Skip to main content
Log in

The Gauthier Contract: Applicable or Not?

  • Published:
Res Publica Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

In a 2013 article, David Gauthier noted upon the twenty-fifth anniversary of the publication of Morals by Agreement that his contractarian approach to morality had found a niche among ‘some of those who remain unpersuaded by either Kantianism or utilitarianism’. In this article I will focus on Pareto optimization and I will argue that the Gauthier contract, even in spite of the article’s revisions, is still less useful for consultation purposes than Gauthier is assuming. To highlight the conceptual distance that I think separates the Gauthier contract from real-world circumstances—a separation that is greater than Gauthier supposes—I will focus on the problem of ‘civic defection’. The point is not for us to repudiate as such the deliverances of the Gauthier model, but simply to use caution in our deployment of the model, and, in order to access the full extent of the model’s offerings, to resist the temptation to deploy it in the service of purposes which it is not capable of accomplishing.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. ‘[o]n the maximizing conception it is not interests in the self, that take oneself as object, but interests of the self, held by oneself as subject, that provide the basis for rational choice and action’ (Gauthier 1986, p. 7).

  2. To be a utility maximizer is not necessarily to maximize one’s non-tuistic preferences. I follow Christopher Morris: contractarians can defend the view that utility-maximization involves the maximization of agent-relative coherent preference. Such a conception of maximization allows for both non-tuistic and tuistic preferences.

  3. Pareto optimality is a way of measuring social efficiency: an outcome is Pareto optimal if no other outcome would make every participant at least as well off and at least one participant strictly better off.

  4. Also, Gauthier (1997, pp. 132–148) and Gauthier (1993, pp. 24–40).

  5. My critiques draw to some extent on Murray (2007) and also Southwood (2010).

  6. Without the political domain, how else in a large liberal democracy would morals be enforced?

  7. See Putnam (2000, pp. 31–64, 277–284), Galston (2001a, p. 16), Elshtain (1995, pp. 1–36), Galston (2004, pp. 263–266), Galston (2001a, pp. 217–234), and Dagger (1997, pp. 132–153).

  8. Activities which are being abandoned include voting, demonstrating, lobbying, and running for office. See Putnam (1995, pp. 664–683), Rahn and Transue (1998, pp. 545–565), and Costa and Kahn (2001).

  9. Their partial defections are representable with the preference relation R, where xRy means that x is at least as good as y. If agents believe that xRy and not that yRx, then for them, xPyx is preferred to y. The participation of the civic defectors is describable as yPx, where y is civic defection and x is civic participation. Yet, typically, they also believe that yPz, where z is a further step – defection from society as such – and y is merely an initial step of civic defection. In selecting both yPx and yPz, they are electing to be first-stage cooperators and second-stage defectors.

  10. For evidence that liberal democratic governance is more functional the more that the citizens participate, see Putnam (1993) and Knack (2002).

  11. See Taylor (1985), Crowder (2002), Gans (1991), Grabb et al. (1999), and (Bellah et al. 2007).

  12. American Millennials are increasingly viewing the Pareto-optimizing impact of civic defectors as being just as great as the Pareto-optimizing impact of civic participants. Instead of choosing lives of civic service the Millennials are turning increasingly to the private sector, believing that their capacity to promote a Pareto-optimal outcome is just as great through civic defection as it is through second-stage participation. See Duncan (2012), Lapin (2012), and Denz (2012).

  13. The institutional system is an indifferent cooperator and not an unconditional cooperator. It does not cooperate at all times—the roads are not always reliably repaired.

  14. Suppose it were objected that at America’s stage two the decision-making scenario is already moralized because its stage-one moral features are already shaping the citizens, and thus the case study does not resemble Gauthier. I respond that the empirical evidence suggests that the second stage is inseparable from the first, because in a society of strangers who lack relational discernment mechanisms, the choice has to be for both, and not just for one.

  15. Think of the senior citizens who donate their time to public causes, the altruistic polling station operators, the citizens who serve for lesser pay on county juries, and the volunteer political campaign workers.

  16. Civic defection of course has been well-traveled in the literature; here I am just saying it is not capable of being solved via a Pareto-optimization strategy. For instance, Brian Barry has argued that Gauthier's contractarianism collapses because it fails to provide a satisfactory answer to the question of why agents should obey the rules if at some time some other action path offers a better prospect of promoting their conception of the good (Barry 1995, p. 34). Examples of works that have highlighted the free-rider problem in a general-purpose civic context include Schumpeter (2008), and Arneson (2009).

