Skip to main content

Notes on Future and History in Hermann Cohen’s Anti-Eschatological Messianism

  • Chapter
Hermann Cohen’s Critical Idealism

Part of the book series: Amsterdam Studies in Jewish Thought ((ASJT,volume 10))

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 169.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 219.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 219.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

References

  1. This paper is a revised version of my article ‘Una debole forza messianica’, in: Annuario filosofico 12 (1996), 299–327. Translated from the Italian by John Denton. One example is the extensive interest and widespread discussion, in European philosophy, following R. Koselleck’s reflections on ‘experience space’ and ‘expectation horizon’ in Vergangene Zukunft (Frankfurt am Main, 1979).

    Google Scholar 

  2. Cf. H. Jonas, Das Prinzip Verantwortung (Frankfurt am Main, 1979). Cf. also the widespread, predominantly Anglo-American discussion on responsibilities and obligations to future generations.

    Google Scholar 

  3. Cf. J. Derrida, D’un ton apocalyptique adopté naguère en philosophie (Paris, 1983).

    Google Scholar 

  4. I am especially thinking of the international best-seller by F. Fukuyama, The End of History and the Last Man (New York, 1992).

    Google Scholar 

  5. Such a strong contrast between the teleological and eschatological interpretation of history is a recurrent theme in J. Taubes, Ad Carl Schmitt. Gegenstrebige Fügung (Berlin, 1987).

    Google Scholar 

  6. The expression comes from N. Bolz, Auszug aus der entzauberten Welt. Philosophischer Extremismus zwischen den Weltkriegen (München, 1989).

    Google Scholar 

  7. A ‘kurze Rekapitulation des Herganges, in dem die Marburger Philosophie zwar verdrängt, aber nicht “überwunden” wurde’ opens D. Adelmann’s dissertation: Einheit des Bewußtseins als Grundproblem der Philosophie Hermann Cohens (Heidelberg 1968), which has the merit of opening up a new phase in the reception of Cohen’s philosophy. Similar considerations lie behind studies by H. Holzhey: Cohen und Natorp (Basel/Stuttgart, 1986), and A. Poma, La filosofia critica di Hermann Cohen (Milano, 1988), English translation: The Critical Philosophy of Hermann Cohen (Albany, 1997).

    Google Scholar 

  8. It is clearly impossible to consider all the aspects of these outlooks in the brief space of one article. A better strategy is to concentrate on the most essential relevant features in this sense of Cohen’s less well known approach. A collection of the main links between decisionism and eschatology is to be found in Taubes’ writings on Schmitt (see note 5). For an interpretation of the common features of the different forms of decisionism, including Heidegger’s, cf., in addition to the well known concluding pages of the essay by K. Löwith, ‘Der okkasionelle Dezisionismus von Carl Schmitt’, in Sämtliche Schriften (Stuttgart, 1981ff.), vol. 8, 32–71, the persuasive views, influenced by Taubes, of N. Bolz in Auszug aus der entzauberten Welt, 47–94.

    Google Scholar 

  9. Cf. Religion der Vernunft, 505.

    Google Scholar 

  10. Cf. K. Löwith, Meaning in History (1949), 17; German edition (1953), revised by the author: Weltgeschichte und Heilsgeschehen, in: Sämtliche Schriften (Stuttgart, 1983), vol. 2, 28.

    Google Scholar 

  11. Cf. Religion der Vernunft, 305, 291f. — Löwith is actually quoting from the 1919 Leipzig edition, which, however, has no variations compared with the Frankfurt edition published ten years later, as far as the passages in question are concerned.

    Google Scholar 

  12. The book’s complicated publishing history evidently affected attention to detail. It is significant that not only this last quotation, but also the lack of precision in the quotation of the other passages are absent from the version Löwith prepared for Anteile, the Festschrift for Heidegger published by Klostermann in 1950, i.e. a year after the publication of Meaning in History in the USA. Cf. the essay ‘Weltgeschichte und Heilsgeschehen’ (1950), now in: Sämtliche Schriften, vol. 2, 240–279, esp. 255. Löwith himself points out in the introduction to the 1953 German edition that in 1949 he had had to use a language that ‘the author had to make his own’ and that ‘does not lend itself to conceptual and verbal subtleties’. Since several terminological and conceptual clarifications were introduced into the 1953 text, for the above reasons, it is from this edition that we shall quote, though also with reference to the American edition.

