Skip to main content

Part of the book series: Studies in the History of Mathematics and Physical Sciences ((HISTORY,volume 8))

  • 952 Accesses

Abstract

David Hilbert once wrote that Zermelo’s Axiom of Choice was the axiom “most attacked up to the present in the mathematical literature...” [1926, 178].1 To this, Abraham Fraenkel later added that “the axiom of choice is probably the most interesting and, in spite of its late appearance, the most discussed axiom of mathematics, second only to Euclid’s axiom of parallels which was introduced more than two thousand years ago” [Fraenkel and Bar-Hillel 1958, 56–57]. Rarely have the practitioners of mathematics, a discipline known for the certainty of its conclusions, differed so vehemently over one of its central premises as they have done over the Axiom of Choice. Yet without the Axiom, mathematics today would be quite different.2 The very nature of modern mathematics would be altered and, if the Axiom’s most severe constructivist critics prevailed, mathematics would be reduced to a collection of algorithms. Indeed, the Axiom epitomizes the fundamental changes—mathematical, philosophical, and psychological—that took place when mathematicians seriously began to study infinite collections of sets.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 39.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 54.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

References

  1. This and all other cited articles by Hilbert can be found in his Gesammelte Abhandlungen (Hilbert 1932–1935).

    Google Scholar 

  2. When the term “the Axiom” occurs hereafter, it always refers to the Axiom of Choice.

    Google Scholar 

  3. A set A can be well-ordered if there exists a relation S (where aSb may be read as “a is less than b”) which orders A and if each non-empty subset B of A contains an element b such that bSc for all other c in B. Such an element b is called the least element of B. The relation S orders A if for every a, b, c in A, (i) if aSb and bSc, then aSc, and (ii) aSb or a = b or bSa, and (iii) not aSa.

    Google Scholar 

  4. Cantor 1883a, 550. This and all other cited articles by Cantor can be found in his Gesammelte Abhandlungen (Cantor 1932).

    Google Scholar 

  5. Zermelo 1904, translated in van Heijenoort 1967.

    Google Scholar 

  6. Zermelo 1908 and 1908a; both are translated in van Heijenoort 1967.

    Google Scholar 

  7. An urelement (also called an individual or an atom) was an object which contained no elements, belonged to some set, and yet was not identical with the empty set.

    Google Scholar 

  8. See Appendix 2 as well as Rubin and Rubin 1963.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 1982 Springer-Verlag New York Inc.

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Moore, G.H. (1982). Prologue. In: Zermelo’s Axiom of Choice. Studies in the History of Mathematics and Physical Sciences, vol 8. Springer, New York, NY. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-1-4613-9478-5_1

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-1-4613-9478-5_1

  • Publisher Name: Springer, New York, NY

  • Print ISBN: 978-1-4613-9480-8

  • Online ISBN: 978-1-4613-9478-5

  • eBook Packages: Springer Book Archive

Publish with us

Policies and ethics