  17. Civic defection is just one of numerous different real-world problems that could potentially be referenced to demonstrate the inability of the Gauthier contract to offer consultation help. Others are the tendency of persons to change their minds in the course of their cooperative efforts; the inconsistencies of their behaviors in crises; their inability to discern each other’s intentions with the certainty that Gauthier anticipates; and their propensity to deceive each other.

  18. For McClennen, ‘the failure of any arrangement to generate a Strictly Pareto-Optimal outcome means that the arrangement in question fails to meet a condition of individual rationality’ (McClennen 2010, p. 531). Also, see Roth (1977, pp. 64-65).

  19. Note that while defection is just as rational as participation (if not more so, because of the agent’s other considerations), it too is not decisively rational because the agent might have an individual cocktail of non-Pareto-optimizing considerations that suggest participation.

  20. See Bogaert et al. (2008), Also, Murphy et al. (2011). Another good overview of social value orientation and the social dilemmas literature is Van Lange et al. (2013); and also Henrich et al. (2005). There is likewise literature on the neurodynamics of prosocial behavior (Declerck et al. 2013).

  21. This point has already to some extent been made, although in a different way and not in a manner that is backed with recent social science studies, by Hubin (1991); also on point is McCracken and Shaw (1995); a response is available in Dimock (1999); again, see Morris and Ripstein (2001).

  22. This conviction is a reiteration of what he said earlier in Morals: ‘[a] community in which most individuals are disposed to comply with fair and optimal agreements and practices, and so to base their actions on joint cooperative strategies, will be self-sustaining’ (Gauthier 1986, p. 182).

  23. See Biel et al. (2008).

  24. Such a response is certainly consistent with Gauthier’s sentiments in chapter six of Morals, where he suggests that real-world persons act for motives and principles that are otherwise than the motives and principles of his ideal bargainers.

  25. This is true, I think, even though I grant that he does not see its normative deliverances as being one-to-one replacements for real-world cooperative values (Gauthier 1991, p. 27). In numerous passages in Morals Gauthier also expresses his confidence in the real-world traction of his contract: in chapter six he says that ‘Constrained maximization thus links the idea of morals by agreement to actual moral practice’ (Gauthier 1986, p. 168).

  26. ‘…the force of the social contract is not found simply in its being an agreement. Rather its force lies in its being the nearest approximation to an agreement in a context in which literal agreement is not possible but would be desirable. We cannot literally choose the terms of our interaction, but we can determine what terms we would rationally choose, from an ex ante standpoint that does not privilege the actual course that our interaction has taken’ (Gauthier 2013, p. 619).

  27. This includes especially the setups which are nefarious (Gauthier 1991, p. 29).

  28. Earlier, in Morals, Gauthier confirms these sentiments. For instance, in chapter six of Morals he says that ‘Constrained maximization thus links the idea of morals by agreement to actual moral practice’ (Gauthier 1986, p. 168). Elsewhere, he says that ‘we may defend actual moral principles by reference to ideal co-operative arrangements, and the closer the principles fit, the stronger the defense’ (Gauthier 1991, p. 28).

References

  • Aristotle. 1941, 2001. Politics, nicomachean ethics. In The basic works of Aristotle, ed. Richard McKeon. New York, NY: Random House Publishers.

  • Arneson, Richard. 2009. The supposed right to a democratic say. In Contemporary debates in political philosophy, ed. Thomas Christiano, and John Christman, 197–212. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Barry, Brian. 1995. Justice as impartiality. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bellah, Robert, et al. 2007. Habits of the heart: Individualism and commitment in American life, 2nd ed. Berkeley, CA: University of California Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Biel, Anders, Daniel Eek, Tommy Garling, and Mathias Gustafson. 2008. Promoting cooperation in social dilemmas via fairness norms and group goals. New York, NY: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bogaert, Sandy, Christophe Boone, and Carolyn Declerck. 2008. Social value orientation and cooperation in social dilemmas: A review and conceptual model. British Journal of Social Psychology 47: 453–480.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Braybrooke, David. 1991. Gauthier’s foundations for ethics under the test of application. In Contractarianism and Rational Choice, ed. Peter Vallentyne. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Costa, Dora, and Matthew Kahn. 2001. Understanding the decline in social capital, 1952–1998. National Bureau of Economic Research Working Paper No. 8295.

  • Crowder, George. 2002. Liberalism and value pluralism. London: Continuum.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dagger, Richard. 1997. Civic virtues: Rights, citizenship, and republican liberalism. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Declerck, Carolyn H., Christophe Boone, and Griet Emonds. 2013. When do people cooperate? The neuroeconomics of prosocial decision making. Brain and Cognition 81: 95–117.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Denz, Kimberly. 2012. Young people and public sector careers. Govloop.com. http://www.govloop.com/forum/topics/young-people-and-public-sector-careers. Accessed 3 August 2013.