    Google Scholar 

  13. The same orientation in an eschatological direction of Cohen’s thoughts and expressions can be traced in the passage where Löwith writes: ‘“mankind” has not existed in the historical past, nor can it exist in any present. It is an idea and an ideal of the future, the necessary horizon for the eschatological concept of history and its universality.’, Weltgeschichte und Heilsgeschehen, 29; Meaning in History, 18; cf. Religion der Vernunft, 292.

    Google Scholar 

  14. Cf. Religion der Vernunft, 57.

    Google Scholar 

  15. Cf. Religion der Vernunft, 336.

    Google Scholar 

  16. Weltgeschichte und Heilsgeschehen, 11; Meaning in History, 1

    Google Scholar 

  17. Weltgeschichte und Heilsgeschehen, 15; Meaning in History, 5

    Google Scholar 

  18. Weltgeschichte und Heilsgeschehen, 15; Meaning in History, 6

    Google Scholar 

  19. Weltgeschichte und Heilsgeschehen, 16; Meaning in History, 6

    Google Scholar 

  20. Weltgeschichte und Heilsgeschehen, 29; Meaning in History, 18

    Google Scholar 

  21. ‘Weltgeschichte und Heilsgeschehen’ (= essay for Anteile, see note 12), 259.

    Google Scholar 

  22. Cf. Weltgeschichte und Heilsgeschehen, 29; Meaning in History, 18

    Google Scholar 

  23. Weltgeschichte und Heilsgeschehen, 15 — words added to the German edition.

    Google Scholar 

  24. Weltgeschichte und Heilsgeschehen, 15; Meaning in History, 5

    Google Scholar 

  25. Cf. ‘Weltgeschichte und Heilsgeschehen’ (see note 12), 258f.

    Google Scholar 

  26. ‘Geschichte, Geschichtlichkeit und Seinsgeschick’, in: Heidegger. Denker in dürftiger Zeit, (Göttingen, 19602), 44–71, reprinted in vol. 8 of Sämtliche Schriften (henceforth: ‘Geschichte’).

    Google Scholar 

  27. ‘Geschichte’, 67. See also 47.

    Google Scholar 

  28. ‘Geschichte’, 47.

    Google Scholar 

  29. ‘Geschichte’, 56. Cf. also 45. The expression ‘eschatology of being’ is used by Heidegger, as is well known, in his essay on the saying of Anaximander, where it is stated that ‘being itself, inasmuch as it is geschicklich, is in itself eschatological’, Holzwege (Frankfurt am Main, 19806), 323. On the meaning of this ‘eschatology’ cf. G. Vattimo, Essere, storia e linguaggio in Heidegger (Genova, 19892), 23–25; here see also the considerations on the eschatological structure of temporality in Sein und Zeit, 77f.

    Google Scholar 

  30. ‘Geschichte’, 49. — As can be seen in his autobiographical work Mein Leben in Deutschland vor und nach 1933 (Stuttgart, 1986), this expression comes from a successful parody of Heidegger by one of his students.

    Google Scholar 

  31. ‘Geschichte’, 49.

    Google Scholar 

  32. ‘Geschichte’, 51.

    Google Scholar 

  33. ‘Geschichte’, 44 and 50.

    Google Scholar 

  34. Cf. the final pages of the essay ‘M. Heidegger und F. Rosenzweig. Ein Nachtrag zu “Sein und Zeit”’, now in: Sämliche Schriften, vol. 8, 161–188.

    Google Scholar 

  35. Cf. J. Habermas, ‘Karl Löwiths stoischer Rückzug vom historischen Bewußsein’, in: idem, Theorie und Praxis (Neuwied am Rhein/Berlin, 19672), 352–370, as well as the concluding pages of A. Caracciolo, Karl Löwith (Napoli, 1974).

    Google Scholar 

  36. This is a revised and expanded version of the lecture he gave in Marburg on 21 June 1968 on the occasion of the fiftieeth anniversary of Cohen’s death. It was first published in the same year in Sitzungsberichte der Heidelberger Akademie der Wissenschaften and reprinted in vol. 3 of Sämtliche Schriften, 349–383, from which quotations are taken here. Although this is his only work dealing specifically with Cohen, Löwith’s familiarity with some of the former’s writings is borne out by his Habilitationsschrift: cf. Das Individuum in der Rolle des Mitmenschen (München, 1928), 2 and 55, reprinted in Sämtliche Werke, vol. 1 (1981), 17 and 71. Cf., however, his letter dated 15 April 1935 to Leo Strauss, where he admits that he had ‘not studied [Cohen] very much’.

    Google Scholar 

  37. Sämtliche Schriften vol 3, 381f.

    Google Scholar 

  38. Sämtliche Schriften vol. 3, 381.

    Google Scholar 

  39. Cf. Sämliche Schriften vol. 3, 383: ‘Die Welt der Geschichte bezeugt sich in historischen Dokumenten, die Welt der Natur bezeugt sich unmittelbar selbst.’ (The world of history testifies in historical documents, the world of nature immediately testifies by itself.) This presumed ahistorical immediacy of our access to nature is actually, perhaps beyond Löwith’s intentions, the exact overturning of that ‘in gedruckten Büchern gegebene und in einer Geschichte wirklich gewordene Erfahrung’ (experience given in printed books and become real in history) which Cohen mentions, cf. Kants Begründung der Ethik (Berlin, 19102), 35.

    Google Scholar 

  40. Cf. M. Heidegger und F. Rosenzweig, 188.

    Google Scholar 

  41. Cf. Weltgeschichte und Heilsgeschehen, 213.

    Google Scholar 

  42. Cf. H. Holzhey, ‘Neukantianismus und Sozialismus’, in: idem (ed.), Ethischer Sozialismus. Zur politischen Philosophie des Neukantianismus (Frankfurt am Main, 1994), 23.

    Google Scholar 

  43. G. Scholem, über einige Grundbegriffe des Judentums (Frankfurt am Main, 1970), 167. Scholem underlines this idea by the use of the concept of ‘life in postponement’ (Leben im Aufschub). He had originally developed this train of thought on this theological category in his notes ‘Ueber das Buch Jonas und den Begriff der Gerechtigkeit’ written in Bern in 1919; now in: G. Scholem, Tagebücher 1917–1923 (Frankfurt am Main, 2000), 522–536. He attributed the inapplicability of the written Torah to the fact that, though it is divine law, it is not yet justice. It becomes the latter in ‘the infinite postponement of tradition’. In this sense, ‘justice is the idea of the historical annihilation of divine judgment’. These notes considerably influenced Benjamin: cf. Scholem’s remarks in: Walter Benjamin — Die Geschichte einer Freundschaft (Frankfurt am Main, 1975), 93, 181, 213 and Benjamin’s texts in Gesammelte Schriften vol. 2, 427 and 1191, vol. 6, 60. It is also significant that Aufschub is the German translation of Derrida’s term différance: cf. the translation of L’écriture et la différence: Die Schrift und die Differenz, trans. by R. Gasché (Frankfurt am Main, 1972), especially 311: ‘Der Aufschub bildet das Wesen des Lebens’. It also appears relevant that this interpretation of messianism met with disagreement by J. Taubes in his Jerusalem lecture ‘The Price of Messianism’, now in a German edition in: idem, Vom Kult zur Kultur (München, 1996), especially 48f.

    Google Scholar 

  44. P.A. Schmid, Ethik als Hermeneutik. Systematische Untersuchungen zu Hermann Cohens Rechts-und Tugendlehre (Würzburg, 1995), 197.

    Google Scholar 

  45. Cf. H. Holzhey, ‘Hermann Cohen: der Philosoph in Auseinandersetzung mit den politischen und gesellschaftlichen Problemen seiner Zeit’, in: R. Brandt, F. Orlik (eds), Philosophisches Denken — Politisches Wirken (Hildesheim, 1993), 15–36, especially 32. Cohen’s interpretation of the legend of the three rings is of particular significance here: Der Begriff der Religion, 119f.

