Skip to main content

Information and Semiosis in Living Systems: A Semiotic Approach

  • Chapter
Essential Readings in Biosemiotics

Part of the book series: Biosemiotics ((BSEM,volume 3))

Abstract

At the Ninth World Congress of the International Association for Semiotic Studies in 2007, molecular biologist Jesper Hoffmeyer recalls the impetus leading to the founding of “biosemiotics” as a research agenda in Denmark by himself and Claus Emmeche in 1985 thusly:

Claus Emmeche(1956–),João Queiroz(1963–),and Charbel El-Hani(1968–)

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 259.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 329.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 329.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    Readers wishing to learn more about Peirce’s philosophy and logic of semiotic should consult Murphey 1993, Nöth 1995, Parker 1998, and Peirce 1931–1935, 1967, 1976, 1998, and 1982–2000, as detailed in our Reference List.

  2. 2.

     When a part or subsystem of a system is the interpreter, its actions as an interpreter will be typically subordinated, i.e., regulated by the system as a whole (that we will call, in this case, a “global” interpreter). We can call, as Jablonka (2002), the subordinated interpreters “interpretative systems” within a global interpreter. It can happen that a system loses its control over one or more of its included interpreters. In this case, dysfunctional states may result from the interpretation of signs in that system. These are misinterpretation events. By “misinterpretation”, we mean the interpretation of a sign that does not lead to a successful coping with its circumstances, i.e., that does not contribute to the maintenanceof the dynamic stability of a system in a given context.

  3. 3.

    For a review of these topics, see Savan (1987), Liszka (1990), Short (1996).

  4. 4.

    In the context of our analysis, we will not employ the concept of Final Interpretant. It will not play an important role in our current arguments, and, thus, we think we can leave it to subsequent works.

  5. 5.

    It should be clear at this point that by “communication” we mean more than mere transmission of a form.

  6. 6.

    The irreducibility of the triadic relation S-O-I is a logical property. Therefore, while it makes no sense to sort out a primary constraining factor in such a logical relation, dynamically it makes sense to sort out the dynamical object as the primary constraining factor of semiosis (for a detailed discussion about this issue, see Short 1998: 31).

  7. 7.

    For more details, we refer the reader to El-Hani et al. (forthcoming).

  8. 8.

     We will deliberately avoid introducing a large number of details, which can be easily found in any molecular and cell biology textbook (e.g., Lodish et al. 2003, Cooper and Haussman 2003, Alberts et al. 2002, Lewin 2000). These books are also the basic sources in this section, unless otherwise noticed. As the following paragraphs only summarize some elementary ideas in cell and molecular biology, any reader who doesn’t feel any need of perusing these notions can simply skip them.

  9. 9.

    If alternative splicing does not occur, it will be the case that signs in DNA and signs in mature mRNA will be equivalent.

  10. 10.

     In the case of genes, the objects at stake are entities, as described above. Nevertheless, it is important to bear in mind that, in Peirce’s framework, it is not the case that the object of a sign should necessarily be an entity, a thing, or even an existent. Consider, for instance, the following passage: “The Objects – for a Sign may have any number of them – may each be a single known existing thing or thing believed formerly to have existed or expected to exist, or a collection of such things, or a known quality or relation or fact, which single Object may be a collection, or whole of parts, or it may have some other mode of being, such as some act permitted whose being does not prevent its negation from being equally permitted, or something of a general nature desired, required, or invariably found under certain general circumstances” (CP 2.232).

  11. 11.

     To be more precise, we should consider that some proteins acquire their mature conformation spontaneously. These proteins show the property of self-assembly. In this case, the three-dimensional structure of a protein simply follows from its primary sequence of amino acids, and, therefore, the immediate Object directly determines the dynamical Object. (Here we find yet another peculiar feature of the genetic information system, when compared to the standard Peircean framework). There are a number of proteins, however, that cannot self-assemble and should be assisted by proteins called “chaperones” in order to acquire their proper structures. In this case, the sequence of amino acids, the Immediate object, only indicates the functional protein, the dynamic object. In the text, we are dealing particularly with this case, which fits Peirce’s understanding of the relationship between immediate and dynamical objects. “Chaperones” can be treated, in these terms, as part of the habits cells acquired in evolution.

  12. 12.

     Symptomatically, Godfrey-Smith (1999) and Griffiths (2001) argue that developmental information is not stored in the genetic code, because the formal coding relation between codons in DNA and amino acids in polypeptides specifies only the primary structure of proteins.

