Skip to main content

On Explanation in Retro-causal Interpretations of Quantum Mechanics

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Probabilities, Causes and Propensities in Physics

Part of the book series: Synthese Library ((SYLI,volume 347))

Abstract

The curious correlations between distant events in quantum phenomena suggest the existence of non-local influences. Indeed, as John Bell demonstrated in his celebrated theorem, granted some plausible premises any quantum theory will predict the existence of such non-local influences. One of the theorem’s premises is that the probability distribution of the states that systems may assume is independent of the measurements that they undergo at a later time. Retro-causal interpretations of quantum mechanics postulate backward influences from measurement events to the state of systems at an earlier time, and accordingly violate this premise. We argue that retro-causal interpretations predict the existence of closed causal loops, and consider the challenges that these loops for the explanatory power of these interpretations.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 84.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    There are some dissenting views. In particular, Fine (1981, 1986, 59–60, 1989) denies that non-accidental correlations must have causal explanation, and Cartwright (1989, Chapters 3 and 6) and Chang and Cartwright (1993) challenge the assumption that common causes render their joint effects probabilistically independent.

  2. 2.

    Recall that an event C screens off event E from event F if given C the probability of E is independent of F: \(P\left( {E/C\; \& \;F} \right) = P\left( {E/C} \right)\).

  3. 3.

    There are different ways to interpret the meaning of conditional probability. The common way is along Kolmogorov’s axiomatization, where the probability of B given A is defined as the ratio of unconditional probabilities: \(P\left( {B/A} \right) \equiv {{P\left( {B\;\&\; A} \right)} \mathord{\left/ {\vphantom {{P\left( {B\& A} \right)} {P\left( A \right)}}} \right. \kern-\nulldelimiterspace} {P\left( A \right)}}\). A different approach is to interpret conditional probability as a ‘primitive’, \(P_A \left( B \right)\), so that the conditioning events A are outside the probability space. On this alternative approach, conditional probability could be understood as a conditional with a probabilistic consequent, so that \(P_A \left( B \right) = p\) denotes the conditional “if A, then the probability of B is p” or “if A had been the case, then the probability of B would have been p”. For ease of presentation, we shall follow the first approach. For a general discussion of the second approach and its relation to the first approach, see Hajek (2003) and Berkovitz (2009a,2009b), and for a discussion of the advantages of the second approach in the context of Bell’s theorem, see Butterfield (1992) and Berkovitz (2002).

  4. 4.

    Although Bell’s conclusion is widely accepted, there are some dissenting views. In particular, Fine (1981, 1986, pp. 59–60, 1989), Cartwright (1989, Chapters 3 and 6) and Chang & Cartwright (1993) deny that the failure of Factorizability entails non-locality, and Fine (1982a, p. 294) argues that what the Bell inequalities are all about is the dubious requirement of making “well defined precisely those probability distributions for non-commuting observables whose rejection is the very essence of quantum mechanics” (cf. Berkovitz 1995, 2009a, Sections 1–2).

  5. 5.

    For recent review essays on Bell’s theorem and its implications for non-locality, see Shimony (2006) and Berkovitz (2007) and references therein.

  6. 6.

    In more general models, the complete pair-state at the emission may also be influenced by other factors, such as other final boundary conditions of the experiment. But while these models will substantially complicate our analysis, they will not alter significantly its main conclusions.

  7. 7.

    The main arguments to follow will hold even if we assume that complete pair-states are only compatible with certain apparatus settings, and accordingly prescribe outcomes just for the corresponding measurements.

  8. 8.

    I am grateful to Mauricio Suarez for pointing out to me the importance of emphasizing here the distinction between deterministic causal connections and indeterministic causal connections with propensity one.

  9. 9.

    The constraints of causal loops with two indeterministic causes may, however, limit the range of the possible long-run frequencies of effects in the reference class of their indeterministic causes. For an example, see Berkovitz (2002, Section 4).

  10. 10.

    The same is true for the complete pair-state, i.e. the state that is constituted by the initial and final wavefunctions of the particles and their position configuration; for the initial and final wavefunctions of the particles determine the measurement outcomes.

  11. 11.

    In Loop I, the differences between Model DS and Model IS are suppressed. Model DS predict Loop I with all the causal connections being deterministic, whereas Model IS predict Loop I with the causal connections between the complete pair-state and the R-outcome and between the L-setting and the complete pair-state being indeterministic.

References

  • Aharonov, Y. and Gruss, E. (2005), Two-time interpretation of quantum mechanics. http://arxiv.org/pdf/quant-ph/0507269

  • Aharonov, Y. and Tollaksen, J. (2007), New insights on time-symmetry in quantum mechanics. arXiv:0706.1232VI

    Google Scholar 

  • Aharonov, Y. and Vaidman, L. (2007), The two-state vector formalism: An updated review. Lectures Notes in Physics 734, 399–447. arXiv:quant-ph/0105101v2

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Argaman, N. (2007), On Bell’s theorem and causality. Unpublished manuscript.