    Google Scholar 

  46. This aspect has been especially highlighted in Cohen’s case by H. Holzhey, ‘Hermann Cohen: der Philosoph in Auseinandersetzung mit den politischen und gesellschaftlichen Problemen seiner Zeit’, passim, and by P.A. Schmid, Ethik als Hermeneutik, 168–173 and 293–309.

    Google Scholar 

  47. Religion der Vernunft, 278.

    Google Scholar 

  48. The ‘motive of humanity as a fundamental, systematic problem’ is the core of the third chapter of D. Adelmann, Einheit des Bewußseins, 109ff.

    Google Scholar 

  49. For the relationship between truth and system in Cohen cf. especially Chapters 1 and 9 of the Ethik.

    Google Scholar 

  50. ‘Platons Ideenlehre und die Mathematik’ (1878), in: Schriften I, 336–366, esp. 348.

    Google Scholar 

  51. On spiritualism, materialism and idealism cf., in this sense, Ethik, 315.

    Google Scholar 

  52. Cf. Logik, 80f.

    Google Scholar 

  53. The expression ‘meontologia’ is used by S. Givone, Storia del nulla (Roma-Bari, 1995), xviii. Certain similarities and differences between Cohen’s negative ontology (with the raising of Plato’s mè ón to a structural principle) and an ontology of nothing originating in Heidegger will emerge from subsequent pages. Cf. H. Holzhey, ‘Heidegger und Cohen. Negativitāt in Denken des Ursprungs’, in: G. Hauff, H.R. Schweizer, A. Wildermuth (eds.), In Erscheinung treten. Heinrich Barths Philosophie des Āsthetischen (Basel, 1990), 97–114.

    Google Scholar 

  54. Cf. Begriff der Religion, 46f., 50 and Religion der Vernunft, 38, 51f. I attempted a more detailed treatment of this aspect in my article ‘Problematologia divina. La filosofia dell’origine in Cohen tra ontologismo cristiano e nichilismo’, in: Discipline filosofiche 9 (1999), 103–120.

    Google Scholar 

  55. Logik, 127f.

    Google Scholar 

  56. Cf. in this sense M. Heidegger, Logik. Die Frage nach der Wahrheit (Frankfurt am Main, 1976), 390.

    Google Scholar 

  57. Cf. the relevant chapters in Logik, 79–104.

    Google Scholar 

  58. ‘Die Bedeutung der Einheit ist keineswegs einheitlich; sondern sie spiegelt die Unklarheit ab, welche über dem Grunde des reinen Denkens schwebt’, Logik 144.

    Google Scholar 

  59. Logik, 134.

    Google Scholar 

  60. Logik, 129.

    Google Scholar 

  61. Logik, 134.

    Google Scholar 

  62. Cf. Logik, 84.

    Google Scholar 

  63. Logik, 31

    Google Scholar 

  64. Logik, 135

    Google Scholar 

  65. Logik, 146.

    Google Scholar 

  66. Ethik, 399.

    Google Scholar 

  67. Logik, 228. An emphasis somewhat analogous to the spatial component of the ‘ordinary present’ can be found in E. Bloch, Experimentum mundi (Frankfurt am Main, 1975), 84ff.