  13. 13.

     In a Peircean framework, the immediate object can be understood as the characteristics selected in the sign as a means of indicating the dynamical object. It is not the case, in this framework, that the immediate object is a condition of possibility to the dynamical object. Nevertheless, in the case we are analyzing here the interpreter creates a dynamical object of a given class (showing a given habit) on the grounds of indications present in the sign. A cell uses signs in DNA as a basis for synthesizing a dynamical object sufficiently resembling a past dynamical object which does not exist anymore but resulted in successful, adaptive experiences. This is the reason why we claim that, in this case, the immediate object establishes conditions of possibility to the dynamical object.

  14. 14.

     By “coding”, we mean here a system of constraints which establishes a range of possible effects of a sign (see Nöth 1995: 210).

  15. 15.

    In this picture, it is important to take in due account that we are not claiming that DNA causes or brings about the protein as an object, since DNA is a set of data (or, as we prefer, signs) rather than a program, a source of materials rather than a master agent in the cell. It is the DNA processing system that produces the proteins. We are not claiming, therefore, that the sign causes the object.

  16. 16.

    In another paper, we substantiate and elaborate these conclusions by means of a more detailed analysis of some processes in the genetic information system, namely, transcription and translation. For this analysis, see El-Hani et al. (forthcoming).

References

  • Adami, C. (2004). Information theory in molecular biology. Physics of Life Reviews 1, 3–22.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Adams, F. (2003). The Informational Turn in Philosophy. Minds and Machines 13, 471–501.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Alberts, B., Johnson, A., Lewis, J., Raff, M., Roberts, K., Walter, P. (2002). Molecular Biology of the Cell. 4th Edition. New York: Garland Science.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bergman, M. (2000). Reflections on the role of the communicative sign. In Semeiotic. Transactions of the Charles S. Peirce Society: A Quarterly Journal in American Philosophy. Spring, XXXVI(2), 225–254.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brunning, J. (1997). Genuine triads and teridentity. In: Houser, N., Roberts, D., Evra, J., (Eds.) Studies in the logic of Charles Sanders Peirce. Indiana: Indiana University Press, pp. 252–270.

    Google Scholar 

  • Campbell, N. A., Reece, J. B. (2002). Biology. 6th Edition. San Francisco: The Benjamim/Cummings Publ. Co.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cooper, G. M., Haussman, R. E. (2003). The Cell: A Molecular Approach. 3rd Edition. Sunderland-MA: Sinauer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cover, T. M., Thomas, J. A. (1999). Information theory. In Wilson, R. A., Keil, F. C. (Eds.) MIT Encyclopedia of the Cognitive Sciences. Cambridge-MA: MIT Press, pp. 404–406.

    Google Scholar 

  • Deacon, T. (1997). The Symbolic Species: The Co-evolution of Language and the Brain. New York: W.W. Norton & Company.

    Google Scholar 

  • Debrock, G. (1996). Information and the metaphysical status of the sign. In Colapietro, V., Olshewsky, T. (Eds.) Peirce’s Doctrine of Signs – theory, applications, and connections. Berlin, New York: Mouton de Gruyter, pp.80–89.

    Google Scholar 

  • De Tienne, A. (2003). Learning qua semiosis. Semiotics Evolution Energy and Development 3, 37–53.

    Google Scholar 

  • El-Hani, C.N., Queiroz, J., Emmeche, C. (Forthcoming). A semiotic analysis of the genetic information system. Semiotica.

    Google Scholar 

  • Emmeche, C. (1991). A semiotical reflection on biology, living signs and artificial life. Biology and Philosophy 6:325–340.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Emmeche, C. (2003). Causal processes, semiosis, and consciousness. In Seibt, J. (Ed.) Process Theories: Crossdisciplinary Studies in Dynamic Categories. Dordrecht: Kluwer, pp. 313–336.

    Google Scholar 

  • Emmeche, C., Hoffmeyer, J. (1991). From language to nature – the semiotic metaphor in biology. Semiotica 84(1/2), 1–42.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fetzer, J. (2001). Computers and Cognition: Why Minds are not Machines. Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fitzgerald, J. (1966). Peirce’s Theory of Signs as Foundation for Pragmatism. University of Notre Dame: Mouton & Co.