    Google Scholar 

  • Arntzenius, F. and Maudlin, T. (2009). Time travel and modern physics. In E. N. Zalta (ed.), The Stanford Encyclopaedia of Philosophy (Summer 2005 Edition), URL = <http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2010/entries/time-travel-phys/>

  • Bell, JS. (1964), On the Einstein-Podolsky-Rosen paradox. Physics, 1, 195–200. Reprinted in Bell (1987), pp. 14–21.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bell, JS. (1966), On the problem of hidden variables in quantum mechanics. Reviews of Modern Physics 38, 447–452. Reprinted in Bell (1987), pp. 1–13.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bell, JS. (1971), Introduction to the hidden-variable question. In Espagnat B. (ed.), Foundations of Quantum Mechanics. Proceedings of the International School of Physics ‘Enrico Fermi’, Academic Press, New York-London, pp. 171–181. Reprinted in Bell (1987), pp. 29–39.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bell, JS. (1975a). The theory of local beables. TH-2053-Cern. Reprinted in Epistemological Letters March 1976 and Bell (1987), pp. 52–62.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bell, JS. (1975b), Locality in quantum mechanics: reply to critics. Epistemological Letters, Nov. 1975, 2–6. Reprinted in Bell (1987), pp. 63–66.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bell, JS. (1987). Speakable and Unspeakable in Quantum Mechanics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Berkovitz, J. (1995), What econometrics cannot teach quantum mechanics. Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics 26, 163–200.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Berkovitz, J. (2001), On chance in causal loops. Mind, 110, 1–23.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Berkovitz, J. (2002), On causal loops in the quantum realm. In T. Placek, and Butterfield, J. (eds.), Non-locality and Modality. Proceedings of the NATO Advanced Research Workshop on Modality, Probability and Bell’s Theorems, Kluwer, pp. 235–257.

    Google Scholar 

  • Berkovitz, J. (2007). Action at a distance in quantum mechanics. In Edward N. Zalta (ed.), The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Spring 2007 Edition), URL = <http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2007/entries/qm-action-distance/>.

  • Berkovitz, J. (2008), On predictions in retro-causal interpretations of quantum mechanics. Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics 39, 709–735.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Berkovitz, J. (2009a), The world according to de Finetti. Unpublished manuscript.

    Google Scholar 

  • Berkovitz (2009b), The propensity interpretation: Reply to critics. Unpublished manuscript.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bohm, D. (1951), Quantum theory. Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall.

    Google Scholar 

  • Butterfield, J. (1992), Bell’s Theorem: What It Takes. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 48, 41–83.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cartwright, N. (1989), Nature’s Capacities and their Measurements. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chang, H. and Cartwright, N. (1993), Causality and realism in the EPR experiment. Erkenntnis 38, 169–190.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Costa de Beauregard, O. (1953), Une réponse à l’argument dirigé par Einstein, Podolsky et Rosen contre l’interprétation Bohrienne des phénomènes quantiques, Comptes Rendus de l’Académie des Sciences 236 (1953), pp. 1632–1634.

    Google Scholar 

  • Costa de Beauregard, O. (1977), Time symmetry and the Einstein paradox. Il Nuovo Cimento 42B, 41–64.

    Google Scholar 

  • Costa de Beauregard, O. (1979), Time symmetry and the Einstein paradox – II. Il Nuovo Cimento 51B, 267–279.

    Google Scholar 

  • Costa de Beauregard, O. (1985), On some frequent but controversial statements concerning the Einstein-Podolsky-Rosen correlations. Foundations of Physics 15, 871–887.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cramer, J. (1980), Generalised absorber theory and the Einstein-Podolsky-Rosen paradox. Physical Review D 22, 362–376.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cramer, J. (1983), The Arrow of Electromagnetic Time and Generalized Absorber Theory. Foundations of Physics 13, 887–902.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cramer, J. (1986), The transactional interpretation of quantum mechanics. Reviews of Modern Physics 58, 647–687.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cramer, J. (1988), An overview of the transactional interpretation of quantum mechanics. International Journal of Theoretical Physics 27, 227–236.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Davidon, W. C. (1976), Quantum physics of single systems. Il Nuovo Cimento, 36B, 34–39.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dowe, P. (2003), The coincidences of time travel. Philosophy of Science 70, 574–589.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dummett, M. (1964), Bringing about the past. Philosophical Review 73, 338–359.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Einstein, A., Podolsky, R., and Rosen, N. (1935), Can quantum-mechanical description of physical reality be considered complete? Physics Review 47, 777–780.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fine, A. (1981), Correlations and physical locality. In P. Asquith and Giere, R. (eds.), PSA 1980, vol. 2. East Lansing, Michigan: Philosophy of Science Association, pp. 535–562.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fine, A. (1982a), Hidden variables, joint probability, and the Bell inequalities. Physics Review Letters 48 (1982), pp. 291–295.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fine, A. (1986), The Shaky Game. Chicago: The University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fine, A. (1989), Do correlations need to be explained? In J. Cushing and E. McMullin (eds.), Philosophical Consequences of Quantum Theory: Reflections on Bell’s Theorem, South Bend: The University of Notre Dame Press, pp. 175–194.