    Google Scholar 

  68. Logik, 155.

    Google Scholar 

  69. Logik, 154.

    Google Scholar 

  70. Cf. Ethik, 399.

    Google Scholar 

  71. Logik, 154f.

    Google Scholar 

  72. Logik, 155.

    Google Scholar 

  73. Religion der Vernunft, 291.

    Google Scholar 

  74. Ethik, 408.

    Google Scholar 

  75. Religion der Vernunft, 360.

    Google Scholar 

  76. Logik, 155.

    Google Scholar 

  77. Cf. Logik, 151–153.

    Google Scholar 

  78. Religion der Vernunft, 312.

    Google Scholar 

  79. For an adequate treatment of this problem area in Cohen’s thought cf., the pages of Religion der Vernunft where the ethical optimism of messianism is contrasted with the subtle metaphysical lure of pessimism (Religion der Vernunft, 20f., 524), and also the final statement of the first edition of Kants Begründung der Ethik (1877): ‘Es ist in Wahrheit nicht nur ein Fortschritt der ethischen Kultur, sondern mittelbar auch ein solcher der ethischen Wissenschaft, da Frage des Optimismus in unserm Jahrhundert, sofern man von der Unterhaltungs-Philosophie abzusehen hat, abgelöst ist durch das Problem des Sozialismus’. (368) (Actually the fact that the question of optimism has been substituted, in our century, regardless of drawing room philosophy, by the problem of socialism is a sign of progress, not only of ethical culture, but, indirectly, of ethical science).

    Google Scholar 

  80. Ethik, 140.

    Google Scholar 

  81. Logik, 155. These expressions are used by E. Bloch in his essay ‘Differenzierungen im Begriff Fortschritt’, see: idem, Tübinger Einleitung in die Philosophie (Frankfurt am Main, 1970), 119f.

    Google Scholar 

  82. Logik, 31.

    Google Scholar 

  83. For Cohen’s criticism of the postulates of practical reason, cf., especially, Kants Begründung der Ethik 344–369.

    Google Scholar 

  84. P.A. Schmid, Ethik als Hermeneutik, 101–109. But on the systematic meaning of Kants Begründung der Ethik, cf. also D. Adelmann, Einheit des Bewuβtseins, 142–165, and G. Gigliotti, Hermann Cohen e la fondazione kantiana dell’etica (Firenze, 1977), 31–66.

    Google Scholar 

  85. Kants Begründung der Ethik, 185.

    Google Scholar 

  86. P.A. Schmid, Ethik als Hermeneutik, 147. For an exhaustive analysis of the problems concerning the concept of intelligible contingency (developed by Cohen especially in the first chapter of Kants Begründung der Ethik) cf. 115ff. As is evident both from the Kommentar zu Immanuel Kants Kritik der reinen Vernunft (Leipzig, 1907), reprinted in Werke, vol. 4 (1978), 150, 198, and from Kants Theorie der Erfahrung, 636ff., Cohen is not so much thinking of the note to the thesis of the fourth antinomy, where Kant refers specifically to intelligible contingency, but rather of the passage on the contingency of experience in Kritik der reinen Vernunft B 764f. Cf. H. Holzhey, ‘Wissenschaft und Gottesidee. Cohen vor dem “Abgrund der intelligibeln Zufälligkeit”’, in: I.U. Dalferth, Ph. Stoellger (eds.), Vernunft, Kontingenz und Gott (Tübingen, 2000), 273–290.

    Google Scholar 

  87. P.A. Schmid, Ethik als Hermeneutik, 170.

    Google Scholar 

  88. Kants Begründung der Ethik, 79.

    Google Scholar 

  89. Kants Begründung der Ethik, 48.

    Google Scholar 

  90. Kants Begründung der Ethik, 103.

    Google Scholar 

  91. For an analysis of these problems cf. P.A. Schmid, Ethik als Hermeneutik, 151–167.

    Google Scholar 

  92. Kants Begründung der Ethik, 110.

    Google Scholar 

  93. Kants Begründung der Ethik, 103.

    Google Scholar 

  94. Kants Begründung der Ethik, 110f. For an interpretation of this passage cf. D. Adelmann, Einheit des Bewuβtseins, 149f.

    Google Scholar 

  95. Ethik, 320.

    Google Scholar 

  96. Einleitung mit kritischem Nachtrag, 113.

    Google Scholar 

  97. Kants Begründung der Ethik, 274.

    Google Scholar 

  98. Einleitung mit kritischem Nachtrag, 113.

    Google Scholar 

  99. Ethik, 319.

    Google Scholar 

  100. Besides the contributions collected in the volume Ethischer Sozialismus, cf. H. van der Linden, Kantian Ethics and Socialism (Indianapolis, 1988).

    Google Scholar 

  101. Cf. Kants Begründung der Ethik, 265.

    Google Scholar 

  102. Cf. H. van der Linden, ‘Cohens sozialistische Rekonstruktion der Ethik Kants’, in: H. Holzhey (ed), Ethischer Sozialismus, especially 154–159.

