Skip to main content

Juggling the B-Ball: Being a Systems Practitioner

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Systems Practice: How to Act in a Climate-Change World
  • 1040 Accesses

Abstract

This chapter starts by offering an explanation about explanations. It then invites the reader to consider seriously the explanations offered about (i) the nature of explanations, (ii) the role and place of emotions, and (iii) embodied knowing. Four aspects of being a systems practitioner are then addressed. The first is being aware of the constraints and possibilities of the observer. The second is understanding understanding and knowing knowing. The third is learning, and the fourth is being ethical. The concept of social technologies is introduced as a means to appreciate how technology mediates, thus enhancing or constraining, the effective juggling of the B-ball; that is how we are when we are a systems practitioner.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 64.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 84.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    Following Maturana [27] I understand the social dynamics of explanations to be a key aspect of being human and which begins to be learnt in early childhood. Maturana says (ibid p. 148) that an ‘explanation is an answer to a question about the origin of some particular experience of the observer that is asked in such a way that it explicitly or implicitly demands an answer that satisfies the following two conditions: (i) the answer must consist in the proposition of a mechanism or process that, if it were allowed to operate, would give rise in the observer as a result of its operation the experience that she or he wanted to explain; (ii) the generative mechanism or process proposed as an answer must be accepted as doing what it claims to do by an observer, who could be the same person that proposes it, because it satisfies some other condition that he or she puts in his or her listening.’

  2. 2.

    I will say more about embodiment later in this chapter – at this stage it is worth noting that embodiment is a term I take from theoretical and practical concerns in a number of disciplines about embodied or embedded cognition, a position in cognitive science, for example, stating that intelligent behaviour emerges out of the interplay between brain, body and world (See http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Embodiment. Accessed 16th July 2009).

  3. 3.

    I am grateful to Peter Roberts for his original work on which this is based.

  4. 4.

    My reference to history makes it sound like colour perception is learned – and partly it is. We learn the names of nuances of wavelengths that are relevant in our culture. But there is also “relativistic colour coding” that means we see colour by ratios of stimulation of cones, not by wavelength of light. We don’t work the same way as the instruments we invent to record colour.

  5. 5.

    This may often involve developing and using different muscles, i.e. differences in our body.

  6. 6.

    We usually vilify other cosmologies as “myths” because we know better now.

  7. 7.

    See http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Philosophy_of_science: ‘most observations are theory-laden – that is, they depend in part on an underlying theory that is used to frame the observations. Observation involves perception as well as a cognitive process. That is, one does not make an observation passively, but is actively involved in distinguishing the thing being observed from surrounding sensory data. Therefore, observations depend on some underlying understanding of the way in which the world functions and that understanding may influence what is perceived, noticed or deemed worthy of consideration.’ (Accessed 25th January 2009).

  8. 8.

    And at the same time we have specified a domain (a framing) in which that particular split makes sense. This is probably much more significant than the particular split because people will discuss the boundary, but never realise they have already accepted the domain, or they will think they speak of the same split, but it won’t be the same if they have done it in different domains [3].

  9. 9.

    In systems theoretical terms the word ‘environment’, as “that which surrounds”, is the correct term but it has no relation to the so-called physical environment – it is an abstract or conceptual notion that only arises whenever a system of interest is distinguished by someone.

  10. 10.

    The concept circle is also brought forth in this action – but in every day life most of us have from an early age, as part of our tradition of understanding, the concept circle and thus when we distinguish circles in everyday life the boundary usually disappears from view. Mainly we only become aware of most borders when something is ambiguous.

  11. 11.

    This is not BAD, it is how we and language are constituted. We manage just fine, unless we fall into the trap of certainty. And knowing this is how we operate opens up the option for new perspectives that better fit our situation.

  12. 12.

    See von Foerster [49]; people assume Heisenberg’s uncertainty principle only pertains to elementary events but a more useful framing might be to say he invented it for that, but it has far wider application!

