Skip to main content
Log in

Primary Intersubjectivity: Empathy, Affective Reversibility, ‘Self-Affection’ and the Primordial ‘We’

  • Published:
Topoi Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

The arguments advanced in this paper are the following. Firstly, that just as Trevarthen’s three subjective/intersubjective levels, primary, secondary, and tertiary, mapped out different modes of access, so too response is similarly structured, from direct primordial responsiveness, to that informed by shared pragmatic concerns and narrative contexts, to that which demands the distantiation afforded by representation. Secondly, I propose that empathy is an essential mode of intentionality, integral to the primary level of subjectivity/intersubjectivity, which is crucial to our survival as individuals and as a species. Further to this last point, I argue that empathy is not derived on the basis of intersubjectivity, nor does it merely disclose intersubjectivity, rather it is constitutive of intersubjectivity at the primary level. Empathy is a direct, irreducible intentionality separable in thought from the other primary intentional modes of perception, rationality, memory and imagination, but co-arising with these. In regard to the inter-personal level, the concrete relations with others, primary empathy is both the ground for the possibility of the secondary manifestations—pity, sympathy, perspective taking, etc., and motivates them. Thirdly, it is the movement in the core of subjectivity initially generated by shifting attention between the ‘I’ and ‘we’ perspectives and later ‘solidified’ through affect to become shifting identification, which opens up the intersubjective domain. So we can affirm that we are not only born into sociality but our sociality goes to the roots of our being as Husserl, Heidegger and Merleau-Ponty have claimed.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Representationalists—Dretske (1981, 1995), Fodor (1981), Devitt (1996), Tye (2009), Clark (2002), Chalmers (2004), Block (2003), Hohwy (2007). What I dispute strongly in the representationalist account is the pre-eminence given to cognitive capacities over non-cognitive capacities and the tendency to claim that this account is the definitive account. On the basis of the work of the philosophers mentioned below, it is clear that representation plays no role at the level of primary subjectivity. However, I do recognise the important though more circumscribed than previously supposed role that cognitive capacities and representation may play at the secondary level of subjectivity and that they are crucial at the tertiary level of intersubjective engagement wherein metadiscursive capacities are paramount. For analyses which decisively repudiate the hegemony of representationalist accounts see Gallagher et al. (2013), Gallagher & Zahavi (2010), Gallagher (2006), Zahavi (2004), Varela et al (1991), Gallagher (2005), Zahavi (2005), Dreyfus (1998), Kelly (2002).

  2. Trevarthen (1998).

  3. Gallagher (2005).

  4. This paper is a revised, condensed version of a chapter from my doctoral thesis “The problem of the other in the work of Merleau-Ponty: from epistemology to ethics” (2012). The thesis sought to explicate Merleau-Ponty’s implicit ethics on the basis of his accounts of alterity and also drew on recent neuroscience as empirical support to vindicate some of his claims.

  5. See the later discussions of Batson (2009) and Coplan (2012).

  6. “What is the Reversibility Thesis? The reversibility thesis is the thesis that self, other and world are inherently relational—not in the obvious and trivial sense that they stand in relation to each other, can affect each other, that there are actual and potential causal connections between them. This without question is so and these relations occur between entities that are external to each other. Merleau-Ponty’s Reversibility Thesis, however, proposes that self, other and world are internally related, that there is interdependence at the level of ontology. What does it mean to be internally related? The other—whether other subjectivities or the otherness of the world and things—is essential for self-awareness and vice versa. No self can be apprehended without an-other. Ipseity and alterity are mutually dependent and this interdependence is both pervasive and intrinsic. What is at stake in the reversibility thesis is whether it is able to overcome skeptical objections in assuring real communication and at the same time avoid any collapse into solipsism in assuring real difference. The other must be a genuine, irreducible Other” (Daly 2013).

  7. Merleau-Ponty (1968, 1964b) (VI: 133, 138, 142, 147, 153, 155, 215, 263, 272; VI: 176, 182, 187, 194, 200, 204, 268, 316, 325).