    Google Scholar 

  • Flew, A. (1954), Can an effect precede its cause? Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society Supplement 28, 45–52.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gruss, E. (2000), A Suggestion for a teleological interpretation of quantum mechanics. http://arxiv.org/abs/quant-ph/0006070

  • Hajek, A. (2003), What conditional probability could not be, Synthese 137, 273–323.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Horwich, P. (1987), Asymmetries in Time. Cambridge MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, D. (1986), Philosophical papers Vol. 2. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, P. J. (2006), Conspiracy theories of quantum mechanics. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 57/2, 359–381.

    Google Scholar 

  • Marchildon, L. (2006), Causal loops and collapse in the transactional Interpretation of quantum mechanics. http://arxiv.org/pdf/quant-ph/0603018v2

  • Maudlin, T. (1994), Quantum Non-locality and Relativity. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Miller, D. (1996), Realism and time symmetry in quantum mechanics. Physics Letters A 222, 31–36.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Miller, D. (2008), Quantum mechanics as a consistency condition on initial and final boundary conditions. Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics 39, 767–781.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mellor, D. H. (1981), Real Time. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mellor, D. H. (1998), Real Time II. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Price, H. (1984), The philosophy and physics of affecting the past. Synthese 61/3, 299–323.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Price, H. (1994), A neglected route to realism about quantum mechanics. Mind 103, 303–336.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Price, H. (1996), Time’s Arrow and Archimedes’ Point. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Price, H (2008), Toy models for retrocausality. Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics 39, 752–761.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Reichenbach, H. (1956), The Direction of Time. University of California Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Renninger, M. (1953), Zum wellen-korpuskel-dualismns. Zeit Schrift Für Physik, 251–261.

    Google Scholar 

  • Reznik, B. and Aharonov, Y. (1995), On a time symmetric formulation of quantum mechanics. http://arxiv.org/pdf/quant-ph/9501011

  • Shimony, A. (2006), Bell’s theorem. In E. N. Zalta (ed.), The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Fall 2006 Edition), URL = <http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2006/entries/bell-theorem/>.

  • Smith, N. (1997), Bananas enough for time travel? British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 48, 363–389.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sutherland, R. I. (1983), Bell’s theorem and backwards-in-time causality. International Journal of Theoretical Physics 22, 377–384.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sutherland, R. I. (1998), Density formalism for quantum theory. Foundations of Physics 28/7, 1157–1190.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sutherland, R. I. (2008), Causally symmetric Bohm model. Studies in the History and Philosophy of Modern Physics 39, 782–805.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tooley, M. (1997), Time, tense, and causation. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wheeler, J. A. and Feynman, R. P. (1945), Interaction with the absorber as the mechanism of radiation. Reviews of Modern Physics 17, 157–181.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wheeler, J. A. and Feynman, R. P. (1949), Classical electromagnetics in terms of direct infer particle action. Reviews of Modern Physics 21, 425–434.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

The work on this paper was prompted by an invitation to contribute to this volume. I am very grateful to the editor, Mauricio Suarez. Parts of this paper were presented at the Time-Symmetric Interpretations of Quantum Mechanics Workshop and the Summer Foundations Conference 2006, Centre for Time, Department of Philosophy, University of Sydney; CREA, Polytechnique, Paris; the Department of Philosophy, Universidad de Barcelona; the Department of Philosophy, Universidad Complutense de Madrid; and the Sigma Club, Centre for the Philosophy of Natural and Social Sciences, London School of Economics. These conferences and colloquia were instrumental in the development of the paper, and I thank the organizers, audiences, and in particular Rod Sutherland, Mauricio Suarez, Huw Price, David Miller, Carl Hoefer, Roman Frigg and Guido Bacciagaluppi. For support, I am very grateful to the Department of Philosophy, University of Sydney, and the Institute for History and Philosophy of Science and Technology, University of Toronto.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Joseph Berkovitz .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2011 Springer Netherlands

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Berkovitz, J. (2011). On Explanation in Retro-causal Interpretations of Quantum Mechanics. In: Suárez, M. (eds) Probabilities, Causes and Propensities in Physics. Synthese Library, vol 347. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-1-4020-9904-5_6

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics