure 4

Source Sava (2017, 34 and A20)

Breakdown of ‘ethics’ in ‘ethics directives’ in different areas (percentage).

When, in a next step, we turn from these EU directives to the national level, the various findings of the national implementation measures (NIM) of the eight MS examined can be summarized as followsFootnote 398:

Although it might sound obvious, keywords in EU directives have only been implemented, when mentioned in those parts of a Directive which have to be implemented, i.e. articles, but not if only mentioned in the recitals of the preamble.Footnote 399 For instance, references to fundamental rights or the EU’s common values mainly occur in the preamble of directives, thus they play no major role in the NIM.

To make a long story short, there are mainly two reasons why one has to be cautious with over-stressing a quantitative approach.Footnote 400 First of all, the degree to which a country (e.g. France) refers to ethics and morality when implementing EU Directives is strongly linked to the pre-existing substantive (e.g. “les bonnes mœurs françaises”)Footnote 401 and procedural (e.g. since 1983: Comité Consultatif National d’Ethique, CCNE) approach to ethics and morality in this country. This might also explain the low ratio of NIM referring to keywords (e.g. 15.4%). Second, although a country like Spain has a high number of references to key terms in its NIM, this might be due to the pragmatic ‘copy-paste’ approach, which, beside the text of the directives, also includes copy-pasting recitals and annexes.Footnote 402 Thirdly, a large number of national provisions can implement one single directive, which can distort the validity of quantitative analyses.Footnote 403

Another interesting result could be identified by comparing the results of the different countries. The two waves of this research project revealed, that countries with comparable legal traditions also display similar results. That was true for Austria and Germany,Footnote 404 for Ireland and the UK,Footnote 405 as well as for the Czech Republic and Slovakia.Footnote 406, Footnote 407 The question of an ‘ethicalization’ of national law via these EU ‘ethics directives’ has to be answered in the sense of not playing a major role, as these legal traditions clearly have a higher impact. Again, we can identify an approach, which is not very ambitious, where MS mainly implement these ‘ethics elements’ of a directive, which are mandatory for them.

In a similar way as for the key terms identified in the directives, also the NIM mainly refer to ethics and especially ‘ethics committees’, primarily because of Directive clinical trials.Footnote 408 This was, for instance, the case in Italy, were 73% of all terms related to ethics, were about ‘ethics committees’ (‘comitato etico’),Footnote 409 or in France, with the highest number of references to ‘comité d’éthique’,Footnote 410 and the same for Austria and Germany.Footnote 411

Consequently, while some references to ethics, etc. were unavoidable in the sense that it was mandatory for the MS, we cannot observe a uniform ‘ethicalization’ via EU directives in these nine countries.