  8. Zur Phänomenologie de Intersubjektivität III, in Husserliana XV, 74–75 and also in Erste Philosophie II in Husserliana VIII, 480 These references represent approximations to the quote above, which has been frequently cited by other researchers. Merleau-Ponty also writes: “Transcendental subjectivity is a revealed subjectivity, revealed to itself and to others, and is for that reason an intersubjectivity” (pp. 361, 421, 419). Zahavi (2002)—furnishes the most conclusive and thorough account of this scholarly dispute. He writes: “As I have already indicated, scholars have occasionally claimed that not all of Merleau-Ponty’s references to passages in Husserl’s unpublished manuscripts should be taken at face value. Spiegelberg, for instance, points out that Merleau-Ponty’s repeated quotation of a statement in Husserl’s Krisis to the effect that transcendental subjectivity is an intersubjectivity is actually not contained in this work. But although Husserl might not have made exactly that statement in Krisis, he did so elsewhere, for instance in Zur Phänomenologie der Intersubjektivität III. Here Husserl writes: “I have to distinguish: the currently transcendentally phenomenologizing subjectivity (as an actual ego—monad), and transcendental subjectivity as such; the latter turns out to be transcendental intersubjectivity, which includes the transcendentally phenomenologizing subjectivity within itself” (Hua XV 74–75). … [and further] he writes that transcendental subjectivity in its full universality is exactly intersubjectivity (Hua VIII 480).” Zahavi (2002, p. 24), this issue.

  9. For explanations of phenomenological methodology see Zahavi (2005): 4–6, Gallagher (2012), Merleau-Ponty (1945, 2006).

  10. Trevarthen Op. Cit. (1998, pp. 15–46).

  11. Bateson (1979).

  12. Coplan (2012).

  13. Zahavi (2001, 2005, 2007).

  14. Sheets-Johnstone (2006).

  15. This serves a similar function to the ‘reflective equilibrium’ in various accounts of ethical justification (Rawls 1971; Daniels 1996; Scanlan 2002). However, it is important to note that ‘reflective equilibrium’ remains in the conceptual domain, as the designation indicates.

  16. To be very clear, I am not suggesting that empathy or the embodied, embedded intuitions can replace the evaluative and judgment capacities. Nor am I endorsing unreflective intuition as a reliable arbiter of moral value. However, I am proposing that pre-reflective empathy and embodied, embedded intuitions may serve to alert us if these evaluative and judgment capacities have been co-opted for destructive purposes as in the cases of dehumanisation and demonization.

  17. Varela (1992).

  18. Batson (2009).

  19. Which Batson acknowledges in a footnote.

  20. Scheler (1913).

  21. ibid p. 8.

  22. ibid p. 9.

  23. Zahavi, Op. Cit. (2007, p. 37), this issue.

  24. Batson, Op. Cit. (2009, p. 3).

  25. Concept 1: Knowing Another Person’s Internal state, Including His or Her Thoughts and Feelings; Concept 2: Adopting the Posture or Matching the Neural Responses of an Observed Other, (see—Husserl, Heidegger, Merleau-Ponty and the various neuroscientific findings Gordon (1995), Dimberg et al. (2000), Hoffman (2000), Lipps (1903), Meltzoff and Moore (1977), Titchner (1909), Preston and de Waal (2002) in Batson (2009); Concept 3: Coming to Feel as Another Person Feels, Hume (1740/1896), Smith (1759/1853), Hatfield et al. (1994), Zahn-Waxler et al. (1992), Hodges and Wegner (1997), Hoffman (2000) in Batson (2009); Concept 4: Intuiting or Projecting Oneself into Another’s Situation was originally inspired by what was termed ‘aesthetic empathy’, wherein artists could project themselves into the subject-matter of their work of art, Stein (1964); Concept 5: Imagining How Another is Thinking and Feeling, Stein (1964); Concept 6: Imagining How One Would Think and Feel in the Other’s Place has various historical antecedents—Adam’s Smith’s “changing places in fancy”, Mead’s “role-taking”, Povinelli’s “cognitive empathy”, Darwell’s “projective empathy” or “simulation” and Piaget’s “perspective taking” or “decentering”; Concept 7: Feeling Distress at Witnessing Another Person’s Suffering. To my mind, distress may arise from two very different orientations; the first is other-oriented and therefore moves naturally into Concept 8 engendering a ‘selfless’ response; the second kind of distress is a self-oriented, parasitic distress; Concept 8: Feeling for Another Who is Suffering, tips the balance from empathic understanding, through responsivity towards empathic action—aimed at relieving the suffering of the other. As Batson writes, this kind of empathy refers to “an other-oriented emotional response elicited by and congruent with the perceived welfare of someone else”. He notes that in the literature this is sometimes termed “pity”, “compassion”, “sympathetic distress” or “sympathy”. But what differentiates it markedly from other versions of empathy is that it is concerned with congruent response and the self truly-leaves-home. The concern is entirely directed at the suffering other, neither as a projected nor introjected ‘project’—but as a genuine other.

  26. Coplan Op Cit. (2012, p. 6).

  27. In both cases being ‘informed’ is preferable to being ‘constrained’.

  28. Bennett and Hacker (2007), drawing a parallel with a quote from Aristotle,—“to say that the soul [psyche] is angry is as if one were to say that the soul weaves or builds. For it is surely better not to say that the soul pities, learns or thinks, but that a man does these with his soul” (De Anima 408b, 12–15)—Bennett and Hacker assert that this is the same as ascribing experiences to the brain—when in fact, these should be ascribed to the human as a whole. Thus the capacities for thinking, reasoning, desiring, planning and imagining cannot be reduced to neural events, but they may be co-arising. The failure to recognize this distinction is the mereological fallacy of neuroscience, p. 132.

  29. Coplan Op. Cit. (2012, p. 6) my italics.

  30. ibid.

  31. See Gallagher Op. Cit. (2005) and Zahavi Op. Cit. (2005) for critiques of simulation accounts (Zahavi, this issue).

  32. Gallagher (2001, p. 91).

  33. Merleau-Ponty (1964c, 1960).

  34. Einfühlung literally, “feeling one’s way into” was originally used in German aesthetics in the late (nineteenth century, which itself was derived from the Greek “empatheia” which is translated as “passion, state of emotion”. It was first translated into English as “empathy” by Titchener (1909), after which it came into common usage in American psychological research. So it would seem that the original sense has become confused and mixed with the word “sympathy”. “Sympathie” (fr) is “affinity between certain things”; the Latin “sympathia” is “community of feeling”: and the Greek “sympatheia” is “Fellow-feeling”. Colwyn Trevarthen has written most cogently on this confusion and he proposes that “the word ‘sympathy’ clearly conveys best the core sense of intersubjective awareness of agency and emotion that works reciprocally between persons” (2012: 466). With apologies to Trevarthen, I will be using the term “empathy” as an umbrella term to encompass all these renderings, which are I propose (perhaps with the exception of the original Greek) able to capture the sense of affective reversibility.

  35. Merleau-Ponty, M. Op. Cit. (1964a, b, c, p. 170); Op. Cit. (1960, p. 217).

  36. Meltzoff and Moore (1995), Adolphs (2000), Gallagher and Hutto (2008), Slaby (2007), Fuchs (2005). Fuchs notes “It was Erwin Strauss [20; p. 151] who aptly distinguished a ‘pathic’ and a ‘gnostic’ component in perception…” p. 135.

  37. Merleau-Ponty (1964a, p. 30).

  38. Merleau-Ponty (1948, fr, 1970).

  39. I propose that the reason why there is such a strong expectation of reciprocity in regard to empathic behaviour is that just as with perception—even if the perceptive relation is asymmetrical and non-reciprocal—the important point is that the other defines an external vantage on the self. So too with empathy—regardless of non-reciprocity, the other still nonetheless defines an external potentially affectively reciprocal vantage on the self. Furthermore, ‘fellow-feeling’/empathy, as I am arguing, is constitutive of subjectivity.

  40. See earlier footnote this paper, Bennett and Hacker pp. 8 and 9.

  41. Zahavi, Op. Cit. (2001).

  42. Zahavi Op. Cit, (2001, p. 155).

  43. Zahavi Op. Cit, (2001, p. 155).

  44. Zahavi Op. Cit, (2001, p. 156).

  45. The empathy account refers to accounts based on the work of both Max Scheler and Edith Stein. That Scheler’s work is titled The Nature of Sympathy and Stein’s On the Problem of Empathy already signals the complications at this early stage in the precise use of terms to cover affectively responsive intersubjective engagements. Nonetheless, both were developed in rejection of the earlier prevailing account of intersubjectivity—the Argument from Analogy.

  46. Zahavi, Op. Cit. (2001, p.165).

  47. Ibid, p. 153.

  48. Ibid, pp. 153 and 154.

  49. At this point (2001) Zahavi’s philosophical interests are directed towards the more cognitively demanding aspects of intersubjectivity. More recently it would seem that he has returned to an examination of the first person perspective and specifically the “we—perspective”. See Zahavi (2013).

  50. My use of the term ‘self-affection’ is consistent with, but not identical to, the interpretations offered by Zahavi (1999, 2005) and Sheets-Johnstone (2006).

  51. The three levels of subjectivity/intersubjectivity—primary, secondary and tertiary—refer to the seminal work of Trevarthen, Op. Cit. (1998).

  52. Merleau-Ponty (1964c, p. 175).

  53. Merleau-Ponty (2006) (pp. 405–407, 470–472, 466–468) Imbalances between these perspectives may I propose lay the grounds for sociopathology and psychopathology.

  54. Gallagher (2005), Zahavi (2005), Fuchs (2008) offer thorough accounts of both the phenomenology and the neuroscience.

  55. Daly (2013).

  56. Sheets-Johnstone, Op. Cit. (2006).

  57. ibid, pp. 362, 363, 364, 365, 366, 376 etc.

  58. ibid, p. 371.

  59. ibid, p. 376.

  60. Zahavi, Op Cit (Zahavi 2005, p. 54).

  61. ibid, pp. 71 and 72.

  62. Merleau-Ponty’s Chapter “Temporality” in The Phenomenology of Perception pp. 410–433, 477–503 and; “time is ‘the affecting of self by self’; *what exerts the effect is time as a thrust and a passing towards a future: what is affected is time as an unfolded series of presents: the affecting agent and affected recipient are one, because the thrust of time is nothing but the transition from one present to another. This ek-stase, this projection of an indivisible power into an outcome which is already present to it, is subjectivity” (p. 495). * footnote—The expression is applied by Kant to the Geműt. Heidegger transfers it to time: ‘Die Zeit is ihren Wesen nach reine Affektion ihrer selbst.’ Kant und das Problem der Metaphysik, pp. 180–181.

  63. Zahavi Op. Cit. (2005, p. 124).

  64. Sheets-Johnstone Op. Cit. (2006, p. 376).

  65. Merleau-Ponty (1993) my italics.

  66. Zahavi (1999).

  67. Sheets-Johnstone, Op Cit, (2006, p. 364).

  68. Merleau-Ponty (1962:360–361, 2006:420, 1945:418–419) my italics.

  69. Restak (2002), Gied et al. (1999).

  70. Eisenberg and Eggum (2009).

  71. The work of Vittorio Gallese on the mirroring mechanisms in the brain offers much in the way of supporting such claims (Gallese, 2004, 2007, 2009, 2010a, b). So too, the work of Jordan Zlatev (2007) which emphasizes the linguistic dimensions.

  72. Trevarthen, Op. Cit. (1998, p. 18).

  73. “In the absence of reciprocity there is no alter ego, since the world of the one then takes in completely that of the other, so that one feels disinherited in favour of the other… co-existence must in all cases be experienced on both sides.” The Phenomenology of Perception (1962:357, 2006:416, 1945:415).

  74. Trevarthen, Op Cit (1998, p. 34, 2012).

  75. Bateson (1979).

  76. Proponents of the Theory Theory school of thought include Baron-Cohen (1995), Gopnik and Meltzoff (1998), Wellman (1990), Baron-Cohen (2001).

  77. Leslie (1987), Currie and Ravenscroft (1992).

  78. Thomas Fuchs and his team in the psychiatric department, University of Heidelberg, have done much to illuminate the role of perception and embodiment in psychopathology. See Fuchs Op. Cit. (2005), Fuchs and Schlimme (2009).

  79. Merleau-Ponty (1962:360, 2006:419, 1945:418).

  80. ibid (1962:360, 2006:419, 1945:418).

  81. This refers to the extremely well-known central aim of Merleau-Ponty’s philosophical project—to establish a non-dualist ontology, also known as a relational ontology.

References

  • Adolphs R (2000) A role for somatosensory cortexes in the visual recognition of emotion as revealed by three-dimensional lesion mapping J Neurosci 20(7):2683–2690. Sourced from http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/folkpsych-simulation/. Retrieved 28-12-11

    Google Scholar 

  • Baron-Cohen S (1995) An essay on autism and theory of mind. MIT Press, Boston

    Google Scholar 

  • Baron-Cohen S (2001) Theory of mind in normal development and autism. Prisme 34:174–183

    Google Scholar 

  • Bateson MC (1979) The epigenesis of conversational interaction: a personal account of research development. In: Bullowa M (ed) Before speech: the beginning of human communication. Cambridge University Press, London, pp 63–77

    Google Scholar 

  • Batson CD (2009) These Things Called Empathy: Eight Related but Distinct Phenomena. In: Decety J, Ickes W (eds) The social neuroscience of empathy. MIT Press, Cambridge, MA, pp 3–15

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Bennett M, Hacker P (2007) The conceptual presuppositions of cognitive neuroscience. In: Bennett D (ed) Neuroscience and philosophy: brain, mind and language. Columbia University Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Block N (2003) Mental paint. In: Hahn M, Ramberg B (eds) Reflections and replies: essays on the philosophy of Tyler Burge. MIT Press, Cambridge, MA

    Google Scholar 

  • Chalmers D (2004) The representational character of experience. In: Leiter B (ed) The future for philosophy. Oxford University Press, Oxford, pp 153–181

    Google Scholar 

  • Clark A (2002) Minds, brains and tools. In: Clapin H (ed) The philosophy of mental representation. Clarendon Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Coplan A (2012) Understanding empathy: its features and effects. In: Coplan A, Goldie P (eds) Empathy: philosophical and psychologic perspectives, Published on Oxford Scholarship Online, Jan 2012, OUP 2013. Accessed 8-8-13

  • Currie G, Ravenscroft I (1992) Meeting of minds: thought, perception and imagination. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Daly A (2013) Does the Reversibility Thesis deliver all that Merleau-Ponty claims it can? Eur J Philos (forthcoming) 2–3

  • Daniels N (1996) Justice and justification: reflective equilibrium in theory and practice. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Devitt M (1996) Coming to our senses: a naturalistic program for semantic localism. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Dretske F (1981) Knowledge and the flow of information. MIT Press, Cambridge, MA

    Google Scholar 

  • Dretske F (1995) Naturalising the mind. MIT press, Cambridge, MA

    Google Scholar 

  • Dreyfus H (1998) Intelligence without representation http://www.class.uh.edu/cogsci/dreyfus.html. Retrieved 26 Nov 2011

  • Eisenberg N, Eggum ND (2009) Empathic responding: sympathy and personal distress. In: Decety J, Ickes W (eds) The social neuroscience of empathy. MIT Press, Cambridge, MA, pp 71–83

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Fodor JA (1981) Representations. MIT Press, Cambridge, MA

    Google Scholar 

  • Fuchs T (2005) Delusional mood and delusional perception—a phenomenological analysis. Psychopathology 38:133–139

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fuchs T (2008) The brain as a relational organ: a phenomenological and ecological concept. Kohlhammer, Stuttgart

    Google Scholar 

  • Fuchs T, Schlimme JE (2009) Embodiment and psychopathology: a phenomenological perspective. Curr Opin Psychiatry 22:570–575

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gallagher S (2001) The practice of mind: theory, simulation, or interaction. J Consci Stud 8(5-7):83–108

    Google Scholar 

  • Gallagher S (2005) How the body shapes the mind. Clarendon Press, London

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Gallagher S (2006) Review of perspectives on imitation: from neuroscience to social science. In: Hurley S, Chater N (eds) MIT Press 2005 in metapsychology online reviews, July 4th 2006 (Volume 10, Issue 27) Retrieved September 2011

  • Gallagher S (2012) Phenomenology. Palgrave Macmillan, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Gallagher S, Hutto DD (2008) Understanding others through primary interaction and narrative practice. In: Zlatev J, Racine T, Sinha C, Itkonen E (eds) The shared mind: perspectives on intersubjectivity. Amsterdam, John Benjamins. Retrieved 28 December 2011

  • Gallagher S, Zahavi D (2010) Phenomenological approaches to self-consciousness. In: Zalta EN (ed) The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Winter 2010 Edition). Retrieved 26-8-13, url:http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2010/entries/self-consciousness-phenomenological