  • Dimock, Susan. 1999. Defending non-tuism. Canadian Journal of Philosophy 29: 251–274.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Duncan, David. 2012. Why do our best and brightest end up in Silicon Valley and not in D.C.? The Atlantic. http://www.theatlantic.com/technology/archive/2012/05/why-do-our-best-and-brightest-end-up-in-silicon-valley-and-not-dc/256767/. Accessed 11 September 2015.

  • Elshtain, Jean. 1995. Democracy on trial. New York: Basic Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Galston, William. 2001a. Can patriotism be turned into civic engagement? The Chronicle of Higher Education 16 Nov: 16.

  • Galston, William. 2001b. Political knowledge, political engagement, and civic education. Annual Review of Political Science 4: 217–234.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Galston, William. 2004. Civic education and political participation. Political Science and Politics 37: 263–266.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Galston, William. 2007. Civic knowledge, civic education, and civic engagement: A summary of recent research. International Journal of Public Administration 30: 623–642.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gans, Herbert. 1991. Middle american individualism: Political participation and liberal democracy. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gauthier, David. 1986. Morals by agreement. New York, NY: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gauthier, David. 1993. Between Hobbes and Rawls. In Rationality, justice and the social contract: Themes from morals by agreement, ed. David Gauthier, and Robert Sugden, 24–40. Hertfordshire: Harvester Wheatsheaf.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gauthier, David. 1997. Political contractarianism. Journal of Political Philosophy 5: 132–148.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gauthier, David. 2013. Twenty-five on. Ethics 123: 601–624.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Grabb, Edward, et al. 1999. The origins of american individualism: reconsidering the historical evidence. Canadian Journal of Sociology 24: 511–533.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Henrich, J., et al. 2005. ‘Economic man’ in cross-cultural perspective: Behavioral experiments in 15 small-scale societies. Behavioral and Brain Sciences 28: 795–855.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hubin, Donald. 1991. Non-tuism. Canadian Journal of Philosophy 21: 441–468.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Knack, Stephen. 2002. Social capital and the quality of government: Evidence from the states. American Journal of Political Science 46: 772–785.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lange, Van, A.M. Paul, Jeff Joireman, Craig D. Parks, and Eric Van Dijk. 2013. The psychology of social dilemmas: A review. Organizational Behavior and Human Decision Processes 120: 125–141.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lapin, Andrew. 2012. Young feds say bureaucracy, inefficiency keeping their peers away. Govexec.com. http://www.govexec.com/management/2012/05/young-feds-say-bureaucracy-inefficiency-keeping-their-peers-away/55618/. Accessed 5 August 2013.

  • McCracken, Janet, and Bill Shaw. 1995. Social contracts and business ethics. Business Ethics Quarterly 5: 297–312.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McClennen, Edward. 2010. Rational choice and moral theory. Ethical Theory and Moral Practice 13: 521–540.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Moehler, Michael. 2015. Rational cooperation and the Nash bargaining solution. Ethical Theory and Moral Practice 18: 577–594.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Morris, Christopher, and Arthur Ripstein (eds.). 2001. Practical rationality and preference: essays for David Gauthier. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Murphy, Ryan, Kurt Ackermann, and Michel Handgraaf. 2011. Measuring social value orientation. Judgment and Decision Making 6: 771–781.

    Google Scholar 

  • Murray, Malcolm. 2007. The moral wager: Evolution and contract. New York, NY: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Putnam, Robert. 1993. Making democracy work: Civic traditions in modern Italy. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Putnam, Robert. 1995. Tuning in, tuning out: The strange disappearance of social capital in America. PS. Political Science and Politics 28: 664–683.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Putnam, Robert. 2000. Bowling alone. New York: Simon and Schuster.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Roth, A.E. 1977. Individual rationality and Nash’s solution to the bargaining problem. Mathematics of Operations Research 2: 64–65.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schumpeter, Joseph. 2008. Capitalism, socialism, and democracy. Harper Perennial Modern Classics.

  • Southwood, Nicholas. 2010. Contractualism and the foundations of morality. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Rahn, Wendy, and John Transue. 1998. Social trust and value change: The decline of social capital in American Youth, 1976–1995. Political Psychology 19: 545–565.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Taylor, Charles. 1985. Atomism. In Philosophy and the human sciences: Philosophical papers, vol. 2, 187–210. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

I am grateful to two anonymous reviewers for their revision suggestions.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Jeremy Neill.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Neill, J. The Gauthier Contract: Applicable or Not?. Res Publica 23, 1–22 (2017). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11158-015-9294-x

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11158-015-9294-x

Keywords

Navigation