    Google Scholar 

  • Freadman, A. (2004). The Machinery of Talk – Charles Peirce and the Sign Hypothesis. Stanford: Stanford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Freeman, E. (1983). The Relevance of Charles Peirce. La Salle, Illinois: Monist Library of Philosophy.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gilbert, W. (1978). Why genes in pieces? Nature 271, 501.

    Article  PubMed  CAS  Google Scholar 

  • Godfrey-Smith, P. (1999). Genes and codes: Lessons from the philosophy of mind? In Hardcastle, V. G. (Ed.) Biology Meets Psychology: Philosophical Essays. Cambridge-MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Godfrey-Smith, P. (2000). Information, arbitrariness, and selection: Comments on Maynard Smith. Philosophy of Science 67(2), 202–207.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Griffiths, A. J. F., Gelbart, W. M., Miller, J. H., Lewontin, R. C. (1999). Modern Genetic Analysis. New York: W. H. Freeman & Co.

    Google Scholar 

  • Griffiths, P. (2001). Genetic information: A metaphor in search of a theory. Philosophy of Science 68(3), 394–403.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hausman, C. (1993). Charles Sanders Peirce’s Evolutionary Philosophy. Cambridge, England: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hoffmeyer, J. (1996). Signs of Meaning in the Universe. Bloomington and Indianapolis: Indiana University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Houser, N. (1997). Introduction: Peirce as a logician. In Houser, N., Roberts, D., Evra, J. (Eds.) Studies in the Logic of Charles Sanders Peirce. Indiana: Indiana University Press, pp. 1–22.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ideker, T., Galitski, T., Hood, L. (2001). A new approach to decoding life: Systems biology. Annual Review of Genomics and Human Genetics 2, 343–372.

    Article  PubMed  CAS  Google Scholar 

  • Jablonka, E. (1994). Inheritance systems and the evolution of new levels of individuality. Journal of Theoretical Biology 170, 301–309.

    Article  PubMed  CAS  Google Scholar 

  • Jablonka, E. (2002). Information: its interpretation, its inheritance, and its sharing. Philosophy of Science 69, 578–605.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jablonka, E., Szathmáry, E. (1995). The evolution of information storage and heredity. Trends in Ecology and Evolution 10, 206–211.

    Article  PubMed  CAS  Google Scholar 

  • Jablonka, E., Lamb, M. J., Avital, E. (1998). ‘Lamarckian’ mechanisms in Darwinian evolution. Trends in Ecology and Evolution 13, 206–210.

    Article  PubMed  CAS  Google Scholar 

  • Johansen, J. (1993). Dialogic Semiosis. Indiana: Indiana University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lewin, B. (2000). Genes VII. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lizska, J. J. (1990). Peirce’s interpretant. Transactions of the Charles S. Peirce Society. Summer XXVI(1), 17–61.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lodish, H., Berk, A., Matsudaira, P., Kaiser, C. A., Krieger, M., Scott, M. P., Zipursky, S. L., Darnell, J. (2003). Molecular Cell Biology. 5th Edition. New York: W. H. Freeman & Co.

    Google Scholar 

  • Maynard, S. J. (2000). The concept of information in Biology. Philosophy of Science 67(2), 177–194.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Maynard, S. J., Szathmáry, E. (1995). The Major Transitions in Evolution. Oxford: W. H. Freeman.

    Google Scholar 

  • Maynard, S. J., Szathmáry, E. (1999). The Origins of Life: From the Birth of Life to the Origins of Language. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Merrell, F. (1995). Peirce’s Semiotics Now. Toronto: Canadian Scholar’s Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Murphey, M. (1993). The Development of Peirce’s Philosophy. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nöth, W. (1995). Handbook of Semiotics. Bloomington and Indianapolis: Indiana University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Oyama, S. (2000). The Ontogeny of Information: Developmental Systems and Evolution. 2nd Edition. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Parker, K. (1998). The Continuity of Peirce’s Thought. Nashville:Vanderbilt University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Peirce, C. S. (1931–1935). The Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce. [Hartshorne, C., Weiss, P. (Eds.) Cambridge-MA: Harvard University Press, 1931–1935], Vols. VII–VIII [Burks, A. W. (Ed.) same publisher, 1958]. Electronic edition reproducing Vols. I–VI. Charlottesville: Intelex Corporation. (Here referred as CP, followed by volume and paragraph number.)