  • Gallagher S, Hutto D, Slaby J, Cole J (2013) The brain as part of an enactive system. Behav Brain Sci 36:421–422. doi:10.1017/S0140525X12002105 (abstract sighted 26-8-13, ordered but yet to receive)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gallese V (2009) Mirror neurons. In: Baynes T (ed) Oxford companion to consciousness. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Gallese V (2010a) A neuroscientific approach to intersubjectivity. In: Fuchs T, Sattel HC, Henningsen P (eds) The embodied self: dimensions, coherence and disorders. Schattauer Verlag, Stuttgart, pp 77–92

    Google Scholar 

  • Gallese V (2010b) Embodied simulation and its role in intersubjectivity. In: Fuchs T, Sattel HC, Hennington P (eds) The embodied self: dimensions, coherence and disorders. Schattauer Verlag, Stuttgart, pp 78–92

  • Gallese V, Keyses C, Rizzolatti G (2004) A unifying view of the basis of social cognition. Trends Cognit Sci 8:396–403

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gallese V, Eagle ME, Migone P (2007) Intentional attunement: mirror neurons and the neural underpinnings of interpersonal relations. J Am Psycholanal Assoc 55:131–176

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gied J, Blumenthal J, Jeffries N, Castellanos F, Lieu H, Ijdenbos A, Paus T, Evans A, Rapoport J (1999) Brain development during childhood and adolescence: a longitudinal MRI study. Nat Neurosci 2(10):861–863

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gopnik A, Meltzoff A (1998) Words, thoughts and theories. MIT Press, Boston

    Google Scholar 

  • Hohwy J (2007) Functional integration and the mind. Synthese 159(3):315–328

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Husserl E (1952) Ideas II ideas pertaining to a pure phenomenology and to a phenomenological philosophy, husserl archives (1989) (trans: Rojcewicz R, Schewer A), Dordrecht/Boston/London, KluwerAcademic Publishers

  • Husserl E (1923/24) Zur Phänomenologie de Intersubjektivität III, in Husserliana XV, 74–75 and also in Erste Philosophie II in Husserliana VIII, 480

  • Kelly SD (2002) Merleau-Ponty on the body. In: Ratio (new series) XV 4 December 2002, 0034-0006 Oxford, Blackwell Publishers

  • Leslie AM (1987) Pretense and representation: the origins of ‘Theory of Mind’. Psychol Rev 94:412–426

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Meltzoff A, Moore MK (1977) Imitation of facial and manual gestures by human neonates. Science 198:75–78

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Meltzoff A, Moore MK (1995) Infants’ understanding of people and things: from body imitation to folk psychology. In: Burmudez J, Marcel A, Eilan N (eds) The body and the self. MIT/Bradford Press, Cambridge, MA, pp 53–54

    Google Scholar 

  • Merleau-Ponty M (1933, 1934, 1996) La primat de la perception et ses conséquences philosophiques. Paris, Verdier

  • Merleau-Ponty M (1948) Sens et non-sens (4th ed 1963). Paris, Nagel

  • Merleau-Ponty M (1960) Signes. Éditions Gallimard, Paris, p 221

    Google Scholar 

  • Merleau-Ponty M (1962) The phenomenology of perception, 1st edn. (trans: Smith C). London, Routledge Kegan Paul (1st reference)

  • Merleau-Ponty M (1964a) Le visible et l’invisible. Gallimard, Paris (French original)

    Google Scholar 

  • Merleau-Ponty M (1964b) The Primacy of Perception and Other Essays. Trans. James. Edie Evanston: Northwestern University Press

  • Merleau-Ponty M (1964c) The philosopher and his shadow. Signs (trans: Librarie Gallimard). Evanston, Illinois, Northwestern University Press

  • Merleau-Ponty M (1968) The Visible and the Invisible (trans: Lingus A). Evanston, Northwestern University Press

  • Merleau-Ponty M (1970) Sense and non-sense (trans: Dreyfus HL, Dreyfus PA). Evanston, Illinois, Northwestern University Press pp. 5253

  • Merleau-Ponty M (1993) Eye and mind. In: Galen AJ (ed) The Merleau-Ponty aesthetics reader: philosophy and painting (1968) (trans: Michael BS). Northwestern University Press, Evanston

  • Merleau-Ponty M (1945) Phénoménologie de la perception. Gallimard, Paris

    Google Scholar 

  • Merleau-Ponty M (2006) The phenomenology of perception (1962) (trans: Smith C). Reprint, London, Routledge Kegan Paul

  • Rawls John (1971) A theory of justice. Harvard University Press, Cambridge, MA

    Google Scholar 

  • Restak R (2002) The secret life of the brain. Dana Press and Joseph Henry Press, Washington

    Google Scholar 

  • Rizzolatti G, Fogassi L, Gallese V (2006) Mirrors in the mind. Sci Am 295(5):54–61

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Scanlan TM (2002) Rawls on justification. In: Freeman S (ed) The Cambridge companion to rawls. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Scheler M (1913) The nature of sympathy (1970) (trans: Heath P). Hamden CT, Archon Books

  • Sheets-Johnstone M (2006) Essential clarifications of ‘self-affection’ and Husserl’s ‘sphere of ownness’: first steps toward a pure phenomenology of (human) nature. Cont Philos Rev 39:361–391, doi:10.1007/s11007-006-9030-9. Accessed 30-8-13

    Google Scholar 

  • Slaby J (2007) Affective intentionality and the feeling body, Springer science and business media. http://fu-berlin.academia.edu/JanSlaby/Papers/440428/Affective-Intentionality-and-the-Feeling-Body. Retrieved 20-2-2012

  • Stein E (1964) On the problem of empathy (trans Stein W). The Hague, Martinus Nijhoff

  • Trevarthen C (1998) The concept and foundations of infant intersubjectivity. In: Braten S (ed) Intersubjective communication and emotion in early ontogeny. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, pp 15–46

    Google Scholar 

  • Trevarthen C (2012) Natural sources of meaning in human sympathetic vitality. In: Foolen A, Lűdtke UM, Racine TP, Zlatev J (eds) Moving ourselves, moving others: motion and emotion in intersubjectivity. Consciousness and language. John Benjamins Publishing Company, Amsterdam/Philadelphia, pp 451–483

    Google Scholar 

  • Tye M (2009) Consciousness revisited. MIT press, Cambridge, MA

    Google Scholar 

  • Varela FJ (1992) Ethical know-how: action. Stanford University Press, California

    Google Scholar 

  • Varela FJ, Thompson E, Rosch E (1991) The embodied mind: cognitive science and human experience. MIT Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Wellman H (1990) The child’s theory of mind. MIT Press, Boston

    Google Scholar 

  • Zahavi Dan (1999) Self-awareness and alterity: a phenomenological investigation. Northwestern University Press, Evanston, Il

    Google Scholar 

  • Zahavi Dan (2005) Subjectivity and selfhood: investigating the first-person perspective. MIT Press, Cambridge, MA

    Google Scholar 

  • Zahavi D (2007) Expression and empathy. In: Ratcliffe MM, Hutto D (eds) Folk psychology re-assessed. Dordrecht, The Netherlands: Springer, p 25–40, Google Books, Retrieved 26-1-2012

  • Zahavi D (2013) Empathy, emotional sharing and we-intentionality. In: Abstract for conference, the phenomenology of sociality, University College, Dublin May 8–10, 2013. Accessed 30-6-13

  • Zahavi D (2001) Beyond empathy: phenomenological approaches to intersubjectivity. J Conscious Stud 8(5–7):151–167

    Google Scholar 

  • Zahavi D (2002) Merleau-Ponty on husserl: a reappraisal. In: Toadvine T, Embree L (eds) Merleau-Ponty’s reading of husserl. Kluwer Academic Publishers, Dordrecht

    Google Scholar 

  • Zahavi D (2004) Alterity in self. In: Gallagher S, Watson S, Brun P, Romanski P (eds) Ipseity and alterity: interdisciplinary approaches to intersubjectivity. Presses Universitaires de Rouen, Rouen

    Google Scholar 

  • Zlatev J (2007) Embodiment, language and mimesis. In: Ziemke T, Zlatev J, Frank Body R (eds) Language and mind, 1st edn. Mouton, Embodiment Berlin

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Anya Daly.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Daly, A. Primary Intersubjectivity: Empathy, Affective Reversibility, ‘Self-Affection’ and the Primordial ‘We’. Topoi 33, 227–241 (2014). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11245-013-9206-7

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11245-013-9206-7

Keywords

Navigation