Skip to main content
Log in

Derrida's language-games

  • Published:
Topoi Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Conclusion

In previous essays (1973, 1975, 1977) I have praised Derrida's contributions to philosophical dialogue and also insisted on their limitations. The considerations raised in this present essay do not lead me to a position that is less ambivalent.

Philosophy is a particular language-game. Like any other, it has its constitutive rules; or, perhaps better: its practice has certain distinctive features by means of which we recognize philosophizing and distinguish it from other linguistic activities. None of this can be set down in the form of necessary and sufficient conditions, and there always will be large areas of controversy about the paradigms themselves. Nonetheless there are philosophers, and they generally acknowledge Plato, Aristotle, Leibniz, Hume, and even some of their colleagues as also being philosophers. This acknowledgement holds even where there is philosophical disagreement - as must inevitably be the case, in view of the dialogical character of philosophical discourse.

Derrida occasionally enters into the dialogue, as do many others - poets, novelists, critics, diplomats, attorneys, cooks, barbers, and babysitters. These occasional contributions to philosophical dialogue differ in focus, in style, and in lack of self-referentiality from the works which constitute the main corpus of philosophy. Some might wish to say, as if the matter were paradoxical, that such contributions are both philosophical and not philosophical, or that they are neither philosophy nor not-philosophy. That might be as good a thing to say as anything. The practice of philosophy is complex and has many levels. Those who are acknowledged as its finest practitioners have a focus, a style, and a respect for where questions begin and end. Derrida does not share these qualities, and does not care to share them. That is no reason to ignore his work, but it is sufficient to explain why philosophers do not recognize it as a contribution to the central corpus of philosophy.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

References

  • Austin, J. L.: 1955/1975 How to Do Things with Words; The William James Lectures delivered at Harvard University in 1955. J.O. Urmson and Marina Sbisà (eds.), second edition, Harvard University Press, Cambridge, MA.

    Google Scholar 

  • Austin, J. L.: 1961, Philosophical Papers, J. O. Urmson and G. J. Warnock (eds.) Clarendon Press, Oxford.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bubner, Rüdiger: 1974, ‘Zur Struktur eines tranzendentalen Argu-Ments” Kantstudien 65 Sonderheft, pp. 15–27. This Sonderheft is the same as G. Funke (ed.), Akten des 4 Internationalen Kant-Kongresses, Mainz, 1974, de Gruyter, Berlin/New York.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bubner, Rüdiger: 1975, ‘Kant, Transcendental Arguments, and the Problem of the Deduction’, Review of Metaphysics XXVIII, 453–467.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bubner, Rüdiger: 1981, ‘L'autoréférence comme structure des arguments transcendantaux’, Les études philosophiques 4, 385–398.

    Google Scholar 

  • Derrida, Jacques: 1967a, La voix et le phénomène, Presses Universitaires de France, Paris. Tr. David Allison, Speech and Phenomena, Northwestern University Press, Evanston, IL, 1973.

    Google Scholar 

  • Derrida, Jacques: 1967b, De la grammatologie, Minuit, Paris.

    Google Scholar 

  • Derrida, Jacques: 1967c, L'écriture et la différence, Le Seuil, Paris.

    Google Scholar 

  • Derrida, Jacques: 1986, Parages, Galilée, Paris.

    Google Scholar 

  • Derrida, Jacques: 1988, ‘The Politics of Friendship’, Journal of Philosophy LXXXV, 632–644.

    Google Scholar 

  • Garver, Newton: 1965, ‘Varieties of Use and Mention’, Philosophy and Phenomenological Research XXVI, 230–238.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Garver, Newton: 1967, ‘Analyticity and Grammar’, The Monist L, 397–425. Reprinted in L. W. Beck (ed.), Kant Studies Today, Open Court, La Salle, IL, pp. 245–273.

    Google Scholar 

  • Garver, Newton: 1973, ‘Preface’, English translation of Derrida 1967a. Reprinted in John Canfield (ed.), The Philosophy of Wittgenstein, Vol. 15, Garland Press, New York, 1986.