  13. 13.

    We would be so hampered in doing our daily tasks if ALL the time we had to think like this! Reflecting alters our path, but then for a while we just want to engage. It can be thought of as an ongoing dynamic between engaging and reflecting.

  14. 14.

    This phenomenon is likely to be of interest to systems educators – Pille Bunnell [4] in response to my observation says: “I wonder how much that is the approach to the explanation per se. Though I admit it takes me about 25 h of class time to build up to a point where no one becomes ‘angry’ though some (less than 10% of the class) will not accept this in the long term. Others do take it as a fundamental shift.”

  15. 15.

    By including this quote I want to make it clear that I am not interpreting it as “my right to believe whatever I like and declare that as knowledge” but because it offers a perspective that differs widely from the mainstream understanding of what most scientists do when they claim scientific knowledge.

  16. 16.

    I return to the issue of social technologies in Section 5.5.

  17. 17.

    The evidence for this set of claims can be found in the early work of Benjamin Whorf who found, for example, that ‘the strange grammar of Hopi gives rise to different modes of perceiving and conceiving’ (see Carroll [5, p. 17]).

  18. 18.

    Creole in this context means a blend or hybrid of English and the speakers original language.

  19. 19.

    But what is “information”? Is there such a thing at all? I claim it is not a thing, but an arising within – from the Latin roots ‘in formare’; for example, following Bateson, famous for the phrase ‘the difference that makes a difference’, information could be said to arise when someone distinguishes a difference in two domains. In this context information is an explanatory principle.

  20. 20.

    Finding an image to depict the concepts that I consider important has been a challenge – this figure owes much to a Michael Leunig cartoon for inspiration.

  21. 21.

    As I have outlined “making a distinction” is the basis of new experience but over time the act of making a distinction falls into the background as we discern a situation according to an accepted distinction. For example, if we have already distinguished “chair” we can sit on it, pick it up, invite someone else to sit in it… without having to distinguish it as a chair each time! The reason distinctions are so important is that once made they are taken for granted. This makes operational sense but when we are not aware that this is what we do we can end up in traps of our own making.

  22. 22.

    As outlined earlier, for simplicity these figures don’t show a key human dynamic, namely our conversations with other people, which of course greatly influence how our understanding develops, how we “learn”. The ‘real world’ situation too is an abstraction – we are never apart from or independent of such situations.

  23. 23.

    To explain a little further for those who are not British – prominent British leaders such as Winston Churchill often had or were photographed with a ‘British bulldog’ – a breed developed in Britain. This breed came to symbolise a form of British nationalism – if you were British – or a form of oppression if you were subject to British imperial rule. The Union flag itself is a flag generated as part of nation building from the flags of constituent UK nations – England, Scotland, Wales and Northern Ireland.

  24. 24.

    By choice von Foerster means enhancing the opportunity to consider the implications of acting one way or another. This does not happen if one is given rules. Rules preclude consideration of alternatives because the action is specified. Treated superficially the concepts espoused by von Foerster can be easily misunderstood, as seems to have been the case with the UK Labour Government who, when Tony Blair was PM, made much of ‘increased choice’, as in say the operation of the National Health Service. Simplistically they seem to have reduced the concept of choice to the provision of options in contexts that did not matter to patients – the choices that were offered were not choices that mattered to those who used the health service, i.e. the choices were not grounded in the circumstances of patient’s own lives. As Seddon observes [38, p. 15] ‘to say people have choice when they are in no position to make one is disingenuous.’

  25. 25.

    The distinction between systemic and systematic practice was addressed in Chapter 2; I also return to these distinctions at the end of Part II.

  26. 26.

    This applies only if we don’t remain in the default position of thinking there is no other. Usually people do not choose their position, they don’t even know they have one!

  27. 27.

    The action of adjusting or adapting to enable purposeful action amongst those with different understandings and interests.

  28. 28.

    Based at The Open University, UK.

  29. 29.

