1 Introduction

The problem of measuring power in simple games appeared to be solved after the discoveries of the Shapley–Shubik index (Shapley 1953; Shapley and Shubik 1954) and the Banzhaf–Coleman index (Banzhaf 1965; Coleman 1971). Of course, these are not the only power measures (see for instance Fara et al 2014, for more on power measures), but they can be considered as the most important ones. However, both indices, when applied to games with different player sets, have properties that are not intuitive. These issues were first described by Brams (1975) and Brams and Affuso (1976) who showed, using the extension of the EU Council in 1973, that adding new players to a game might increase the power of some old players. Brams (1975) called this discovery the paradox of new members.

Shenoy (1979) derived a similar result when applying power indices not only to the grand coalition but to each of its subcoalitions. Intuitively, players should have more power in smaller coalitions. However, it turned out that in some games there are smaller coalitions in which some players are worse off than in the original larger coalition. In this case, a power index would exhibit the paradox of smaller coalitions.

The latter paradox played a crucial role in the theory of coalition formation in simple games. Shenoy (1979) showed that if a power index does not exhibit the paradox of smaller coalitions on a simple game, then there is a minimal winning coalition which is core stable—that is, which will not be left by any group of players. Dimitrov and Haake (2008) relaxed this condition and showed that it is sufficient that any coalition has at least one subcoalition in which each player is not worse off. This seems like a fair generalization of Shenoy’s result; however, I will show that in the case of monotonic power indices, it is still quite restricting.

The initial work of Brams and Affuso (1976) derived results on how likely the paradox is to appear. I follow a different approach and investigate the connection between the paradox and the monotonicity of a power index. The relevant definitions can be found in Sect. 2; I also show there that the paradoxes of Shenoy and Brams are, in a sense, equivalent. Two versions of the paradox of new members are investigated in Sect. 3. In particular, it is shown that they are exhibited by any monotonic power index on (almost) every simple game that can be extended. The two versions of the paradox of smaller coalitions are under consideration in Sect. 4, where I show that they are exhibited if players are not almost symmetrical. The condition derived there is both sufficient and necessary for the Shapley–Shubik index. I close the article by briefly discussing the consequences of the incompatibility of monotonicity and the paradoxes’ not being exhibited.

2 Four paradoxes and an axiom

2.1 Preliminaries

Let \(\Omega \) be a universe of players, and let \(\mathcal P_f\left( \Omega \right) \) be the collection of finite subsets of \(\Omega \), called coalitions.Footnote 1 Throughout the paper, when I talk about a player set N, N is finite. A simple game is a function \(v:\mathcal P_f\left( \Omega \right) \rightarrow \left\{ 0,1\right\} \) with \(v\left( \emptyset \right) =0\), such that \(v\left( S\right) \le v\left( T\right) \) for all \(S,T\in \mathcal P_f\) with \(S\subseteq T\), and \(v\left( S\right) +v\left( T\right) \le 1\) for any two disjoint coalitions ST; the latter property is called properness. If \(v(S)=0\) for all coalitions S, v is called the zero game.

A coalition S with \(v\left( S\right) =1\) is called winning. Let S be winning. If \( v\left( S\right) - v\left( S{\setminus }\left\{ i\right\} \right) =1\) then i is called pivotal (in S with respect to v). If S is such that each \(i\in S\) is pivotal, S is called minimal winning. The set of minimal winning coalitions is denoted by \(\mathcal M\left( v\right) \). The carrier \(c\left( v\right) \) of a simple game v is defined as \(c\left( v\right) =\bigcup _{S\in \mathcal M\left( v\right) }S\). Throughout the paper, I consider games with finite carrier. If \(\vert \mathcal M\left( v\right) \vert = 1\), then v is called unanimous. If \(v\left( S\right) - v\left( S{\setminus }\left\{ i\right\} \right) =1\) for all winning coalitions S then i is called a veto player (with respect to v). If \(i\notin c\left( v\right) \), then i is called a null player with respect to v.Footnote 2 For a coalition S, the subgame \(v_S\) is defined as \(v_S\left( T\right) =v\left( S\cap T\right) \) for all coalitions T. In particular, \(c\left( v_S\right) \subseteq S\).

A power index \(\varphi \) maps a simple game v and player set N with \(c(v)\subseteq N\) into \(\mathbb R^N\). A power index \(\varphi \) satisfies the null player axiom if \(\varphi _i\left( v,N\right) =0\) for all \(i\notin c(v)\). I will use the null player axiom only for a few remarks, it will not be necessary for the main results. In particular, I will formulate all paradoxes and theorems for arbitrary player sets that include the carrier of the respective game.

2.2 New members and smaller coalitions

In Brams (1975), the author derives several fundamental properties, a power index should satisfy. One of them is the property of new members. Let v be a simple game. An extension of v is a simple game u such that \(\mathcal M(v)\subseteq \mathcal M(u)\) and \(c(v)\subsetneq c(u)\). A simple game v is extendable if there is an extension u of v. Expecting that the addition of new players to a game would not make old players more powerful, Brams (1975) formulated the following paradox.

Strong paradox of new members :

A power index \(\varphi \) exhibits the strong paradox of new members on a simple game v if there is an extension u of v and a player \(i\in c(v)\) such that \(\varphi _i\left( u,N\right) >\varphi _i\left( v,N\right) \) for all player sets N with \(c(u)\subseteq N\).

The definition of an extension is quite strict (in Lemma 1, the set of extendable simple games is characterized), and does not capture a very prominent historical case of an extension of a council: namely, the extension of the EU Council of Ministers in 1973 (see Table 1) that has been analyzed by Brams and Affuso (1976). It can easily be seen that some coalitions (for instance, France, Germany and Italy) had a majority before but not after 1973. A weak extension of a simple game v is a simple game u such that \(c(v)\subsetneq c(u)\) and \(v(S)\ge u_{c(v)}(S)\) for all coalitions S. This means that instead of only adding new winning coalitions, old winning coalitions might be removed. Clearly, every non-trivial extension is a weak extension with \(v(S)= u_{c(v)}(S)\).

Weak paradox of new members :

A power index \(\varphi \) exhibits the weak paradox of new members on a simple game v if there is a weak extension u of v and a player \(i\in c(v)\) such that \(\varphi _i\left( u,N\right) >\varphi _i\left( v,N\right) \) for all player sets N with \(c(u)\subseteq N\).

As every extension of a game is also a weak extension, the paradox of new members indeed implies its weak version. Note that a weak extension of a game can easily be obtained by keeping the votes of old players constant, adding new players with votes, and increasing the quota that is necessary for a coalition to be winning (see, for instance, the extension of the EU Council in 1979 in Table 1).

Table 1 Votes and quotas in the EU Council before the Treaty of Nice

A similar paradox in a different framework appeared in Shenoy (1979). The author was not interested in the extension of games by new players. Rather, he applied power indices on games and subgames. In the expectation that players would be more powerful in smaller coalitions, he formulated the following paradox.

Weak paradox of smaller coalitions :

A power index \(\varphi \) exhibits the weak paradox of smaller coalitions on a simple game v if there are winningFootnote 3 coalitions \(S,T\subseteq c(v)\), \(T\subseteq S\), and \(i\in c\left( v_T\right) \) such that \(\varphi _i\left( v_S,N\right) >\varphi _i\left( v_T,N\right) \) for all player sets N with \(c(v_S)\subseteq N\).

Originally, this paradox was not called weak; however, given more recent developments, this name seems appropriate. Dimitrov and Haake (2008) commented on this paradox as it plays a role when looking for stable coalitions. They introduced a weaker condition on a power index and a simple game by requiring that the following stronger paradox is not exhibited.

Strong paradox of smaller coalitions :

A power index \(\varphi \) exhibits the strong paradox of smaller coalitions on a simple game v if there is a winning coalition \(S\subseteq c(v)\) such that for all \(T\subseteq S\) there is \(i\in c\left( v_T\right) \) with \(\varphi _i\left( v_S,N\right) >\varphi _i\left( v_T,N\right) \) for all player sets N with \(c(v_S)\subseteq N\).

Hence, if each (non-minimal) winning coalition has at least one winning sub-coalition where each member gets at least the same payoff, a power index does not exhibit this stronger paradox. The following easy observation closes this subsection.

Proposition 1

A power index \(\varphi \) exhibits the strong paradox of new members on a simple game v if and only if there is a simple game u such that \(\varphi \) exhibits the weak paradox of smaller coalitions on u.

Proof

Let \(\varphi \) exhibit the weak paradox of smaller coalitions on the simple game u. Then, there are winning coalitions \(S,T\subseteq c(u)\) and a player \(i\in c\left( u_T\right) \) such that \(T\subseteq S\) and \(\varphi _i\left( u_S,N\right) >\varphi _i\left( u_T,N\right) \) for all player sets N with \(c(u_S)\subseteq N\). As \(u_S\) is an extension of \(u_T\), the strong paradox of new members follows.

