Skip to main content
Log in

Content: Covariation, control and contingency

  • Published:
Synthese Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

The Representational Theory of the Mind allows for psychological explanations couched in terms of the contents of propositional attitudes. Propositional attitudes themselves are taken to be relations to mental representations. These representations (partially) determine the contents of the attitudes in which they figure. Thus, Representationalism owes an explanation of the contents of mental representations. This essay constitutes an atomistic theory of the content of formally or syntactically simple mental representation, proposing that the content of such a representation is determined by the intersection of the representation's correlational and control properties. The theory is distinguished from standard information-based accounts of mental content in allowing that the relevant correlations be contingent while insisting on an efferent aspect to mental content. The theory on offer allows for a natural explanation of misrepresentation, finds a niche for the notion ofnarrow content, welcomes radical first person fallibility with respect to questions of content, admits of mental ambiguity and recognizes that the future of a psychological agent is a factor in determining the content of the agent's present psychological states.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

References

  • Adams, Fred, David Drebushenko, Gary, Fuller, and Robert Stecker: 1990, ‘Narrow Content: Fodor's Folly’,Mind and Language 5, 213–29.

    Google Scholar 

  • Baker, Lynne Rudder: 1987,Saving Belief, Princeton University Press, Princeton.

    Google Scholar 

  • Block, Ned: 1986, ‘Advertisement for a Semantics for Psychology’, in P. A. French, T. E. Uehling and H. K. Wettstein (eds.),Midwest Studies in Philosophy: Studies in the Philosophy of Mind 10, 615–78.

    Google Scholar 

  • Burge, Tyler: 1979, ‘Individualism and the Mental’, in P. A. French, T. E. Uehling, and H. K. Wettstein (eds.),Midwest Studies in Philosophy: Studies in Metaphysics 4, 73–122.

    Google Scholar 

  • Burge, Tyler: 1986, ‘Individualism and Psychology’,Philosophical Review 95, 3–46.

    Google Scholar 

  • Churchland, Paul: 1988, ‘Perceptual Plasticity and Theoretical Neutrality’,Philosophy of Science 55, 167–87.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cummins, Robert: 1989,Meaning and Mental Representation, MIT Press, Cambridge, MA.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cummins, Robert: 1992, ‘Conceptual Role Semantics and the Explanatory Role of Content’,Philosophical Studies 65, 104–27.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dennett, Daniel: 1969,Content and Consciousness, Humanities Press, New York.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dennett, Daniel: 1978, ‘Brain Writing and Mind Reading’, in hisBrainstorms, Bradford Books, Montgomery, pp. 39–50.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dretske, Fred I.: 1981,Knowledge and the Flow of Information, MIT Press, Cambridge, MA.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dretske, Fred I.: 1986, ‘Misrepresentation’, in R. Bogdan (ed.),Belief, Oxford University Press, Oxford, pp. 3–17.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dretske, Fred I.: 1988,Explaining Behavior, MIT Press, Cambridge, MA.

    Google Scholar 

  • Egan, Francis M.: 1989, ‘What's Wrong with the Syntactic Theory of Mind’,Philosophy of Science 56, 664–74.

    Google Scholar 

  • Field, Hartry: 1978, ‘Mental Representation’,Erkenntnis 13, 9–61.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fodor, Jerry: 1975,The Language of Thought, Thomas Y. Crowell, New York.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fodor, Jerry: 1980, ‘Methodological Solipsism Considered as a Research Strategy in Cognitive Psychology’,Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3, 63–110.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fodor, Jerry: 1986, ‘Why Paramecia Don't Have Mental Representations’, in P. A. French, T. E. Uehling and H. K. Wettstein (eds.),Midwest Studies in Philosophy X, 3–23.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fodor, Jerry: 1987,Psychosemantics, MIT Press, Cambridge, MA.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fodor, Jerry: 1990a, ‘Observation Reconsidered’, as reprinted in hisA Theory of Content, MIT Press, Cambridge, MA, pp. 231–51.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fodor, Jerry: 1990b, ‘A Reply to Churchland's “Perceptual Plasticity and Theoretical Neutrality”’, as reprinted in Fodor'sA Theory of Content, MIT Press, Cambridge, MA, pp. 253–63.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fodor, Jerry: 1990c, ‘Semantics Wisconsin Style’, as reprinted in hisA Theory of Content, MIT Press, Cambridge, MA, pp. 31–49.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fodor, Jerry: 1990d, ‘A Theory of Content, I & II’, as reprinted in hisA Theory of Content, MIT Press, Cambridge, MA, pp. 51–136.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fodor, J. A. and Z. Pylyshyn: 1988, ‘Connectionism and Cognitive Architecture: A Critical Analysis’,Cognition 28, 3–71.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fodor, J. A. and E. LePore: 1992,Holism, Basil Blackwell, Oxford.

    Google Scholar 

  • Harman, Gilbert: 1973,Thought, Princeton University Press, Princeton.