    As in something between, connected but not directly.

  30. 30.

    The word ‘artifact’ is revealing in this context. It can be understood as an ‘art-in-fact’ and thus raises questions about the nature of social facts – an epistemological divide suggests itself.

  31. 31.

    See http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/New_institutional_economics for more background (Accessed 24th April 2009).

  32. 32.

    I am not claiming that all action and thus practice is purposeful – very often the attribution of purpose, as with intention, arises in reflection, not as a precursor to what we do. In other words we do what we do and then seek a way of describing why. But we have also evolved a manner of living or conversing about ‘what is to be done’ of which rationality is but one facet. This book is based on my experience that enhancing the quality of talking about what might be done benefits the nature and quality of what is done – but I do not make a claim that in the moment we do what we claim we were going to do, or that we have even done what we claimed.

  33. 33.

    For example see the body of work by Don Ihde including Technics and Praxis [17]; Experimental Phenomenology: An Introduction [18]; Technology and the Lifeworld: From Garden to Earth [19]; Philosophy of Technology: An Introduction [20].

  34. 34.

    Those experienced in this sort of practice will understand that in similar situations some would prefer to act in the acceptance of a fiction that those presenting their ideas actually know what to do. Such an attitude is fostered in some of the main discourses on ‘leadership’.

  35. 35.

    Sometimes “I don’t know” can be an abrogation of responsibility but on other occasions it can entail the acceptance of a deeper responsibility. The consultants in this example presumably demonstrated the latter in their initial interview – and evidently followed through. It is easy to pretend to engage in a collaborative process or to follow a prescription for participation and not really engage deeply.

  36. 36.

    Patricia Shaw and I at one period discussed extensively our approaches to practice and found that we had quite profoundly different preferences. My own is to do much more planning or designing at an early stage after becoming as aware of the context as is possible. But then to be open to the unfolding circumstances in the practice situation and act in an emotion that is free to change, not one that tries to hold onto the plan or design. My argument for this form of practice is that it enhances one’s behavioural repertoire in the moment providing the practitioner with more variety and choices.

  37. 37.

    For a well-articulated critique see Checkland and Poulter [8, p. 148–153].

References

  1. http://www.braingle.com/brainteasers/teaser.php?id=26745;op=0;comm=1 (Accessed 3rd August 2009).

  2. Bunnell, P. (2003) Personal communication. Systems Ecologist, President of Lifeworks, Vancouver, British Columbia, June 2003.

    Google Scholar 

  3. Bunnell, P. (2008) Editor’s Foreward. The Origin of Humanness in the Biology of Love. In H.R. Maturana and G. Verden-Zoller (eds), The Origin of Humanness in the Biology of Love. Imprint Academic: Exeter.

    Google Scholar 

  4. Bunnell, P. (2009) Personal communication. Systems Ecologist, President of Lifeworks, Vancouver, British Columbia, June 2009.

    Google Scholar 

  5. Carroll, J.B. (Ed.) (1959) Language thought and reality. Selected writings of Benjamin Lee Whorf. MIT Press: New York.

    Google Scholar 

  6. Ceruti, M. (1994) Constraints and Possibilities. The evolution of knowledge and the knowledge of evolution. Gordon and Breach: New York.

    Google Scholar 

  7. Checkland, P.B. and Casar, A. (1986) Vickers’ concept of an appreciative system: a systemic account. Journal of Applied Systems Analysis 13, 3–17.

    Google Scholar 

  8. Checkland, P.B. and Poulter, J. (2006) Learning for Action: a Short Definitive Account of Soft Systems Methodology and its Use for Practitioners, Teachers and Students. Wiley: Chichester.

    Google Scholar 

  9. Clandinin, D.J. and Connelly, F.M. (1998) Personal experience methods. In N.K. Denzin and Y.S. Lincoln (Eds.), Collecting and Interpreting Qualitative Materials. Sage: London.

    Google Scholar 

  10. Evans, N. (2009) Dying words: Endangered languages and what they have to tell us. Wiley-Blackwell: Maldon, MA.

    Google Scholar 

  11. Fell, L. and Russell, D.B. (2000/2007) The human quest for understanding and agreement. In R.L. Ison and D.B. Russell (Eds.), Agricultural Extension and Rural Development: Breaking out of Traditions (pp. 32–51). Cambridge University Press: Cambridge.

    Google Scholar 

  12. Glanville, R. (1995a) A (cybernetic) musing: Control 1, Cybernetics & Human Knowing 3(1), 47–50.

    Google Scholar 

  13. Glanville, R. (1995b) A (cybernetic) musing: Control 2, Cybernetics & Human Knowing 3(2), 43–46.

    Google Scholar 

  14. Harré, R. (1983) Personal Being: A Theory for Individual Psychology. Basil Blackwell: Oxford.

    Google Scholar 

  15. Helme, M. (2002) Appreciating metaphor for participatory practice: constructivist inquiries in a children and young peoples justice organisation. PhD Thesis, Systems Discipline, The Open University: UK.

    Google Scholar 

  16. Høeg, P. (1994) Miss Smilla’s Feeling for Snow. Flamingo: London.

    Google Scholar 

  17. Ihde, D. (1979) Technics and Praxis. Reidel: Dordrecht.

    Google Scholar 

  18. Ihde, D. (1986) Experimental Phenomenology: An Introduction. Putnam: New York.

    Google Scholar 

  19. Ihde, D. (1990) Technology and the Lifeworld: From Garden to Earth. Indiana University Press: Bloomington, IN.

    Google Scholar 

  20. Ihde, D. (1993) Philosophy of Technology: An Introduction. Paragon: New York.

    Google Scholar 

  21. Lakoff, G. and Johnson, M. (1999) Philosophy in the Flesh: The Embodied Mind and Its Challenge to Western Thought. Basic Books: New York.

    Google Scholar 

  22. MacIntyre, A. (1981) After Virtue. Duckworth: London.

    Google Scholar 

  23. Mahoney, M. (1988) Constructive meta-theory 1: Basic features and historical foundations, International Journal of Personal Construct Psychology 1, 1–35.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  24. Maturana, H. and Varela F. (1987) The Tree of Knowledge: The biological roots of human understanding. New Science Library, Shambala Publications: Boston, MA.

    Google Scholar 

  25. Maturana, H. (1988) Reality: The search for objectivity or the quest for a compelling argument, Irish Journal of Psychology 9, 25–82.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  26. Maturana, H. (1996) Personal Communication. Professor Emeritus, University of Chile, 1996.

    Google Scholar 

  27. Maturana, H.R., Verden-Zöller, G., and Bunnell, P. (Ed.). (2008) The Origin of Humanness in the Biology of Love. Imprint Academic: Exeter.

    Google Scholar 

  28. Monaghan, P. (2009) Never mind the whales, save the languages. The Australian. Wednesday 24th June, 36.

    Google Scholar 

  29. North, D. (1990) Institutions, Institutional Change and Economic Performance. Cambridge University Press: Cambridge.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  30. Open University (2000) Managing complexity A systems approach, Course Code T306. The Open University: Milton Keynes.

    Google Scholar 

  31. Pert, C.B. (1997) Molecules of Emotion. The science of mind-body medicine. Simon & Schuster: New York.

    Google Scholar 

  32. Reyes, A. and Zarama, R. (1998) The process of embodying distinctions: a re-construction of the process of learning, Cybernetics & Human Knowing 5, 19–33.

    Google Scholar 

  33. Rorty, R. (1980) Philosophy and the Mirror of Nature. Basil Blackwell: Oxford.

    Google Scholar 

  34. Rosch, E. (1992) Cognitive psychology. In J.W. Hayward and F.J. Varela (Eds.), Gentle Bridges: Conversations with the Dalai Lama on the sciences of mind. Shambala Publications: Boston, MA.