    Google Scholar 

  • Peirce, C. S. (1967). Annotated Catalogue of the papers of Charles S. Peirce. Amherst-MS: University of Massachusetts. Robin, R. (Ed.) [References to manuscripts and letters by Charles S. Peirce – MS and L – are in accordance with this catalogue.]

    Google Scholar 

  • Peirce, C. S. [1893–1913] (1998). The Essential Peirce: Selected Philosophical Writings. Vol. II. (Ed.) Peirce Edition Project. Bloomington and Indianapolis: Indiana University Press. (Here referred as EP2, followed by the number of the page.)

    Google Scholar 

  • Peirce, C. S. [1839–1914] (1982–2000). Writings of Charles S. Peirce: a Chronological Edition. Vol. 2. Ed. Peirce Edition Project. Bloomington: Indiana University. [Quoted as W, followed by page number].

    Google Scholar 

  • Peirce, C. S. (1976). New Elements of Mathematics by Charles S. Peirce, Carolyn E. (Ed.) The Hague: Mouton. [Quoted as NEM, followed by page number].

    Google Scholar 

  • Potter, V. (1997). Charles S. Peirce: On Norms and Ideals. Amherst, MA: University of Massachusetts Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Queiroz, J., Merrell, F. (2005). Abduction – between subjectivity and objectivity. Semiotica (Special Issue on Abduction) 153(1/4), 1–7.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ransdell, J. (1977). Some leadings ideas of Peirce’s semiotic. Semiotica 19(3/4), 157–178.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rescher, N. (1996). Process Metaphysics: An Introduction to Process Philosophy. New York: State University of New York Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rosenthal, S. (1997). Pragmatic Experimentalism and the Derivation of the Categories, In: Brunning, J., Forster, P. (Eds.) The Rule of Reason. Toronto: University of Toronto Press, pp. 120–138.

    Google Scholar 

  • Santaella-Braga, L. (1994). Peirce’s broad concept of mind. European Journal for Semiotic Studies 6(3,4), 399–411.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sarkar, S. (1996). Biological information: a skeptical look at some central dogmas of molecular biology. In Sarkar, S. (Ed.) The Philosophy and History of Molecular Biology: New Perspectives. Dordrecht: Kluwer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sarkar, S. (2000). Information in genetics and developmental biology: Comments on Maynard Smith. Philosophy of Science 67(2), 208–213.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Savan, D. (1986). Response to T. L. Short. Transactions of the Charles S. Peirce Society: A Quarterly Journal in American Philosophy Summer XXII(2), 125–143.

    Google Scholar 

  • Savan, D. (1987–1988). An Introduction to C. S. Peirce’s Full System of Semeiotic. Toronto Semiotic Circle. Monograph Series of the TSC, Number 1.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shannon, C. E., Weaver, W. (1949). The Mathematical Theory of Communication. Urbana-IL: University of Illinois Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Short, T. L. (1996). Interpreting Peirce’s interpretant: a response to Lalor, Liszka, and Meyers. Transactions of the Charles S. Peirce Society Fall XXXII(4), 488–541.

    Google Scholar 

  • Short, T. L. (1998). What’s the use? Semiotica 122(1/2), 1–68.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sterelny, K. (2000). The ‘genetic program’ program: A commentary on Maynard Smith on information in Biology. Philosophy of Science 67(2), 195–201.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stuart, C. I. J. M. (1985). Bio-informational equivalence. Journal of Theoretical Biology 113, 611–636.

    Article  PubMed  CAS  Google Scholar 

  • Tiercelin, C. (1995). The relevance of Peirce’s semiotic for contemporary issues in cognitive science. In Haaparanta, L., Heinamaa, S. (Eds.) Mind and Cognition: Philosophical Perspectives on Cognitive Science and Artificial Intelligence. Acta Philosophica Fennica 58, pp. 37–74

    Google Scholar 

  • Williams, N. (1997). Biologists cut reductionist approach down to size. Science 277(5325), 476–477.

    Article  PubMed  CAS  Google Scholar 

  • Wynnie, J. A. (2000). Information and structure in Molecular Biology: Comments on Maynard Smith. Philosophy of Science 67(3), 517–526.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2009 Springer Science+Business Media B.V.

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Favareau, D. (2009). Information and Semiosis in Living Systems: A Semiotic Approach. In: Essential Readings in Biosemiotics. Biosemiotics, vol 3. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-1-4020-9650-1_20

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics