Skip to main content
Log in

A Non-factualist defense of the Reflection principle

  • Published:
Synthese Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Are there plausible synchronic constraints on how a subject thinks of herself extended over time? At first glance, Bas van Fraassen’s principle of Reflection seems to prescribe the sort of epistemic authority one’s future self should be taken by one to have over one’s current epistemic states. (The gist of this principle is that I should now believe what I’m convinced I will believe tomorrow.) There has been a general consensus that, as a principle concerning epistemic authority, Reflection does not apply to epistemically non-ideal agents. I agree with this, but argue here that it misses the point of Reflection. Rather than an epistemic principle concerning reasons for belief, Reflection concerns the semantics of belief avowal. I present a non-factual interpretation of Reflection, argue that the principle provides a constraint on the ways in which one can reflectively endorse one’s future epistemic self, and say something about the logic governing such an interpretation.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

References

  • Armendt B. (1992) Dutch strategies for diachronic rules: When believers see the sure loss coming. PSA: Proceedings of the Biennial Meeting of the Philosophy of Science Association 1: 217–229

    Google Scholar 

  • Arnzenius F., Elga A., Hawthorne J. (2004) Bayesianism, infinite decisions, and binding. Mind 113(450): 251–282

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bovens L. (1995) ‘P and I will believe that not-P’: Diachronic constraints on rational belief. Mind 104: 737–760

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Broome J. (2000) Normative requirements. In: Dancy J. (ed) Normativity. Blackwell, Oxford, pp 78–99

    Google Scholar 

  • Broome J. (2004) Reasons. In: Wallace R. J., Pettit P., Scheffler S., Smith M. (eds) Reason and value. Clarendon Press, Oxford, pp 28–55

    Google Scholar 

  • Broome J. (2007) Wide or narrow scope?. Mind 116(462): 359–370

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Christensen D. (1991) Clever bookies and coherent beliefs. Philosophical Review 100(2): 229–246

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Christensen D. (1996) Dutch-book arguments depragmatized: Epistemic consistency for partial believers. The Journal of Philosophy 93(9): 450–479

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Elga A. (2000) Self-locating belief and the sleeping beauty problem. Analysis 60(2): 143–147

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Evnine S. J. (2007) Personhood and future belief: Two arguments for something like Reflection. Erkenntnis 67: 91–110

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Foley R. (1994) How should future opinion affect current opinion?. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 54(4): 747–766

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Foley R. (2001) Intellectual trust in oneself and others. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Hild M. (1998a) The coherence argument against conditionalization. Synthese 115: 229–258

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hild M. (1998b) Auto-epistemology and updating. Philosophical Studies 92: 321–361

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jeffrey R. (1988) Conditioning, kinematics and exchangeability. In: Skyrms B., Harper W. L. (eds) Causation, chance, and credence. Kluwer, Dordrecht

    Google Scholar 

  • Kolodny N. (2005) Why be rational?. Mind 114: 509–563

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lewis D. (1979) Attitudes de dicto and de se. The philosophical review 88: 513–543

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Loewer B., Belzer M. (1983) Dyadic deontic detachment. Synthese 54: 295–318

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Maher P. (1992) Diachronic rationality. Philosophy of Science 59: 120–141

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Plantinga A. (1993) Warrant: The current debate. Oxford University Press, New York

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • van Fraassen B. C. (1984) Belief and the will. Journal of Philosophy 81: 235–256

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • van Fraassen B. C. (1985) Empiricism in the philosophy of science. In: Curchland P. M., Hooker C. A. (eds) Images of science. University of Chicago Press, Chicago

    Google Scholar 

  • van Fraassen B. C. (1993). Rationality does not require conditionalization. In Ullmann-Margalit E. (ed.) The Israel colloquium studies in the history, philosophy, and sociology of science. (Vol. 5). Dordrecht, Kluwer

    Google Scholar 

  • van Fraassen B. C. (1995) Belief and the problem of Ulysses and the sirens. Philosophical Studies 77(1): 7–37

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Weisberg J. (2007) Conditionalization, reflection, and self-knowledge. Philosophical Studies 135(2): 179–197

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Stephanie Beardman.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Beardman, S. A Non-factualist defense of the Reflection principle. Synthese 190, 2981–2999 (2013). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-012-0114-y

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-012-0114-y

Keywords

Navigation