    Google Scholar 

  35. Rose, C., Dade, P. and Scott, J. (2007) Research into Motivating Prospectors, Settlers and Pioneers to Change Behaviours that Affect Climate Emissions. http://www.campaignstrategy.org/articles/behaviourchange_climate.pdf (accessed 11 August 2009).

  36. Russell, D.B. and Ison, R.L. (2000) The research-development relationship in rural communities: an opportunity for contextual science. In R.L. Ison and D.B. Russell (Eds.), Agricultural Extension and Rural Development: Breaking out of Traditions (pp. 10–31). Cambridge University Press: Cambridge.

    Google Scholar 

  37. Russell, D.B. and Ison, R.L. (2007) The research-development relationship in rural communities: an opportunity for contextual science. In R.L. Ison and D.B. Russell (Eds.), Agricultural Extension and Rural Development: Breaking out of Knowledge Transfer Traditions (pp. 10–31). Cambridge University Press: Cambridge, UK.

    Google Scholar 

  38. Seddon, J. (2008) Systems Thinking in the Public Sector: the failure of the reform regime, and a manifesto for a better way. Triarchy Press: Axminster.

    Google Scholar 

  39. Shaw, P. (2002) Changing Conversations in Organizations. A Complexity Approach to Change. Routledge: London.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  40. Shotter, J. (1993) Conversational Realities: constructing life through language. Sage: London.

    Google Scholar 

  41. SLIM (2004) The role of conducive policies in fostering social learning for integrated management of water. Slim Policy Briefing No. 5. See http://slim.open.ac.uk. Accessed 31 July 2009.

  42. Varela, F. (1979) Principles of Biological Autonomy. North Holland: New York.

    Google Scholar 

  43. Vickers, G. (1965) The Art of Judgement: a study of policy making. Chapman and Hall: London.

    Google Scholar 

  44. Vickers, G. (1970) Freedom in a Rocking Boat: changing values in an unstable society. Penguin: Harmondsworth.

    Google Scholar 

  45. Vickers, G. (1983) Human Systems are Different. Harper and Row: London.

    Google Scholar 

  46. Vickers, J. (Ed.). (1991) Rethinking the Future: The Correspondence between Geoffrey Vickers and Adolf Lowe. Transaction Publishers: London.

    Google Scholar 

  47. von Foerster, H. (1984) Observing Systems. Systems Publications: Salinas, CA.

    Google Scholar 

  48. von Foerster, H. (1992) Ethics and second-order cybernetics, Cybernetics & Human Knowing 1, 9–19.

    Google Scholar 

  49. von Foerster, H. (1994) Foreword. In Ceruti, M. Constraints and Possibilities: The knowledge of evolution and the evolution of knowledge. Gordon and Breach: Lausanne.

    Google Scholar 

  50. von Foerster, H. and Poerkson, B. (2002) Understanding Systems. Conversations on Epistemology and Ethics. IFSR International Series on Systems Science and Engineering, Vol 17. Kluwer/Plenum: New York.

    MATH  Google Scholar 

  51. Wenger, E. (1998) Communities of Practice: Learning, meaning and identity. Cambridge University Press: Cambridge, UK.

    Google Scholar 

  52. Wittgenstein, L. (1981) Zettel. Basil Blackwell: Oxford.

    Google Scholar 

  53. Wittgenstein, L. (1999) Philosophical Investigations. Blackwell: Oxford.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2010 Springer-Verlag London

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Ison, R. (2010). Juggling the B-Ball: Being a Systems Practitioner. In: Systems Practice: How to Act in a Climate-Change World. Springer, London. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-1-84996-125-7_5

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-1-84996-125-7_5

  • Published:

  • Publisher Name: Springer, London

  • Print ISBN: 978-1-84996-124-0

  • Online ISBN: 978-1-84996-125-7

  • eBook Packages: Computer ScienceComputer Science (R0)

Publish with us

Policies and ethics