Skip to main content
Log in

Retroductive Analogy: How to and How Not to Make Claims of Good Reasons to Believe in Evolutionary and Anti-Evolutionary Hypotheses

  • Published:
Argumentation Aims and scope Submit manuscript

    We’re sorry, something doesn't seem to be working properly.

    Please try refreshing the page. If that doesn't work, please contact support so we can address the problem.

Abstract

This paper describes an argumentative fallacy we call ‘Retroductive Analogy.’ It occurs when the ability of a favored hypothesis to explain some phenomena, together with the fact that hypotheses of a similar sort are well supported, is taken to be sufficient evidence to accept the hypothesis. This fallacy derives from the retroductive or abductive form of reasoning described by Charles Sanders Peirce. According to Peirce’s account, retroduction can provide good reasons to pursue a hypothesis but does not, by itself, provide good reasons to believe the hypothesis. In successful applications of retroduction, pursuit leads to the accumulation of evidence. In retroductive analogy, comparison with other successful hypotheses is substituted for the genuine pursuit of evidence. We describe a case from ecological genetics in which retroduction plays a legitimate role as the initial phase of an ongoing research program that serves to accumulate genuine evidence for a hypothesis. We also examine two contexts in which the fallacy of retroductive analogy occurs: in defenses of Intelligent Design Theory and in defense of some hypotheses in Evolutionary Psychology.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. The same line of argument and the same SETI example are used in Dembski (2002).

References

  • Behe, Michael. 1996. Darwin’s black box. New York: Free Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cain, A.J., and P.M. Sheppard. 1950. Selection in the polymorphic land snail Cepaea nemoralis. Heredity 4: 275–294.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cain, A.J., and P.M. Sheppard. 1953. Natural selection in Cepaea. Genetics 39: 89–116.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dembski, William. 1997. The design inference: Eliminating chance through small probabilities. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dembski, William. 2002. No free lunch. Lanham: Rowman & Littlefield.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dembski, William. 2005. Expert witness report: The scientific status of intelligent design. Kitzmiller et al. v. Dover Area School District. http://www.designinference.com/. Retrieved 18 June 2008.

  • Fitelson, Branden, Christopher Stephens, and Elliott Sober. 1999. How not to detect design—critical notice: William A. Dembski, The design inference. Philosophy of Science 66: 472–488.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Godfrey-Smith, Peter. 2001. Information and the argument from design. In Intelligent design creationism and its critics, ed. Robert T. Pennock. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gould, Stephen Jay, and Richard C. Lewontin. 1979. The spandrels of San Marco and the Panglossian Paradigm: A critique of the adaptationist programme. Proceedings of the Royal Society of London B 205: 581–598.

  • Kitcher, Philip. 1993. The advancement of science. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lamotte, Maxime. 1951. Rescherches sur la structure genetique des populations naturelles de Cepaea nemoralis L. Supplement to Bulletin Biologique de France et de Belguque 35: 1–239.

  • Lamotte, Maxime. 1959. Polymorphism of natural populations of Cepaea nemoralis. Cold Spring Harbor Symposium on Quantitative Biology 24: 65–86.

  • Mealey, Linda. 1995. The sociobiology of sociopathy: An integrated evolutionary model. Behavioral and Brain Sciences 18 (3): 523–599.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Miller, Kenneth R. 2005. Expert testimony, Kitzmiller et. al. v. Dover area school district. http://www.talkorigins.org/faqs/dover/day1am.html. Retrieved 18 June 2008.

  • Peirce, Charles Sanders. 1901. Hume on miracles. In Collected papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, vol. VI, eds. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss. Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1935.

  • Peirce, Charles Sanders. 1901/1903. Abduction and induction. In The philosophy of Peirce: Selected writings, ed. Justus Buchler. New York: Harcourt Brace, 1940.

  • Peirce, Charles Sanders. c. 1910. A letter to Paul Carus. In Collected papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, vol. VIII, ed. Arthur Burks. Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1958.

  • Pennock, Robert T. 2001. Naturalism, evidence, and creationism: The case of Philip Johnson. In Intelligent design creationism and its critics, ed. Robert T. Pennock. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sheppard, P.M. 1951. Fluctuations in the selective value of certain phenotypes in the polymorphic land snail Cepeae nemoralis (L.). Heredity 5: 125–134.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sober, Elliot. 2000. Philosophy of biology, 2nd ed. Boulder: Westview Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Chuck Ward.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Ward, C., Gimbel, S. Retroductive Analogy: How to and How Not to Make Claims of Good Reasons to Believe in Evolutionary and Anti-Evolutionary Hypotheses. Argumentation 24, 71–84 (2010). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10503-009-9129-z

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10503-009-9129-z

Keywords

Navigation