    Google Scholar 

  • Harman, Gilbert: 1982, ‘Conceptual Role Semantics’,Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 23, 432–3.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jackson, Frank and Philip Pettit: 1988, ‘Functionalism and Broad Content’,Mind XCVII, 381–400.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kosslyn, S.: 1980,Imagery and Mind, Harvard University Press, Cambridge, MA.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kosslyn, S.: 1983,Ghosts in the Mind's Machine: Creating and Using Images in the Brain, Norton, New York.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, David: 1972, ‘Psychophysical and Theoretical Identifications’,Australasian Journal of Philosophy 50, 249–58.

    Google Scholar 

  • Loar, Brian: 1981,Mind and Meaning, Cambridge University Press, Cambridge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Loar, Brian: 1982, ‘Conceptual Role and Truth-Conditions’,Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 23, 272–83.

    Google Scholar 

  • Maloney, J. Christopher: 1986a, ‘Psychology without Content’,Behaviorism 14, 159–82.

    Google Scholar 

  • Maloney, J. Christopher: 1986b, ‘Sensuous Content’,Philosophical Papers 15, 131–54.

    Google Scholar 

  • Maloney, J. Christopher: 1989,The Mundane Matter of the Mental Language, Cambridge University Press, Cambridge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Maloney, J. Christopher: 1990, ‘Mental Misrepresentation’,Philosophy of Science 57, 445–58.

    Google Scholar 

  • Maloney, J. Christopher: 1991, ‘Saving Psychological Solipsism’,Philosophical Studies 61, 267–83.

    Google Scholar 

  • Millikan, Ruth Garrett: 1984,Language, Thought and Other Biological Categories, MIT Press, Cambridge, MA.

    Google Scholar 

  • Papineau, David: 1988,Reality and Representation, Basil Blackwell, Oxford.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pollock, John: 1989,How to Build a Person, MIT Press, Cambridge, MA.

    Google Scholar 

  • Putnam, Hilary: 1975, ‘The Meaning of Meaning’ in hisMind, Language and Reality, Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, pp. 215–71.

    Google Scholar 

  • Putnam, Hilary: 1988,Representation and Reality, MIT Press, Cambridge, MA.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pylyshyn, Zenon: 1984,Computation and Cognition, MIT Press, Cambridge, MA.

    Google Scholar 

  • Quine, Willard van Orman: 1960,Word and Object, MIT Press, Cambridge, MA.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rescorla, R. A.: 1988, ‘Pavlovian Conditioning: Its Not What You Think’,American Psychologist 43, 151–60.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rowlands, M.: 1989, ‘Discussion of Jackson's and Pettit's “Functionalism and Broad Content”’,Mind XCVIII, 269–75.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rumelhart, David E. and James L. McClelland: 19??,Parallel Distributed Processing, Vols. I and II, MIT Press, Cambridge, MA.

  • Schiffer, Stephen: 1987,Remnants of Meaning, MIT Press, Cambridge, MA.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sellars, W.: 1963, ‘Empiricism and the Philosophy of Mind’, in hisScience, Perception and Reality, Routledge & Kegan Paul, London.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shepard, R. N. and Lynn A. Cooper: 1982,Mental Images and Their Transformations, MIT Press, Cambridge, MA.

    Google Scholar 

  • Smolensky, Paul: 1988, ‘On the Proper Treatment of Connectionism’,Behavioral and Brain Sciences 11, 1–74 (with peer commentary).

    Google Scholar 

  • Stalnaker, Robert: 1984,Inquiry, MIT Press, Cambridge, MA.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stampe, D. W.: 1975, ‘Show and Tell’, in B. Freedet al. (eds.)Forms of Representation, North Holland Press, New York.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stampe, D. W.: 1977, ‘Towards a Causal Theory of Linguistic Representation’, in P. French, T. Uehling and H. Wettstein (eds.),Midwest Studies in Philosophy 2, 42–63.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stampe, D. W.: 1987, ‘Verificationism and a Causal Account of Meaning’,Synthese 69, 107–37.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stampe, D. W.: 1990, ‘Content, Context and Explanation’, in E. Villanueva (ed.),Information, Semantics and Epistemology, Basil Blackwell, Oxford, pp. 134–52.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stich, Stephen: 1983,From Folk Psychology to Cognitive Science: The Case Against Belief, MIT Press, Cambridge, MA.

    Google Scholar 

  • Teller, Paul: forthcoming, ‘A Contemporary Look at Emergence’.

  • Tolliver, Joseph: 1987, ‘Disjunctivitis’,Mind and Language 3, 64–70.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tolliver, Joseph: ‘Calibrational Semantics’ (typescript).

  • Turkkan, J. S.: 1989, ‘Classical Conditioning: The New Hegemony’,Behavioral and Brain Sciences 12, 121–79 (including peer commentary).

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Maloney, J.C. Content: Covariation, control and contingency. Synthese 100, 241–290 (1994). https://doi.org/10.1007/BF01063811

Download citation

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/BF01063811

Keywords

Navigation