On the other hand, if \(\varphi \) exhibits the strong paradox of new members on v, there are an extension u of v and a player \(i\in c(v)\) such that \(\varphi _i\left( u,N\right) >\varphi _i\left( v,N\right) \) for all player sets N with \(c(u)\subseteq N\). As \(v=u_{c\left( v\right) }\), the weak paradox of smaller coalitions follows. \(\square \)

2.3 Monotonic power indices

In the next two sections, I show that the following axiom, which is satisfied for instance by the Shapley–Shubik index (Shapley and Shubik 1954) and the Banzhaf–Coleman index (Banzhaf 1965; Coleman 1971), is responsible for the paradoxes.Footnote 4

Monotonicity :

A power index \(\varphi \) is called monotonic Footnote 5 if for all simple games uv and all N where \(c(u)\cup c(v)\subseteq N\) it holds that \(\varphi _i\left( v,N\right) > \varphi _i\left( u,N\right) \) for all \(i\in N\) such that

$$\begin{aligned}&v\left( S\right) - v\left( S{\setminus }\left\{ i\right\} \right) \ge u\left( S\right) - u\left( S{\setminus }\left\{ i\right\} \right) \quad \text {for all } S\subseteq N,\\ \text {and}\quad&v\left( S\right) - v\left( S{\setminus }\left\{ i\right\} \right) > u\left( S\right) - u\left( S{\setminus }\left\{ i\right\} \right) \quad \text {for some } S\subseteq N. \end{aligned}$$

It can easily be seen that if i is a null player in u but not in v then monotonicity implies that i has strictly greater power in v than in u; in particular, if the null player axiom is, additionally, satisfied then i’s power in v is strictly positive.

3 The paradox of new members

Before any results on the exhibition of the strong paradox of new players are derived, I shall answer the question: what games are extendable at all? To formulate the next lemma, I need the following definition. A simple game v is called strong if \(v\left( S\right) +v\left( c(v){\setminus } S\right) =1\) for all \(S\subseteq c(v)\). That means, it is not only required that the complement of a winning coalition [in c(v)] is losing, but also that the complement of a losing coalition [in c(v)] is winning.

Lemma 1

A simple game v is extendable if and only if it is not strong.

Proof

Let v be a strong game. Then, there are exactly \(2^{\vert c(v)\vert -1}\) winning coalitions contained in c(v). Suppose there is an extension u of v. Then, v has exactly \(2^{\vert c(u)\vert -1}\) winning coalitions that are contained in c(u). As u is an extension of v, it must have at least \(2^{\vert c(u)\vert -1}+1\) winning coalitions in c(u). Hence, u cannot be proper, i.e., it cannot be an extension of v.

On the other hand, let v not be strong. Then, there is a nonempty coalition S such that \(v\left( S\right) =v\left( c(v){\setminus } S\right) =0\). Let \(k\notin c(v)\) and u be the (unique) simple game with minimal winning coalitions \(\mathcal M\left( v\right) \cup \left\{ S\cup \left\{ k\right\} \right\} \). Then, u is a non-trivial extension of v. \(\square \)

The good news is that extendable games can easily be identified. From a theoretical perspective, these games can now easily be handled and much is already known about them. The following theorem, however, shows that if a simple game is extendable then any monotonic power index exhibits the strong paradox of new members on it.

Theorem 1

Let \(\varphi \) be a monotonic power index. Then, \(\varphi \) does not exhibit the strong paradox of new members on a simple game v if and only if v is strong.

Proof

If v is strong, it is not extendable and thus \(\varphi \) cannot exhibit the paradox. So, let v not be strong. Then, there is a nonempty coalition \(S\subseteq c(v)\) such that \(v\left( S\right) =v\left( c(v){\setminus } S\right) =0\). Let \(k\notin c(v)\) and let u be the simple game with minimal winning coalitions \(\mathcal M\left( v\right) \cup \left\{ S\cup \left\{ k\right\} \right\} \). Obviously, \(c(u)=c(v)\cup \left\{ k\right\} \). Let N be a player set containing c(u), let \(i\in S\), and let \(T\subseteq N\). Suppose that T is such that i is pivotal in T with respect to v. As \(k\notin c(v)\), this means that i is also pivotal in \(T{\setminus }\left\{ k\right\} \) with respect to v. In particular, \(u\left( T\right) \ge u\left( T{\setminus }\left\{ k\right\} \right) = v\left( T{\setminus }\left\{ k\right\} \right) =1\). Further, the only minimal winning coalition with respect to u that contains k is \(S\cup \left\{ k\right\} \), and therefore it contains i as well. This means that k cannot be pivotal (with respect to u) in any coalition that does not contain i. Hence, \(u\left( T{\setminus }\left\{ i\right\} \right) =u\left( T{\setminus }\left\{ i,k\right\} \right) =v\left( T{\setminus }\left\{ i,k\right\} \right) =0\). Therefore,

$$\begin{aligned} u\left( T\right) - u\left( T{\setminus }\left\{ i\right\} \right) \ge v\left( T\right) - v\left( T{\setminus }\left\{ i\right\} \right) \end{aligned}$$
(1)

for all \(T\subseteq N\) in which i is pivotal with respect to v. If T is such that i is not pivotal in T with respect to v, then \(v\left( T\right) - v\left( T{\setminus }\left\{ i\right\} \right) =0\) and Eq. (1) holds as well. Further,

$$\begin{aligned} u\left( S\cup \left\{ k\right\} \right) - u\left( \left( S\cup \lbrace k\rbrace \right) {\setminus }\left\{ i\right\} \right) = 1 > 0 = v\left( S\cup \left\{ k\right\} \right) - v\left( \left( S\cup \lbrace k\rbrace \right) {\setminus }\left\{ i\right\} \right) \end{aligned}$$

as \(v\left( S\cup \left\{ k\right\} \right) =0\). Hence, by monotonicity, \(\varphi _i\left( u,N\right) >\varphi _i\left( v,N\right) \). \(\square \)

The following corollary is an easy consequence of the foregoing proof. It states that for every simple game v that is not strong and for every player, whether or not he is a null player with respect to v, an extension of v can be found that makes this player better off.

Corollary 1

Let \(\varphi \) be a monotonic power index and let v be a simple game that is not strong. Then, for each \(i\in \Omega \), there is an extension u of v such that \(\varphi _i\left( u,N\right) >\varphi _i\left( v,N\right) \) for each N with \(c(u)\cup \left\{ i\right\} \subseteq N\).

Proof

Let v be a simple game that is not strong. If \(i\in c(v)\), there is \(S\subseteq c(v)\) such that \(v(S)=v(c(v){\setminus } S)=0\) and \(i\in S\). Using the construction in the proof of Theorem 1, an extension u of v can be obtained with \(\varphi _i(u,N)>\varphi _i(v,N)\) for all N with \(c(v)\subseteq N\).

If \(i\notin c(v)\), there is \(S\subseteq c(v)\) such that \(v(S)=v(c(v){\setminus } S)=0\). Let u be the simple game with minimal winning coalitions \(\lbrace S\cup \lbrace i\rbrace \rbrace \cup \mathcal M(v)\). Then, by monotonicity, \(\varphi _i(u,N)>\varphi _i(v,N)\) for each N with \(c(u)\cup \left\{ i\right\} \subseteq N\), as i is not pivotal in any coalition with respect to v but is pivotal in \(S\cup \lbrace i\rbrace \) with respect to u.

The remainder of this section will deal with weak extensions. Note that every game can be weakly extended; I have already mentioned how it can be done for weighted voting games in Sect. 2. And, again, monotonicity will imply the paradox on almost all games. A dictatorship is a simple game v with \(c(v)=\lbrace i\rbrace \) for a player \(i\in \Omega \). In such a game, a decision can be made by i only, independently of the player set that v is applied to. Note that if there is a veto player in a strong game v then v is a dictatorship.

Theorem 2

Let \(\varphi \) be a monotonic power index. Then, \(\varphi \) exhibits the weak paradox of new members on all simple games that are not dictatorships.

Proof

Let v be a game that is not a dictatorship and let \(N'\) be a player set with \(c(v)\subseteq N'\). I first show that there exist a game \(v'\) and a player \(i\in c(v')\) such that \(v'\) is not strong, \(v'(S)\le v(S)\) for all coalitions S, and \(\varphi _i(v,N')\le \varphi _i(v',N')\). If v is not strong, choose \(v'=v\). If v is strong, there is \(i\in c(v)\) that is not contained in all minimal winning coalitions (otherwise, v would be a dictatorship). Let \(S\in \mathcal M(v)\) such that \(i\notin S\) and let \(v'\) be the simple game that is defined by

Then, \(v'(T)-v'(T{\setminus }\lbrace i\rbrace )\ge v(T)-v(T{\setminus }\lbrace i\rbrace )\) for all \(T\subseteq N'\) and

$$\begin{aligned} v'(S\cup \lbrace i\rbrace )-v'(S)=v(S\cup \lbrace i\rbrace )-0=1>v(S\cup \lbrace i\rbrace )-v(S). \end{aligned}$$

Hence, \(\varphi _i(v,N')<\varphi _i(v',N')\) by monotonicity of \(\varphi \).

By Corollary 1, there is an extension u of \(v'\) such that \(\varphi _i(u,N)>\varphi _i(v',N)\ge \varphi _i(v,N)\) for all N with \(c(u)\subseteq N\). Since, in particular, u is a weak extension of v, the claim is proved. \(\square \)

The following corollary is now clear and the proof is omitted.

Corollary 2

Let \(\varphi \) be a monotonic power index and let v be a simple game which is not a dictatorship. Then, for each \(i\in \Omega \), there is a weak extension u of v such that \(\varphi _i\left( u,N\right) >\varphi _i\left( v,N\right) \) for each N with \(c(u)\subseteq N\).

4 The paradox of smaller coalitions

The strong paradox of new members and the weak paradox of smaller coalitions are equivalent in the sense that if one is exhibited by a power index on an arbitrary simple game then there is another game on which the other one is exhibited. Nonetheless, they are not exhibited on the same set of games. In the next subsection, a condition on simple games is derived that is necessary for the non-exhibition of the strong paradox of smaller coalitions by a monotonic power index. In Sect. 4.2, I will show that this condition is also sufficient in case of the Shapley–Shubik index.

4.1 Avoiding the paradox of smaller coalitions

The key problem of monotonic power indices is that veto players have more power in larger coalitions than in smaller ones. The next lemma illustrates this observation. Recall that \(\mathcal M(v)\) is the collection of minimal winning coalitions with respect to v. For a player i, let \(\mathcal M_i(v)\) be the collection of those minimal winning coalitions that contain i. Clearly, \(\mathcal M_i(v)\ne \emptyset \) if and only if \(i\in c(v)\).

Lemma 2

Let \(\varphi \) be a monotonic power index and let v be a simple game such that \(\varphi \) does not exhibit the strong paradox of smaller coalitions on v. Then, for each winning coalition S, either \(v_S\) is an unanimous game or there is no veto player with respect to \(v_S\).

Proof

Let S be a winning coalition with players \(i,j\in S\) such that i is pivotal in S and j is neither null player nor pivotal. Let N be a player set with \(c\left( v_S\right) \subseteq N\) and let \(T\subseteq N\) be such that \(v_{S{\setminus }\left\{ j\right\} }(T) - v_{S{\setminus }\left\{ j\right\} }(T{\setminus }\lbrace i\rbrace )=1\). Then, \(v_S(T)=1\) and \(v_S(T{\setminus }\lbrace i\rbrace )\le v(S{\setminus }\lbrace i\rbrace )=0\). On the other hand, let \(T\subseteq N\) such that \(T\in \mathcal M_j\left( v_S\right) \). (Such a T exists as j is not a null player in S.) Then, i is pivotal in T with respect to \(v_S\) but \(v_{S{\setminus }\left\{ j\right\} }\left( T\right) =v_S\left( T{\setminus }\lbrace j\rbrace \right) =0\). Hence, \(\varphi _i\left( v_S,N\right) >\varphi _i\left( v_{S{\setminus }\lbrace j\rbrace },N\right) \) by strong monotonicity—that is, \(\varphi \) exhibits the strong paradox of smaller coalitions on v. \(\square \)

Lemma 2 reveals that a monotonic power index will exhibit the paradox on a number of simple games. This has been elaborated for instance in Karos (2014). The next theorem characterizes the class of simple games that have the property described in Lemma 2.

Theorem 3

Let v be a simple game. Then, v satisfies the necessary condition of Lemma 2 if and only if \(\vert \mathcal M_j\left( v_S\right) \vert =\vert \mathcal M_k\left( v_S\right) \vert \) for all winning coalitions \(S\subseteq c(v)\) and all \(j,k\in c\left( v_S\right) \).

Proof

First, let \(\vert \mathcal M_i\left( v_S\right) \vert =\vert \mathcal M_j\left( v_S\right) \vert \) for all winning coalitions S and all \(i,j\in c\left( v_S\right) \). Let T be a winning coalition. If \(\mathcal M_i\left( v_T\right) =\mathcal M\left( v_T\right) \) for all \(i\in c\left( v_T\right) \), then \(v_T\) is unanimous. If \(\vert \mathcal M_i\left( v_T\right) \vert <\vert \mathcal M\left( v_T\right) \vert \) for all \(i\in c\left( v_T\right) \), then there are no veto players with respect to \(v_T\). Hence, v satisfies the condition in Lemma 2.

Now, let v be a simple game such that for each winning coalition S, the game \(v_S\) is either unanimous or does not contain any veto players. The claim is proved by induction on the cardinality of c(v), n. For \(n=1\) and \(n=2\), it is obviously true. So, let v be such that \(n=3\). Then, v is either the three player unanimity game or the symmetric game in which each coalition of at least two players is winning. In both cases, the theorem is true.

Let now \(n\ge 4\). If v is the unanimous game, the claim is clearly true. So let v not be unanimous. In this case, there cannot be any veto players with respect to v by our initial condition. In particular, \(v_{c(v){\setminus }\left\{ i\right\} }\) is not the zero game for any \(i\in c\left( v\right) \). For a player \(i\in c(v)\) let

$$\begin{aligned} D_i=\lbrace l\in c(v){\setminus }\lbrace i:i\notin c(v_{c(v){\setminus }\lbrace l\rbrace })\rbrace \end{aligned}$$

and

$$\begin{aligned} E_i=\lbrace l\in c(v):i\in c(v_{c(v){\setminus }\lbrace l\rbrace })\rbrace . \end{aligned}$$

In words, \(D_i\) contains all those players l that “help” i in the sense that after one of them is removed from the game, i becomes a null player. The set \(E_i\) contains those players l on whose presence i does not depend: If l is removed, i still has some (maybe less) power. Note that c(v) can be partitioned into \(D_i\), \(E_i\) and \(\lbrace i\rbrace \). In particular, \(E_i\ne \emptyset \) as otherwise \(c(v)\in \mathcal {M}_i(v)\) in contradiction to v’s not being unanimous. I first show that \(\vert \mathcal M_j\left( v\right) \vert =\vert \mathcal M_k\left( v\right) \vert \) for all \(j,k\in c(v)\). Consider two cases.

  1. 1.

    Let \(k\in D_j\). In this case \(\mathcal M_j(v)\subseteq \mathcal M_k(v)\) or, equivalently, \(\mathcal M(v_{c(v){\setminus }\lbrace k\rbrace })\subseteq \mathcal M(v_{c(v){\setminus }\lbrace j\rbrace })\). I will show that these two sets are equal. For this purpose, note the following observation. Let \(i\in E_j\) and \(l\in D_j\). Then, \(\mathcal M_j(v_{c(v){\setminus }\lbrace i\rbrace })\subseteq \mathcal M_l(v_{c(v){\setminus }\lbrace i\rbrace })\) and the induction hypothesis delivers that \(\vert \mathcal M_j(v_{c(v){\setminus }\lbrace i\rbrace })\vert = \vert \mathcal M_l(v_{c(v){\setminus }\lbrace i\rbrace })\vert \). Hence, \(\mathcal M_j(v_{c(v){\setminus }\lbrace i\rbrace })=\mathcal M_l(v_{c(v){\setminus }\lbrace i\rbrace })\) for all \(i\in E_j\) and all \(l\in D_j\). Assume now that \(\mathcal M_j(v)\subsetneq \mathcal M_k(v)\)—that is, there is a coalition \(S\in \mathcal M_k(v_{c(v){\setminus }\lbrace j\rbrace })\). Then, \(E_j\subseteq S\). For, if there were \(i\in E_j{\setminus } S\), then \(S\in \mathcal M_k(v_{c(v){\setminus }\lbrace i\rbrace })=\mathcal M_j(v_{c(v){\setminus }\lbrace i\rbrace })\) (as seen before), which would mean that S were a minimal winning coalition containing j, in contradiction to \(S\in \mathcal M(v_{c(v){\setminus }\lbrace j\rbrace })\). Recall that \(E_j\ne \emptyset \), let \(i\in E_j\), and let \(T\in \mathcal M(v_{c(v){\setminus }\lbrace i\rbrace })\) (such a T exists, as \(v_{c(v){\setminus }\lbrace i\rbrace }\) is not the zero game). Suppose \(j\notin T\). Then, \(T\notin \mathcal M_j(v_{c(v){\setminus }\lbrace i\rbrace })=\mathcal M_l(v_{c(v){\setminus }\lbrace i\rbrace })\) for any \(l\in D_j\). In particular, \(T\subseteq c(v){\setminus }( D_j\cup \lbrace i,j\rbrace )\subseteq E_j{\setminus }\lbrace i\rbrace \subsetneq S\), contradicting the minimality of S. Hence, \(j\in T\) for all \(T\in \mathcal M(v_{c(v){\setminus }\lbrace i\rbrace })\). This means that \(v_{c(v){\setminus }\lbrace i,j\rbrace }\) is the zero game and therefore, i is pivotal in \(v_{c(v){\setminus }\lbrace j\rbrace }\). By the initial condition, \(v_{c(v){\setminus }\lbrace j\rbrace }\) must be unanimous, and as \(S\in \mathcal M(v_{c(v){\setminus }\lbrace j\rbrace })\) it must hold that \(\lbrace S\rbrace = \mathcal M(v_{c(v){\setminus }\lbrace j\rbrace }) \supseteq \mathcal M(v_{c(v){\setminus }\lbrace k\rbrace })\). Hence, as \(v_{c(v){\setminus }\lbrace k\rbrace }\) is not the zero game, \(\lbrace S\rbrace =\mathcal M(v_{c(v){\setminus }\lbrace k\rbrace })\), in contradiction to \(S\in \mathcal M_k(v)\). Hence, there is no \(S\in \mathcal M_k(v_{c(v){\setminus }\lbrace j\rbrace })\) and therefore \(\mathcal M_k(v)=\mathcal M_j(v)\).

  2. 2.

    Let \(k\in E_j\). I first show that there is \(i\in N\) such that \(\vert \mathcal M_j(v_{c(v){\setminus }\lbrace i\rbrace })\vert = \vert \mathcal M_k(v_{c(v){\setminus }\lbrace i\rbrace })\vert \). By the induction hypothesis, it is sufficient to show that there is \(i\in N\) such that either both j and k are null players in \(v_{c(v){\setminus }\lbrace i\rbrace }\) or neither of them is. Equivalently, either \(i\in D_j\cap D_k\) or \(i\notin D_j\cup D_k\). Suppose that such i does not exist. In this case, \(c(v)=D_j\cup D_k\) and \(D_j\cap D_k=\emptyset \). From the first part of the proof, it follows that \(l\in D_j\) if and only if \(j\in D_l\). In particular, each \(l\in D_j\) is a null player in \(v_{c(v){\setminus }\lbrace j\rbrace }\). Hence, \(v(c(v){\setminus } (D_j\cup \lbrace j\rbrace ))=v(c(v){\setminus }\lbrace j\rbrace ) = 1\). But this means that \(v(D_k)=v(c(v){\setminus } D_j)=1\) and for the same reasons \(v(D_j)=1\). Hence, as \(D_j\) and \(D_k\) are disjoint, v is not proper—a contradiction. Therefore, there must be \(i\in N\) such that \(\vert \mathcal M_j(v_{c(v){\setminus }\lbrace i\rbrace })\vert = \vert \mathcal M_k(v_{c(v){\setminus }\lbrace i\rbrace })\vert \). For such i it holds that

    $$\begin{aligned}\nonumber \vert \mathcal M(v_{c(v){\setminus }\lbrace j\rbrace })\vert= & {} \vert \mathcal M(v_{c(v){\setminus }\lbrace i,j\rbrace })\vert + \vert \mathcal M(v_{c(v){\setminus }\lbrace k,j\rbrace })\vert - \vert \mathcal M(v_{c(v){\setminus }\lbrace i,k,j\rbrace })\vert \\= & {} \vert \mathcal M(v_{c(v){\setminus }\lbrace i\rbrace })\vert - \vert \mathcal M_j(v_{c(v){\setminus }\lbrace i\rbrace })\vert + \vert \mathcal M(v_{c(v){\setminus }\lbrace k,j\rbrace })\vert - \vert \mathcal M(v_{c(v){\setminus }\lbrace i,k,j\rbrace })\vert \\= & {} \vert \mathcal M(v_{c(v){\setminus }\lbrace i\rbrace })\vert - \vert \mathcal M_k(v_{c(v){\setminus }\lbrace i\rbrace })\vert + \vert \mathcal M(v_{c(v){\setminus }\lbrace k,j\rbrace })\vert - \vert \mathcal M(v_{c(v){\setminus }\lbrace i,k,j\rbrace })\vert \\= & {} \vert \mathcal M(v_{c(v){\setminus }\lbrace i,k\rbrace })\vert + \vert \mathcal M(v_{c(v){\setminus }\lbrace j,k\rbrace })\vert - \vert \mathcal M(v_{c(v){\setminus }\lbrace i,j,k\rbrace })\vert \\= & {} \vert \mathcal M(v_{c(v){\setminus }\lbrace k\rbrace })\vert . \end{aligned}$$

    Consequently,

    $$\begin{aligned} \vert \mathcal M_j(v)\vert= & {} \vert \mathcal M(v)\vert - \vert \mathcal M(v_{c(v){\setminus }\lbrace j\rbrace }) \vert \\= & {} \vert \mathcal M(v)\vert - \vert \mathcal M(v_{c(v){\setminus }\lbrace k\rbrace })\vert \\= & {} \vert \mathcal M_k(v)\vert . \end{aligned}$$

I have shown that \(\vert \mathcal M_j(v)\vert =\vert \mathcal M_k(v)\vert \) for all \(j,k\in c(v)\). By the induction hypothesis \(\vert \mathcal M_j(v_S)\vert =\vert \mathcal M_k(v_S)\vert \) for all subsets \(S\subsetneq c(v)\) and all \(j,k\in c(v_S)\). \(\square \)

The condition on a simple game given in Theorem 3, namely that in every subgame every non-null player is contained in the same number of minimal winning coalitions, is quite strong; it is satisfied, for instance, by simple games in which all players are symmetric. Nevertheless, the latter is not a necessary condition as can be seen in the simple game with minimal winning coalitions \(\lbrace 1,2,3\rbrace ,\lbrace 3,4,5\rbrace \), and \(\lbrace 1,2,4,5\rbrace \).

4.2 The Shapley–Shubik index

The Shapley–Shubik index (Shapley 1953; Shapley and Shubik 1954) is defined as

$$\begin{aligned} \sigma _j(v,N) = \sum _{S\subseteq N, j\in S}\frac{(\vert N\vert - \vert S\vert )!(\vert S\vert -1)!}{\vert N\vert !}(v(S)-v(S{\setminus }\lbrace j\rbrace )). \end{aligned}$$

It is well known that \(\sigma \) does not depend on N, I will therefore simply write \(\sigma (v)\) for \(\sigma (v,N)\). Also, \(\sigma \) is monotonic (Sagonti 1991) and therefore exhibits the strong paradox of smaller coalitions on all games not satisfying the condition in Theorem 3. But this condition is, in fact, both necessary and sufficient.

Corollary 3

Let v be a simple game. Then, the Shapley–Shubik index does not exhibit the strong paradox of smaller coalitions on v if and only if \(\vert \mathcal M_i(v_S)\vert =\vert \mathcal M_j(v_S)\vert \) for all winning coalitions S and all \(i,j\in c(v_S)\).

Proof

By be Lemma 2 and Theorem 3, it is necessary that \(\vert \mathcal M_i(v_S)\vert =\vert \mathcal M_j(v_S)\vert \) for all winning coalitions S and all \(i,j\in c(v_S)\). To show that this is sufficient, I show that \(\sigma _j(v)\le \max _{T\in \mathcal M_j}\frac{1}{\vert T\vert }\) for any such v. In this case, for any coalition S, a minimal winning coalition \(T\subseteq S\) of minimal cardinality delivers higher power for each player in T than S. The claim is shown by induction over \(n=\vert c(v)\vert \). It is clearly true if v is unanimous, in particular, it is true if \(n\le 2\). Hence, let \(n\ge 3\) and let v not be unanimous. Then, \(v_{c(v){\setminus }\lbrace k\rbrace }\) is not the zero game for any k. Let T be a minimal winning coalition of minimal cardinality and let \(j\in T\). Then,

$$\begin{aligned} \sigma _j(v) = \frac{1}{\vert c(v)\vert }\sum _{k\ne j}\sigma _j(v_{c(v){\setminus }\lbrace k\rbrace }) \le \frac{\vert c(v)\vert -1}{\vert c(v)\vert }\frac{1}{\vert T\vert } \le \frac{1}{\vert T\vert } \end{aligned}$$

by the induction hypothesis. \(\square \)

5 Conclusion

I have shown that some natural properties one would expect from power indices contradict each other on many simple games. Nevertheless, these two properties are reasonable in different contexts: while monotonicity seems very natural for games with the same carrier, non-exhibition of the paradox of new players (or smaller coalitions) usually concerns games with different carriers.

There are authors arguing that the paradox of new members is not paradoxical (Felsenthal and Machover 1995) on the grounds that the power of a player is a global property that involves the whole structure of the game. Although this is clearly true, it makes the (equivalent) paradox of smaller coalitions even more peculiar: a player has less power in a smaller coalition despite the fact that this coalition is part of the same game and the only difference is that (other) players are left out.

It therefore seems that monotonic power indices (including the Shapley index and the Banzhaf index) are not the right instrument to measure power in a council or parliament where the formation of coalitions is likely. It rather makes a case for power measures that take into account players’ options both within and outside coalitions, such as the bargaining set (Davis and Maschler 1963), or more recently a class of solutions investigated in Karos (2013) where players’ power is based on bargaining solutions.