  • Garver, Newton: 1975, ‘Grammar and Metaphysics’, in D. Ihde and R. M. Zaner (eds.), Selected Studies in Phenomenology and Existential Philosophy, vol. 5, Nijhoff, The Hague.

    Google Scholar 

  • Garver, Newton: 1977, ‘Derrida on Rousseau on Writing’, Journal of Philosophy LXXIV, 663–673.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Garver, Newton: 1990, ‘Wittgenstein and the Critical Tradition’, History of Philosophy Quarterly VII, 227–240.

    Google Scholar 

  • Grice, Paul and Strawson, Peter F.: 1956, ‘In Defense of a Dogma’, Philosophical Review LXVI, 141–158. Reprinted in Paul Grice, Studies in the Ways of Words, Harvard University Press, Cambridge, MA, 1989.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hampshire, Stuart: 1989, Innocence and Experience, Harvard University Press, Cambridge, MA.

    Google Scholar 

  • Heidegger, Martin: 1962, Kant and the Problem of Metaphysics, tr. James S. Churchill, Indiana University Press, Bloomington/London.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jacques, Francis: 1979, Dialogiques: Recherches logiques sur le dialogue, Presses Universitaires de France, Paris.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kant, Immanuel: (KrV) Kritik der reinen Vernunft, in Kant, Werkausgabe, Bände III and IV.

  • Kant, Immanuel: (Fortschritte) ‘Über die von der königlichen Akademie der Wissenschaften zu Berlin für das Jahr 1791 ausgesetzte Preisfrage: Welche sind die wirklichen Fortschritte, die die Metaphysik seit Leibnizens und Wolffs Zeiten in Deutschland gemacht hat?’, in Werkausgabe, Band VI. Page references are given both to this edition and also to the original edition by Rink (Königsberg, 1804).

  • Kant, Immanuel: 1968, Werkausgabe, 12 vol., Wilhelm Weischedel (ed.), Suhrkamp, Frankfurt.

    Google Scholar 

  • Montaigne, Michel: 1962, Essais, two vol., Maurice Rat (ed.), Garnier, Paris.

    Google Scholar 

  • Quine, Willard van drman: 1951, ‘Two Dogmas of Empiricism’, Philosophical Review LXI. Reprinted in Quine, 1953, pp. 20–46.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Quine, Willard van Orman: 1953, From a Logical Point of View, Harvard University Press, Cambridge, MA.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rorty, Richard: 1989, Contingency, Irony, and Solidarity, Cambridge University Press, Cambridge/New York.

    Google Scholar 

  • Royce, Josiah: 1969, Basic Writings, two vol., John J. McDermott (ed.), University of Chicago Press, Chicago.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ryle, Gilbert: 1960, ‘Letters and Syllables in Plato’, Philosophical Review LXIX, 431–451. Reprinted in Ryle, 1971, Vol. I, pp. 54–71.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ryle, Gilbert: 1971 Collected Papers, two vol., Hutchinson & Co., London.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wittgenstein, Ludwig: (LW) Last Writings on the Philosophy of Psychology, Preliminary Studies for Part II of Philosophical Investigations, G. H. von Wright and Heikki Nyman (eds.), tr. C. G. Luckhardt and Maximilian A. E. Aue, Basil Blackwell, Oxford, 1982.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wittgenstein, Ludwig: (OC) On Certainty, Blackwell, Oxford, 1969. References are to numbered sections.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wittgenstein, Ludwig: (PI) Philosophical Investigations second edition, tr. G. E. M. Anscombe, Blackwell, Oxford, 1958. References are to numbered sections in Part I.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wittgenstein, Ludwig: (RF) Remarks on Frazer's Golden Bough, Rush Rhees (ed.), tr. A. C. Miles, Humanities Press, Atlantic Highlands, NJ, 1979.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wittgenstein, Ludwig: (TLP) Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus, tr. David F. Pears/Brian McGuinness, Routledge and Kegan Paul, London, 1961.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Garver, N. Derrida's language-games. Topoi 10, 187–198 (1991). https://doi.org/10.1007/BF00141339

Download citation

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/BF00141339

Keywords

Navigation