    Google Scholar 

  103. Kants Begründung der Ethik, 227.

    Google Scholar 

  104. Kants Begründung der Ethik, 272.

    Google Scholar 

  105. Kants Begründung der Ethik, 270.

    Google Scholar 

  106. Kants Begründung der Ethik, 270.

    Google Scholar 

  107. Kants Begründung der Ethik, 227.

    Google Scholar 

  108. Ethik, 411 — my italics.

    Google Scholar 

  109. Ethik, 408.

    Google Scholar 

  110. Cf. Ethik, 400. In Logik der reinen Erkenntnis the category of space had been placed in the context of the quantitative determination of totality (Allheit); cf. Logik, 188ff.

    Google Scholar 

  111. That time should not be reduced to ‘an infinite sum’, but rather that ‘any sum is an impediment’ is the theme to which Cohen frequently returns in already mentioned parts of the Ethik, against easy misunderstandings of his remarks on the ‘plus sign’ as a’ symbol of time’ (cf. Ethik, 400, 409).

    Google Scholar 

  112. Cf. Religion der Vernunft, 291, 305.

    Google Scholar 

  113. Cf. Religion der Vernunft, 533.

    Google Scholar 

  114. I attempted to demonstrate this in greater detail in Geschichtliche Ewigkeit. Ursprung und Zeitlichkeit in der Philosophie Hermann Cohens (Würzburg, 1993).

    Google Scholar 

  115. Ethik, 408.

    Google Scholar 

  116. Ethik, 417.

    Google Scholar 

  117. Cf. Ethik, 400f. and Religion der Vernunft, 292.

    Google Scholar 

  118. The fact that such characteristics cannot be attributed to the ‘idea of God’ in Cohen’s ethics, has been pointed out again by P.A. Schmid, Ethik als Hermeneutik, 222ff.

    Google Scholar 

  119. Ethik, 410.

    Google Scholar 

  120. Ethik, 410.

    Google Scholar 

  121. Cf. P.A. Schmid, Ethik als Hermeneutik, 201.

    Google Scholar 

  122. Ethik, 411.

    Google Scholar 

  123. Cf. note 43.

    Google Scholar 

  124. Ethik, 411.

    Google Scholar 

  125. Cf. S. Kaplan, Das Geschichtsproblem in der Philosophie Hermann Cohens (Berlin, 1930), 40f.

    Google Scholar 

  126. Kants Theorie der Erfahrung, 8.

    Google Scholar 

  127. Ästhetik I, 47.

    Google Scholar 

  128. Religion der Vernunft, 238, 269, 355.

    Google Scholar 

  129. Ästhetik II, 192.

    Google Scholar 

  130. Logik, 125.

    Google Scholar 

  131. Logik, 80; cf; also 51f.

    Google Scholar 

  132. Religion der Vernunft, 508.

    Google Scholar 

  133. Religion der Vernunft, 530. An exhaustive, systematic treatment of this page within Cohen’s thought can be found in A. Poma, ‘Humour in Religion: Peace and Contentment’, in: S. Moses and H. Wiedebach, (eds), Hermann Cohen’s Philosophy of Religion. International Conference in Jerusalem 1996 (Hildesheim, 1997), 183–204.

    Google Scholar 

  134. On the relationship between irony and resignation in Cohen, cf. the detailed remarks of P.A. Schmid, Ethik als Hermeneutik, 262f.

    Google Scholar 

  135. K. Löwith, ‘Philosophie der Vernunft und Religion der Offenbarung’ (see note 36, above), 381.

    Google Scholar 

  136. Cf. P.A. Schmid, Ethik als Hermeneutik, 167, 174–177.

    Google Scholar 

  137. Cf. H. Holzhey, ‘Neukantianismus und Sozialismus’, 28.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2005 Springer

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Fiorato, P. (2005). Notes on Future and History in Hermann Cohen’s Anti-Eschatological Messianism. In: Munk, R. (eds) Hermann Cohen’s Critical Idealism. Amsterdam Studies in Jewish Thought, vol 10. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/1-4020-4047-4_5

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics