Introduction

The search for a definition of life or of a living being has been recurrent in biological thinking, and has acquired a renovated interest due to the appearance of research programs related to artificial life, the origin of life and astrobiology (reviewed in Popa 2004). The Chilean biologists Humberto Maturana and Francisco Varela (1973; 1980) proposed that the minimal definition of a living being may be based on only one property, which they called autopoiesis. This contrasts sharply with other definitions, which are based on the combination of several properties (e.g., Koshland 2002; Popa 2004, pp. 6–7).Footnote 1 Autopoiesis also contrasts with other definitions by being a relational property (also referred to as systemic, functionalist, formalist or universalist). Its relational character is due to the fact that it does not depend directly on the nature (type, intrinsic properties) of the components of those entities which have the property, but rather depends only upon the relations between the components. Because of this, the concept connects to more general areas of research which have attempted to describe diverse types of systems in relational terms, such as tektology (Bogdanov 1996 [1922], Gorelik 1975, 1984; Dudley 1996), general systems theory (Bertalanffy 1950, 1968; Rapoport 1972), cybernetics (Wiener 1948; Ashby 1957; Varela and Maturana 1972), relational biology (Rashevsky 1954; Rosen 1958, 1959, 1991), information theory (Shannon 1948; Shannon and Weaver 1949; Avery 2003) and the recent research areas of complex systems (Kauffman 1989, 1993; Ruthen 1993; Bak 1996; Reason and Goodwin 1999; Gisiger 2001; Wolfram 2002; Bedau 2003, 2008), systems biology and synthetic biology (Wolkenhauer 2001; Breitling 2010).

The heuristic value and the advantages of relational definitions and descriptions of living beings are prominent in the research on artificial life, astrobiology and the origin of life (Dix 1983, Fleischaker and Margulis 1986; Emmeche 1992; Kauffman 2001; Popa 2004; McMullin 2004; Luisi 2006). One reason for this is that a definition of a living being that does not depend on the type of components which constitute the system would in principle account for remote living beings close to the origin of life—which were possibly much different from current forms (Reilly 2008; Wolfe-Simon et al. 2011), and for artificial life synthesized in vitro or in silico (Langton 1989; Breitling 2010) and living beings which may potentially exist outside Earth (Popa 2004). In all these cases the living beings may be possibly composed of components which are very different from those of currently known living beings (Friedman 2002; Nealson 2002). A relational definition is also attractive from a theoretical standpoint. We normally are not willing to consider as a living being an aggregate of components which have just any type of interrelation; for example, a paste of organic material from a living being which has been ground or centrifuged would not usually be considered a living being. On the other hand, it is not clear that we would in principle refuse to consider as living beings entities which are not based on DNA, polymers or even carbon atoms, that are the basic components of current living beings (see Reilly 2008). Thus it seems reasonable to think that what lets us distinguish living beings as such is based more on the nature of the relations between their components than on the nature of the components themselves. Finally, given the amount of speculation which exists about the origin of life, the specific pathways which originated life on Earth may be less relevant than the general relational characteristics or “family of mechanisms” which generated life (Pross 2004).

The high degree of abstraction of the concept of autopoiesis and its relational character allowed its authors to use this property as the base for a theoretical development which connects autopoiesis with problems of epistemology, cognitive sciences (Maturana and Varela 1972; 1980; 1992 [1987], Varela et al. 1991; Bitbol and Luisi 2004; Barandiaran and Moreno 2006) and evolutionary biology (Maturana and Varela 1992 [1987], Maturana and Mpodozis 1992, 2000; Vargas 2005). The concept has also been used in environmental sciences (Margulis 1997; Mann 1991; Sagan and Margulis 1997; Litfin 2010) and several areas of human sciences, including business administration (Mingers 1995), psychology (Colapinto 1985; Simon 1985; Snyder 1999) and particularly sociology (Luhmann 1986, 1995 [1984], 2007 [1997], Geyer and van der Zouwen 2001; Magalhaes and Sanchez 2009). The impact of the concept has increased and currently, only in ISI Web of Knowledge, the concept appears in more than 30 articles and 300 citations by year (Fig. 1). However, even though its central objective is to understand and delimit the object of study of biology, the concept has not managed to become a definition of living being accepted among biologists, nor has it been incorporated in biology texts or integrated generally into biological disciplines. I will argue that this is due to at least two factors: first, the original definitions are neither clear nor easy to understand; and second, the concept appears difficult to apply in practice. I will show that neither of those factors are actual obstacles to take autopoiesis as a general definition of living being. To do so, I will indicate the causes of this lack of clarity, analyze the possible interpretations of the original definition of Maturana and Varela, and propose a new, clearer and more precise definition, which I propose is the natural result of the analysis of this concept.

Fig. 1
figure 1

Number of articles and citations by year published in ISI Web of Knowledge in which appear the terms ‘autopoiesis’, ‘autopoietic’, ‘autopoyesis’, or ‘autopoyetic’. a. Articles in Science Citation Index Expanded (SCI-EXPANDED), Social Sciences Citation Index (SSCI), and Arts and Humanities Citation Index (AandHCI). b. Articles only in SCI-EXPANDED. c. Citations in SCI-EXPANDED, SSCI, and AandHCI. d. Citations only in SCI-EXPANDED

Autopoiesis: A Variety of Interpretations

The interpretation of the concept of autopoiesis has been controversial (Fleischacker 1988; Zolo 1990, Swenson 1992a, 1992b; Scheper and Scheper 1996; Morán et al. 1999; Escobar 2011). To begin with, the difficult rhetoric of the authors together with their persistent allusions to self-reference and circularity have produced skepticism and have made some authors suspect that the concept could mean just about anything, have no meaning, be tautological, trivial or not very scientific, which would also apply to its derivations (Zolo 1990; Munch 1992; Scheper and Scheper 1996, Swenson 1992a, 1992b, Manriquez and Rothhammer 1997; Gallardo 1997; Nespolo 2003; Valenzuela 2007, 2010). Others have considered the concept “to be nothing but a fancy synonym for both self-organization and self-maintenance” (Mahner and Bunge 1997, p. 144) and thus immediately discountable as a definition of a living being, since self-organization is a property shared by many types of non-living systems (Mahner and Bunge 1997; Pross 2004, Swenson 1992b).

At the other extreme, autopoiesis has been treated as a highly complex property, which would explain the manifest difficulty in the attempts to formalize it and in the search for concrete examples to illustrate the concept, even in purely formal terms. The attempts to formalize the concept of autopoiesis have achieved highly sophisticated results, but it is not clear in what sense these could be considered successful. A first model based on cellular automata (Varela et al. 1974) was later corrected and invalidated by one of its authors (McMullin and Varela 1997; McMullin 2000). A first attempt at a general formalization of an autopoietic system using Spencer-Brown’s very complex calculus of indications (Varela 1979) has not produced satisfactory results (Letelier et al. 2003). Later formalizations based in the very abstract theory of categories and Rosen’s (M,R) systems (Letelier et al. 2003, 2006; Cornish-Bowden et al. 2007) only recently have found a first concrete example of (M,R) system what might be considered a formal autopoietic system (Letelier et al. 2006). This line of investigation has gone to the extreme of claiming that autopoiesis is not computable, that is that autopoietic systems cannot be calculated by Turing machines (Letelier et al. 2003). All this has managed to surround the concept of autopoiesis with an air of mystery, in which it is not clear whether it is a trivial concept (which includes everything or almost everything) or empty (which includes nothing or almost nothing), whether it is useful scientifically, whether it is an extremely sophisticated property or is really very simple.

How can we explain such a wide range of interpretations of the concept? Here I will argue that it is because autopoiesis is characterized by a delicate conceptual subtlety which has not been sufficiently clear. I will show that (i) the concept has not been subject to sufficient conceptual analysis before looking for examples or formalizations, (ii) more than one meaning can be extracted from the definition, and these alternatives have not been clearly distinguished nor has it been determined which is correct, and (iii) it has not been systematically made explicit using precise concepts and making clear their relations with other relevant concepts for the understanding of the basic operation of living beings. I will then attempt to remedy these failings, by analyzing the original definition proposed by the authors and replacing it with a new definition which I feel is clearer and more concise. With this new definition, I will analyze how the concept of autopoiesis is related to other concepts such as closed system, boundary, homeostasis, self-reproduction, circular causality and organization. This critical analysis pretends to come alive again the possibility to take autopoiesis as a general and widely acceptable minimal definition of living being for biology.

Autopoiesis: A Subtle Property

Autopoiesis literally means ‘self-production’ or ‘self-creation’. The concept of autopoiesis in the book De Máquinas y Seres Vivos (On Machines and Living Beings) written in 1972 (Maturana and Varela 1994, p. xvii) was defined explicitly, as follows:

‘An autopoietic machine is a machine organized as a system of processes of production of components concatenated in such a way that they produce components which:

  1. i).

    generate the processes (relations) of production which produce them through their continual interactions and transformations, and

  2. ii).

    constitute the machine as a unit in physical space’ (Maturana and Varela 1973)Footnote 2

A good exercise for the present purpose is to read the original definition several times (if one has sufficient patience). As immediately becomes evident, this definition is relatively difficult and ambiguous (as is the definition of 1980, see Note 1) due to the lack of a precise reference of some of the terms utilized, which will be indicated in italics in what follows: ‘that they produce components which’; ‘generate the processes (relations) of production’; ‘that produce them by means of their continual’. It is not clear whether the terms in italics refer to the “system of processes”, the “processes of production”, to the “concatenated products” that produce, or the “concatenated components” produced. This may well explain the diversity of interpretations of the concept.

Although there is ambiguity in the definition, it may be inferred that autopoiesis defines a type of system constituted by a set of types of components (which I will call X) which, by means of concatenated processes, produces a set of types of components (which I will call Y). Now, what defines Y? i.e., What conditions must Y fulfill in order that a system of production of components (X) may be considered autopoietic?

The most common interpretation (and literal in almost all the paraphrases of the original definitionFootnote 3) is that the network of production of components produces all the components of the network, that is, X = Y. As we shall see, this interpretation is inacceptable given known basic aspects of living beings.

In the first place, if we understand that the ‘components of the system’ (X) are all the reactants and products of the reactions which occur in the system (that is, including its “food” and “waste”), then if we suppose that the system generates all the components of the system (X = Y) we must conclude that autopoietic systems are closed systems. Thus, given that living beings are open systems, we must reject this interpretation.

In the second place, if we consider that the ‘components of the system’ (X) are all the reactants and products of the reactions which occur in the system except its “food” and “waste” (supposing that there is a simple way to distinguish them in relational terms), then if we suppose that the system generates all the components of the system (X = Y) we are faced with two other problems. First, many (and perhaps) all known living beings need for their maintenance elements from their surroundings which form part of their metabolic network and which may act as coenzymes or cofactors, and, above all, which could not be distinguished from any other intermediate metabolites produced internally by the system. Second, if what the system produces permanently is the same set of components of the system (X = Y); this would imply that the system cannot suffer qualitative change over time, that is, it may not have qualitative changes during ontogenesis (such as metamorphosis in insects, Valenzuela 2007). Thus, given that living beings do have ontogeny and may depend upon cofactors or metabolites from their surroundings, this second interpretation must also be rejected. As a consequence, the classical image of M. C. Escher, much used to represent the concept of autopoiesis, of two hands each drawing the other completely (including the pencil) is not an acceptable representation (Fig. 2).

Fig. 2
figure 2

Photograph of Drawing Hands by M. C. Escher, 1948, taken in Escher Museum, The Hague. The usual association between autopoiesis and the drawing of two hands drawing each other is questionable as an analogy of autopoiesis. [Photograph taken by Gabriel Razeto]

According to the above, we are left with only one possible interpretation, that is, that the autopoietic system produces only a subset of the components of the system (YX). In summary, the three characteristics of living beings; (1) they are open systems, (2) they may require coenzymes or metabolites from the environment for their maintenance, and (3) they may change during ontogeny, restrict the possible interpretations of the concept of autopoiesis to one. The network does not produce all the components of the network, only some of them. That is, the network produces a subgroup of the components which characterize the network as a unit.

But now the obvious following question arises, what subgroup of a production network must the network produce in order to be considered autopoietic? Given the functional centrality which molecular biology has given to the enzymes, we might be tempted to define an autopoietic system as “a network of processes which produces all the catalysts of the network”. However, as discussed above, there are many exceptions (coenzymes and cofactors mentioned in point (2) above) and it does not appear to be theoretically necessary for a system to produce all the catalysts of the network in order to be autopoietic, since if these catalysts are available in the environment and may enter the system constantly, the system may continue to maintain the processes of production of the network without producing all the catalysts internally.Footnote 4

From the above I conclude that in part (i) of the original definition of autopoiesis (Maturana and Varela 1973, 1980) there is no specification which permits to demarcate or characterize the subgroup Y that allows a production network to be called autopoietic; thus it is necessary to consider seriously part (ii) of the original definition: ‘constitutes a machine as a unit’. That is, here is the only possible specification of the subgroup Y, viz., the subgroup of components which the system must produce to maintain the system as a unit over time. Based on the above I propose that the only possible interpretation of the concept of autopoiesis which is not empty or trivial, and which is consistent with basic aspects of known living beings, may be summarized in the following short definition of autopoiesis, which I will call D1:

D1: An autopoietic system is a network of processes which produces all the components whose internal production is necessary to maintain the network operating as a unit.

Even though this definition is more clear, precise and concise than the original, it contains some subtleties which should be clarified. Definition D1 implies that, whatever the system be that has to produce (Y) to maintain its production network operating, it will depend on what is available in the environment for it. Thus we cannot impose a priori what components or types of components the network must internally produce (to maintain its production network operating), since this will depend upon the nature of its surroundings. This may explain the difficulty in defining autopoietic organization mathematically, since as is natural traditional formalizations symbolize the system only based on the components of the system (e.g., Letelier et al. 2003, 2006; Cornish-Bowden et al. 2007). Under definition D1, it may be concluded that the autopoietic organization of a system can only be formalized mathematically if components of the environment of the system are included.

Autopoiesis and Molecular Autopoiesis

The 1973 definition of Maturana and Varela suffered a small but significant change in Varela et al. (1974), which is also included in the definition of Maturana and Varela (1980) (see Note 1). The original definition of autopoiesis makes reference to a system as a unit “in physical space”; however, the later definitions refer to a unit “in the space in which the components exist” (not using the word “physical”). This allows the authors to distinguish between the concept of autopoiesis, which is general and abstract and could in principle be applied to any “space” or “dominion” (physical or not physical); and the concept of “molecular autopoiesis”, “chemical autopoiesis”, or “autopoiesis in physical space”, which is the definition of living being as such.Footnote 5 This generated a first differentiation between the thinking of Maturana and Varela. For Maturana there is no restriction in the “space” in which an autopoietic system may exist (Maturana 1981), while for Varela autopoiesis applied to non-physical domains is only metaphoric (Varela 1981).

It is the abstract (not necessarily physical) use of the concept of autopoiesis which has been the base of its success in human sciences such as psychology and sociology, in which, for example, the “space” of production of components is constituted by communications (Luhmann 1986, 1995 [1984], 2007 [1997], Razeto-Barry and Cienfuegos 2011; Veloz et al. 2012). For this reason I maintained the abstraction of the general concept of autopoiesis in definition D1, without specifying the space or domain in which it is applied. Thus D1 may also serve to make the concept more clear and precise in human sciences. However, in what follows I will examine autopoiesis in physical space, where the concept attempts to serve as a definition of living being, and only will comment on a few implications for extra-biological applications of the concept (see Notes 8 and 18).

Traditionally, molecular autopoiesis has been understood as a minimal definition of a single cell, and ‘processes of production’ simply as chemical reactions, and thus autopoietic systems are understood as a sub-class of collectively autocatalytic chemical reaction networks (McMullin 2000). As I will discuss later in this article, this is an inadequate concept of autopoiesis for unicellular and particularly for multicellular living beings.

Autopoiesis and Boundaries

Varela followed a second line somewhat different from that of Maturana. In later works, Varela emphasizes a particular component produced by the system, the boundary; that is, the physical border which limits and separates the interior from the exterior of the system. The boundary, or its cellular parallel, the external membrane of the cell, is not mentioned in the original definitions of the concept (Maturana and Varela 1973, 1980), however, appears explicitly in the first computational examples led by Varela (Varela et al. 1974; McMullin and Varela 1997), and are incorporated explicitly in later paraphrases and explanations of the original definition (e.g., Varela 2000, also in Luisi et al. 1996).

Apparently for Varela the production of the boundary or external membrane from the interior of the system is essential for autopoiesis (see also Fleischacker 1988), that is, if the components of the membrane came from the exterior the system would not be autopoietic (i.e., for Varela one type of element necessary for Y is the boundary component). At first sight this makes sense; for one thing the membrane is effectively a particularly important component which permits the maintenance of the network of component production of the current unicellular living organisms. Also, the production of the external membrane is in reality an important factor which allows these organisms to become established and maintain themselves as units in space, and also in proto-cells generated in vitro (Luisi et al. 2006; Solé et al. 2007).

Notably, this line emphasized by Varela has recently led to the artificial production of chemical systems in the laboratory which some authors consider autopoietic. The Swiss scientist Pier Luigi Luisi and collaborators produced synthetic membranes in the form of spherical vessels which catalyze the production of the components of the membrane; they grow and reproduce spontaneously as a consequence of their self-production (Zepik et al. 2001; Luisi 2006). Although ‘self-reproduction’ and ‘autopoiesis’ (‘self-production’) have been considered definitions of life in competition, the possibility of considering some kinds of self-reproducing chemical systems as autopoietic was first suggested by Luisi and Varela (1989, Luisi 1993). This opened the possibility of considering as autopoietic both “homeostatic” systems (whose mass remains constant) and “self-reproductive” systems (whose mass grows until it spontaneously provokes reproduction) (Luisi and Varela 1989; Luisi et al. 1996; Luisi 1993, 2003, 2006; Varela 2000). From the point of view of the previous discussion, this “experimental shift” with respect to the original interpretation of the concept (although not the definition) is acceptable and completely compatible with definition D1.

It is worth noting that, in spite of the compatibility of D1 with the “shift” of Varela, the generation of a layer forming a physical barrier as a kind of production of a boundary is not necessarily a universal requirement in causal terms, and thus is not a requirement of definition D1. The idea that the production of the components of a barrier is necessary for the maintenance of the system comes from the image of life as a cell with molecules in a liquid state dissolved in an aqueous solvent. However, the physical state of cellular cytoplasm is viscous (Schroder 2010) and under certain circumstances might maintain its unity (and therefore its border) by cohesion and surface tension (as does a drop of water surrounded by air). It is probable that in the origin of the first cells on Earth the production of a membrane was by the self-assembly of simple lipids synthesized in the environment, while the internal production of membrane components was a derived process evolved by natural selection (Hargreaves and Deamer 1978; Hanczyz et al. 2003; Budin and Szostak 2011).Footnote 6 On the other hand, it is possible that in the origin of life the membrane was not a “limit” which separated the interior from the exterior of the living being, but rather the membrane itself was the living being (the membrane would be the interior of the living being, Fig. 3).Footnote 7

Fig. 3
figure 3

Representation of the non-intuitive idea that the system “outside” of a living system may be spatially “inside”. In the origin of life metabolism may ocurr in the membranes rather than inside the space surrounded by the vesicles. Note that Robert Hook (1635–1703) who discovered cells, thought that the spatial inside of cells is not living matter (Mazzarello 1999)

It is also worth noting that the requirement of the internal production of the components of the membrane is not a requirement of the definition itself, but rather a practical condition imposed by the known cellular forms of living beings on Earth. According to D1, if the system did not require a membrane to maintain itself as a cohesive unit, or if the components of the membrane came from the environment and the system continued to produce the subgroup of components necessary for its maintenance as a spatially discreet unit, then the system would continue to be considered autopoietic.

It is important to mention here that the aim of the concept of autopoiesis is to characterize a minimal definition of life. That is, a definition that includes the minimal requirements (semantically) necessary to consider that a system is a living system. Even if studies suggest that on Earth the proposition: “all current autopoietic systems on earth produce the elements of their membranes” (and equally replacing ‘autopoietic systems’ by ‘living beings’) probably is true, the question about the definition of autopoiesis (and of life) implies deciding whether this proposition will be a trivial tautology guaranteed by the definition of autopoiesis (or of living being) or a synthetic empirical result due to current observations and predictions based on current life on the Earth. The minimal life project searches for a minimal definition of life, that is, ‘the definition should… be minimal but specific enough (i.e., it should include just those elements that are common to all forms of life – not being, in principle, restricted to life on Earth…).’ (Ruiz-Mirazo et al. 2004, p. 326, similarly see Emmeche 1998). In this context it is clear that it is preferable to take the mentioned proposition as an interesting synthetic property of known nature rather than an analytical tautology guaranteed by definition, maintaining open the door to include other kinds of life in the definition, together with the one in the origin of life in Earth, for which it is possible that the mentioned proposition is not true (Hargreaves and Deamer 1978; Hanczyz et al. 2003; Budin and Szostak 2011).

In this vein, as we will see below in our discussion about multicellular living beings, as a direct consequence of D1, a multicellular organism is an autopoietic system as such (i.e., it is a “first-order” autopoietic system), and in it the production of a “border” (e.g., an epidermis in vertebrate animals) is not precisely what maintains it as a cohesive unit.Footnote 8

Autopoiesis, Homeostasis and Self-Reproduction

The vesicles generated in the laboratory by Luisi and collaborators are autopoietic according to definition D1, however, they are essentially self-reproductive and cannot maintain themselves dynamically in homoeostasis (without growth or permanent reproduction). This characteristic does not agree with the usual emphasis that Maturana and Varela gave to the concept of autopoiesis, which is based on the maintenance (homeostasis) of the system by means of the regeneration of elements which must necessarily disintegrate spontaneously (Varela et al. 1974; McMullin and Varela 1997; Varela 2000; McMullin 2004). Thus from my point of view it is not necessary to include the ‘disintegration’ and ‘regeneration’ of components as an essential element in the formalization of autopoiesis, in contrast to the original emphasis of its authors and the formal models of autopoiesis (e.g., Varela et al. 1974; McMullin and Varela 1997; Letelier et al. 2003, 2006; Cornish-Bowden et al. 2007; Cornish-Bowden and Cárdenas 2007). As a consequence, the common theoretical contraposition between autopoiesis and self-reproduction as strictly competing ideas (e.g., Cornish-Bowden and Cárdenas 2007) is not necessary. Although Varela (2000; Luisi et al. 1996) admits that autopoietic systems may be in homeostasis or in growth tending to self-replication, he systematically emphasizes the regeneration of degraded elements as an essential factor of autopoiesis. By contrast, I propose that even though there may be autopoietic systems which are not self-reproductive, and self-reproductive systems which are not autopoietic, also there may perfectly well be autopoietic systems which are strictly self-reproductive (such as the special type of self-catalytic network generated in the laboratory by Luisi and collaborators). That is, there may be autopoietic systems without disintegration of their components, and thus in constant growth and sef-reproduction.

It should be clear that the definition D1 I propose is compatible both with systems whose mass is maintained in homeostasis and with systems whose mass is in constant growth (auto-catalytic and auto-reproductive networks). If the products of an auto-catalytic network generate the conditions necessary to maintain the network as a discrete unit in space, then the network is an autopoietic system. As a consequence, I reject the recently proposed idea that autopoietic systems are a Robert Rosen (M,R) type of system (Letelier et al. 2003, 2006; Cornish-Bowden et al. 2007; Cornish-Bowden and Cárdenas 2007), since it is essential that a (M,R) system have degradation and reparation.Footnote 9 It is worth noting that no one has yet generated in the laboratory an artificial system (or a concrete model for the evolution of life on Earth) which is a homeostatic autopoietic system, which without doubt is the most recurrent conception of an autopoietic system, both in the original formulation of its authors and in its formalizations (Maturana and Varela 1972; 1980; Varela et al. 1974; Varela 1979; McMullin and Varela 1997; Varela 2000; McMullin 2004; Letelier et al. 2003, 2006; Cornish-Bowden et al. 2007; Cornish-Bowden and Cárdenas 2007).

Autopoiesis and Circular Causality

Maturana and Varela often emphasized that autopoiesis implies a certain circularity. In their terms, an autopoietic system is open in structure (components enter and leave) but is closed in its organization (its relations are closed as in a circle).Footnote 10 From this idea came others which the authors used, such as ‘operational closure’Footnote 11, ‘operative closure’, ‘recursivity’, and ‘self-referential systems’. Here we address the question: How should this circularity be understood? Firstly, what seems clear is that it is a circular causality. Footnote 12 The notion of circular causality first arose with the appearance of cybernetics, around 1946 (Umpleby 2005), in which the feedback mechanism was represented graphically as a cycle (a circle with a defined direction). For the creators of cybernetics, the cyclic vision of the feedback mechanism assumes a representation of nodes and relations between nodes, which is collectively closed on itself and in which the nodes represent states of particular variables of a system, and the relations between nodes represent the control relations of these states (Fig. 4). Now, what type of causal circularity is autopoiesis?

Fig. 4
figure 4

Abstract representation of a causal cycle

Obviously all circularity is a circularity of some kind of relations. The causal circularity of feedback proposed by the cyberneticists is a circular relation among control relations. Autopoiesis is usually interpreted as a causal circularity of production relations (see the first quotation in Note 10), which is consistent with the literal interpretation of the concept as ‘self-production’. However, according to the earlier arguments, this is not possible. Circularity means that the leaving and entering relations are the same. Starting from a given point, the relations of the cycle must return to the same point (Fig. 4). If the relation is that of production, then starting from any point—all components of the system composing the unit—by means of the relations of production, all the components of the system should be produced. That is, using the earlier nomenclature, if the set X produces the set Y, (X → Y), that the production of the system is circular implies X = Y. However, we have already rejected this. If autopoiesis were a circular causality of production, then the types of components which constitute the system should (indirectly, mediated by a complicated network of relations) produce themselves; that is, produce exactly the same types of components. However, an autopoietic system only produces a subset of all the types of elements of the system (Y∈X). Then, in what sense can its organization be understood as circular (supposing that this is in fact possible)? Definition D1 may be of help.

A living being is undoubtedly a system of production (in which production refers specifically to chemical reactions). Although the components of the system do not produce all the components of the system, they do produce that subset of components ‘whose internal production is necessary to maintain the network function as a unit’ (D1). And since the system must maintain itself to meet D1, this subset of components must be capable of procuring the internal presence of the rest of the components of the system from the exterior, bringing them “in” and maintaining them in a sufficiently local proximity to compose a physical unit. That is, it is not especially relevant whether the functional components of the system (we may exclude the “waste”) come from the environment or are produced internally, what is important is that they be present.Footnote 13 If the chemical reactions of a system produce 90 % of its components and the other 10 % are taken from the environment, this system is no more autopoietic than one which produces 10 % of its components and takes the other 90 % from its environment; for this reason there cannot be “degrees” of autopoiesis.Footnote 14 This means that there is circularity, but even in a system based on production the circularity does not come from the production relations, but rather from a circularity of physical proximity. Thus the basis of the circularity is that the physical proximity of the components of the system allows the production of components whose internal production is necessary for the physical proximity of the components of the system (that which constitutes the network as a discrete unit in space). This may allow us to understand Varela’s emphasis on the production of membrane components that spontaneously form vesicles as a very practical specification of the concept of autopoiesis; not because the production of a boundary is in itself essential, but rather because the membrane is an efficient manner of maintaining a molecular system united, especially in an aquatic medium. If the system does not control molecules diffusion reactants’ dilution will lead to the cessation of chemical reactions in which they are involved.Footnote 15

This causal relation may be profitably understood as a ‘probabilistic causality’.Footnote 16 That is, what the physical proximity of the components of a system does is to increase the probability that the components of the system are constantly in physical proximity. Thus, autopoiesis would be a particular type of circular probabilistic causality. Physical proximity (or spatial-temporal cohesion) is not a scientifically unimportant quality; on the contrary, it is the base of all chemical reactions, catalysis in particular. If we want to produce a chemical reaction, what we have to do is bring the reactants into close proximity, which greatly increases the probability that the product will be produced. In fact, this is exactly what a catalyst does; an enzyme is a “molecular approximation machine”.

In summary, paraphrasing Maturana and Varela, an autopoietic machine is a homeostatic system of chemical production which has its own individual identity as a variable which it maintains constant.Footnote 17 ‘Individual identity’ is understood to be the same as ‘numerical identity’ or ‘quantitative identity (reviewed in Noonan 2009), that is, the maintenance of a discrete spatio-temporal unit (i.e., without losing spatio-temporal continuity or increasing or decreasing its ‘number’ or ‘quantity’), although its properties or qualities may change (i.e. losing its ‘qualitative identity’, see Noonan 2009). Thus the only condition on the chemical system is that it maintains constantly (by its chemical production) its components in physical proximity in such a way that it insures the spatio-temporal continuity which characterizes it as a unit.Footnote 18

It must be kept in mind that a living system is not only a physical system but notably also a chemical system. What distinguishes a living bacterium from a frozen bacterium or a crystal is that the living being is a machine characterized by chemical reactions. A crystal maintains its individual identity by itself (and the physical proximity of its constituents) trivially, due to the immobility of the relative positions of its components, but it is not a production machine. It is very easy in the laboratory to generate a crystal spontaneously; however, generating a concatenated system of chemical reactions which maintains its individual identity thanks to the products of these reactions is something that only has been achieved recently by Luisi and collaborators artificially in the laboratory, and they still have not been able to make the system homeostatic. From the chemical point of view, what is impressive about living systems is their exceptional coherence of chemical reactions which maintain stably (i.e. without disintegrating or spreading out in a continuous massFootnote 19) a discrete unit in space-time.

From the above we extract that possibly the idea of autopoiesis has seemed trivial to some because it is not commonly emphasized that chemical reactions (i.e. processes of chemical production) are not similar, in relevant aspects, to the springs of physicists or the circuits of engineers. Chemical reactions imply the constant modification of the individual identity of the components involved (reactants which become products), which in general impedes a component from maintaining its function over time (the main exceptions are the enzymes). This makes it very difficult to produce or even outline formally the conditions which permit the continued existence of an autopoietic system based on chemical reactions. This does not occur with the homeostasis of a servomechanism or the self-organization of a tornado or a Bénard cell. In these cases it is true that a tornado or a Bénard cell are units whose dynamics make probable the incorporation of components from their surroundings which maintain their individual identity. However, what makes them different from a living being is that living beings are systems which produce components in the form of chemical reactions, in which the individual identity of the components is constantly modified. The maintenance of individual identity of a tornado does not involve more variables than the position and velocity of the particles in its locality. The particles themselves are not modified in the whirlwind; they enter and leave without modifying their identity. They have the same form when they enter and when they leave, they leave being “themselves”, without substantial modification.Footnote 20

In summary, and as a specification of D1 in physical space, I propose a schematic definition of molecular autopoiesis (D2):

D2: A system is autopoietic if and only if:

  1. 1.

    It is a network of physical and chemical processes.

  2. 2.

    This network chemically produces a subset of the components which are parts of the network.

  3. 3.

    This subset of components, by means of relations among its members and with the components of its surroundings, generates the conditions necessary to maintain the components of the network in physical proximity, collectively forming a spatially discrete individual unit over time.

Autopoiesis and Organization

One of the greatest sources of confusion generated around the concept of autopoiesis has been the use that Maturana and Varela gave to the concept of ‘organization’. One phrase of Maturana and Varela (that was paraphrased previously) was used recurrently to explain what an autopoietic system is: “A living system is a homeostatic system whose homeostatic organization has its own organization as the variable that it maintains constant” (Maturana and Varela 1980, p. 48). I will show that the emphasis of the authors in the maintenance of self-organization is difficult to understand due to the sense in which the word ‘organization’ is used by these authors.

At first the reader tends to interpret ‘organization’ in the usual way, that is, as the configuration of the existing relations among the components of a system; as “the relations which determine…the dynamics of the interactions and transformations of the components” (Maturana and Varela 1994, p. 67). But later in the text one understands that, according to the authors, the organization which is maintained constant in the case of an autopoietic system is the type of organization which defines living beings, that is, autopoietic organization. Thus the questioned affirmation is equivalent to saying “an autopoietic system is a system which maintains its autopoietic organization as the variable which it maintains constant”. That is like saying that “a chair is an object that maintains its chair organization as the variable which it maintains constant”. That is, the affirmation would be only a non-informative tautology (i.e., by definition of its terms it cannot be false). On the other hand, if by ‘organization’ we understand “the relations which determine…the dynamics of the interactions and transformations of the components” (as is usual), the affirmation would imply a system composed of relations which do not change over time, a system without ontogeny, without individual history (and of course an insect in metamorphosis would not be a living being, see Valenzuela 2007); that is, something very different from the idea of a living being. As we saw before, definition D1 implies that what characterizes an autopoietic system is not its capacity to oppose changes in its organization, but rather its capacity to oppose the disintegration of its spatio-temporal unity (in spite of its constant chemical reactions). This also implies that the concept of ‘organizational invariance’ (Letelier et al. 2003, 2006; Cornish-Bowden et al. 2007) is not an acceptable term as a formalization of the concept of autopoiesis.

Some of the confusion related to the concept of autopoiesis are associated with a number of the pseudo-problems and classical confusions which have been generated in philosophy and continue to the present day, due to not distinguishing between ‘individual identity’ (=‘quantitative’ or ‘numeric’ identity) and ‘qualitative’ identity (these pseudo-problems are reviewed in Tugendhat 2002 [1992] and Tugendhat and Wolf 1997 [1983]). Individual identity refers to what specifies particular individuals (or ‘tokens’ in philosophical jargon), while qualitative identity refers to what specifies the classes (or kinds) of individuals defined according to their properties (or ‘types’). This confusion arises principally because both concepts are referred to using the ambiguous terms of “identity” or “self” .Footnote 21 Maturana clearly defines ‘organization’ as that which specifies the type or class to which an individual or system pertains, distinguishing it from the ‘structure’ that specifies the characteristics of the individual as a particular system or “token” .Footnote 22 However, the authors tend to specify an autopoietic system as a system which achieves the production and maintenance of a same (constant) organization. That is, unless the authors want to fall into a simple tautology by making ‘organization’ equal ‘autopoietic organization’, they are affirming that autopoietic systems are systems which produce that which maintains their qualitative identity (their properties) constant. That is, systems which do not change their properties during their lives! In other words, the affirmation is either tautological or is false. Put another way, autopoietic systems do not maintain an organizational homeostasis (homeostasis of their qualitative identity), but rather a homeostasis of their individual unity (homeostasis of their quantitative identity). This is the reason for the paraphrase based on D1: An autopoietic machine is a homeostatic system of chemical production which has its own individual identity as the variable which it maintains constant.Footnote 23

Another of the pseudoproblems related to autopoiesis due to not distinguishing between qualitative identity and individual (or quantitative) identity is the so-called problem of ‘infinite regression’ stated by Rosen (1959) in the causal circularity of living beings (Letelier et al. 2003, 2006; Cornish-Bowden and Cárdenas 2008). Robert Rosen believed that there was a kind of paradox in the regeneration of components, in which the components of a living being are produced by other components of the being, which in turn are produced by other components of the being, and so on. However, the error lies in not considering that the regeneration is a replacement of elements of the same type. There is nothing paradoxical in a series of events among particular elements (tokens) producing reactions which generate other particular elements. What makes the system stable over time is that the elements produced are approximately of the same type (approximately, of course, unless there is no change of qualities during ontogeny). In fact, in autopoiesis there is regeneration of both the types of elements and the types of relations (which, as an “epiphenomenon”, produce the regeneration of the process of regeneration). Thus there is no “infinite regression” whatsoever in living beings which is different from any other habitual causal process in nature, including any cybernetic machine.Footnote 24

Autopoiesis and Multicelularity

The essentiality that biology gives of chemical reactions to understand the life is well represented in Helmont’s (1648) claim: ‘All life is chemistry’ (from Pross 2004). Certainly, the main sources of control of processes in living systems are chemical reactions. However, even in unicellular organisms and minimal cell prototypes many necessary processes to the system maintenance are different from chemical reactions or processes catalyzed by chemical reactions of the system. For example, in the model of Varela et al. (1974, McMullin and Varela 1997) there are reactions of concatenation and disintegration that are not catalyzed by products of the system (McMullin 2000). Furthermore, processes of molecules diffusion and vesicles formation are physical spontaneous processes in which there are not changes of chemical substances. Thus, in living beings not all processes (relations) necessary to maintain the system are, or are catalyzed by, chemical reactions. In addition, multicellular living beings depend essentially on many physical (non chemical) processes to its maintenance. For example, circulatory, lymphatic, and respiratory systems in animals are based on fluids flowing within a network of vessels, valves and chambers, in which changes of pressures, heat release and many other physical phenomena are fundamental to organism’s survival. A single mechanical obstruction of a cerebral artery may cause the death and disintegration of a multicellular organism (see also Goldenfeld and Woese 2011).

Maturana and Varela (1973, 1980) briefly characterized multicellular organisms as “second-order autopoietic systems”, which means that they are made up of (first-order) autopoietic systems.Footnote 25 However, they do not affirm that multicellular organisms are first-order autopoietic systems. Maturana and Varela (1992 [1987]) faced directly this problem: ‘What is the organization of metacellulars?… Are some metacellulars autopoietic unities? That is, are second-order autopoietic systems also first-order autopoietic systems?’ (p. 87). However, authors finally avoided giving a response: ‘For the purposes of this book, we shall leave open the question of whether or not metacellular systems are first-order autopoietic systems.’ Because ‘in the case of metacellulars, we are still ignorant of the molecular processes that would constitute those metacellulars as autopoietic unities comparable to cells.’ (pp. 88–89) and characterized multicellular organisms only as “lineages” of cells. This point becomes critical to autopoiesis becomes a unifying concept for biology and a good definition of living being. If multicellular organisms (the paradigmatic living beings, Wilson 2000) are not autopoietic then multicellular organisms are not living beings! In fact, according to Weber and Varela (2002), multicellular organisms are not themselves autopoietic systems: ‘Autopoiesis has been explicitly formulated for the minimal living system, the cell. (…) A multicellular organism (and this includes all vertebrates usually taken as prototypical organisms) is not in itself an autopoietic unit of second order, since its organization does not follow the same selfcontructing principles.’ (p. 115).

It is possible that Maturana and Varela did not include multicellular organisms as autopoietic systems because of their misguided emphasis in chemical reaction networks and in the production of a boundary, which as I have analyzed previously, are unnecessary for the definition of autopoiesis. According to definitions D1 and D2, multicellular organisms are clearly (first-order) autopoietic systems. The ontogeny of mammals develops from a unicellular (zygote) state to a morula, a blastula and so on, as a consequence of the chemical production of a subgroup of the components which maintain it as a discrete multicellular unit. It is important to note that multicellular organisms such as adult humans produce their own boundary (e.g., the skin in vertebrates, shells and cuticles in invertebrates and plants, respectively); however, in contrast with unicellular organisms, the production of the border is not what physically maintains the system as a unit. We can think of multicellular formations of Myxobacteria in Prokarya or Dictyostelium in Eukarya, but also of human beings tortured by ancient indigenous Moche people in South America whom took the skin off of their prisoners while maintaining them alive (Castillo 2000).Footnote 26 Essential components of multicellular organisms are chemical products that maintain cells joined. Probably the first step in the evolution of multicellularity was the chemical production of components that prevent the daughter cells from separating after the replication (Bonner 1998). It seems that this kind of processes is not improbable because multicellularity has evolved independently many times in each domain of life (Bonner 1998; Carroll 2001). Thus the network of interconnected components of multicellular organisms, chemically produce the components that maintain the components of the network in physical proximity, collectively forming a spatially discrete individual unit over time.

Autopoiesis and Life

Now that the definition of autopoiesis has been re-examined and redefined, it may be seen that the definition of ‘living being’ as a ‘molecular autopoietic system’ is a good definition which serves as a demarcation criterion of living beings. That is, autopoiesis understood in its subtle formulation (D1 and D2) is a singular relational property which effectively allows the differentiation of the main groups of systems which we recognize as living beings from the rest of the objects and non-living systems. As we have seen, the ‘self-production’ characteristic of autopoiesis is not the production of the totality of the components which the system materializes, nor is it the production of the same organization of components and relations which give rise to the products of the network, but rather the production of the subgroup of components which actively conserve the continuous discrete existence of the system (that is, which conserve the spatio-temporal individual identity of the system in spite of the chemical reactions it undergoes). This definition excludes not only the machines generated so far by humans (such as automobiles) and typical inanimate natural objects (such as crystals), but also excludes self-organized dynamic systems such as whirlwinds, Bénard cells, and other natural physical systems as dissipative structures.

A definition of a living being should also serve as a demarcation criterion for “borderline beings”, those at the edge of life. Autopoiesis excludes several such beings such as viruses, viroids, transposons and prions, since these are not systems which have chemical reactions whose products maintain the discreet individual unity in space. Other borderline systems are the apparently “superorganisms” such as those of social insects or colonies of coelenterates; in this case the epithet autopoietic is less clear, since the spatial unity is somewhat less clear. In spite of this, the individual identity of a colony is usually quite clear and may be followed in space and time; these must be included as living beings. This may be unintuitive conclusion is consistent with recent approaches that understand “organismality” as a continuous variable characterized by a high level of cooperation and low level of conflict among parts. These approaches consider that colonies of insects are “organisms” in the same degree than an individual animal or human being (Queller and Strassman 2009; West and Kiers 2009).Footnote 27

One of the permanent difficulties in the definitions of living beings is that they must satisfy two conditions which are in constant tension; they must be compatible with the theories of the origin of life on Earth, in which reproduction appears to be essential, and they must not fall into the “mule paradox” (Szathmáry 2002), that is, conclude that non-reproductive systems such as mules are not living beings. One classical dispute in the theories of the origin of life is whether self-maintained metabolism preceded self-replication or whether self-replication occurred first (Pross 2004). In any case, it appears that the basic characteristic of the most primitive living beings (pre-cellular) is the self-reproduction (of singular molecules or complete metabolic systems) (Pross 2004; Razeto-Barry 2012), which is a key condition for their propagation and evolution. However, any definition which requires self-reproduction as a definitive condition for life falls into the “mule paradox”, that is, it excludes individuals which are clearly living beings but which are not self-reproducing (such as mules and some castes of eusocial insects). The subtle definitions D1 and D2 resolve this tension, because both the growth which tends to self-reproduction and the homeostatic maintenance (not self-reproductive) of a system are special cases which comply with the definition of autopoiesis. Thus both self-reproductive vesicles (e.g., Zepik et al. 2001; Luisi 2006) and non-reproductive organisms (mules, naked mole rats, worker bees, plants without seeds) are autopoietic systems as long as some subset of the products of their internal chemical reactions provides the maintenance of the individual identity of the system. It seems evident that self-reproductive autopoiesis is the ancestral condition, but non self-reproducing autopoiesis has arisen many times in the past, and re-occurs with every organism born infertile (see also Razeto-Barry 2012).

The above is highly relevant for the compatibility of autopoiesis with the theories of the origin of life. The fact that definitions D1 and D2 make autopoiesis compatible with the non-homeostatic self-reproduction without internal disintegration of components is what allows autopoiesis to be compatible with any currently plausible theory of the origin of life on Earth (e.g., see Pross 2004). This is because in general the half life (or spontaneous decay) of the components of living beings is much greater than the life span of the organisms. In fact, the decay of the polymers of currently living beings is the result of complex degradation networks (such as the systems of protein degradation). However, it is hard to imagine that in the origin of life there were sophisticated molecular systems (Pross 2004) such as those required for the degradation of enzymes and other products of metabolism. Thus homeostatic autopoietic systems with internal degradation of components are derived living beings and not primitive ones.Footnote 28 Definitions D1 and D2 not only resolve the mule paradox, but also allow a definition of living being compatible with origin of life theories and serves as a good criterion for the demarcation of uni- and multicellular living beings.

Probably one of the greatest defects of the concept of autopoiesis as a definition of a living being is that it is only a descriptive definition and not mechanical-causal. That is, the property in question does not refer to causes or forces which may be analyzed within physical, chemical or thermodynamic theories. One consequence of this is that the autopoietic property also does not explain other properties of living beings in causal terms. A good definition not only should give the conditions for recognition of a living being, but also the conditions for the production and manipulation of living systems (Escobar 2011). For example, one might require that every reaction of an autopoietic system be spontaneous, but autopoiesis does not specify the thermodynamic conditions which allow the complete system to function as an autonomous machine, nor does it define its energetic relation with the environment. The specification of the directive forces may be essential to the understanding of the nature of life (Pross 2004). However, in spite of this shortcoming, it appears that autopoiesis (under D1 and D2) is the only simple property actually available which allows a satisfactory definition of living being, satisfying the majority of the theoretical and practical criteria of a good definition.

Final Conclusions

The analysis of the concepts of autopoiesis (D1) and molecular autopoiesis (D2) have led me to conclusions which contrast strongly with an important part of the literature which deals with autopoiesis. Here I provide a summary of the points in which this work opposes other publications.

First, I conclude that the autopoiesis of a system does not imply the production of all the components of the system, in contrast to the opinions of Capra 1996; Letelier et al. 2003 and Luisi 2003 (see note 3); thus the circularity of autopoiesis is not a causal circularity of production relations, and therefore I reject the concept of “metabolic closure” (Letelier et al. 2003, 2006) or “closure of the reaction network” (McMullin 2000, p. 167) as a characterization of autopoiesis.

Second, I conclude that the concept of autopoiesis is not tautological, trivial or unscientific, and neither are its derivations, in contrast to the conclusion of a number of authors (Zolo 1990; Munch 1992; Scheper and Scheper 1996, Swenson 1992a, 1992b, Manríquez and Rothammer 1997; Gallardo 1997; Nespolo 2003; Valenzuela 2007, 2010),

Third, the concept of autopoiesis is not highly complex, nor does it imply an undecidable or un-computable process, as suggested by Letelier et al. (2003, 2006) (see also the seventh conclusion below).

Fourth, the internal production of the border or external membrane is not essential to the concept of autopoiesis, in contrast to the analyses and formalizations of Varela et al. (1974), Fleischaker (1988), Luisi et al. (1996), McMullin and Varela (1997), and Varela (2000).

Fifth, multicellular organisms are first-order autopoietic systems (in contrast to Weber and Varela 2002).

Sixth, the disintegration and regeneration of disintegrated components is not essential to autopoiesis, in contrast to Varela et al. (1974), McMullin and Varela (1997), Varela (2000), Letelier et al. (2003, 2006), McMullin (2004), Cornish-Bowden et al. (2007), Cornish-Bowden and Cárdenas (2007).

Seventh, and as a consequence of the previous, I conclude that autopoietic systems are not a type of Robert Rosen’s (M,R) system, in contrast to the conclusions of Letelier et al. (2003, 2006), Cornish-Bowden et al. (2007) and Cornish-Bowden and Cárdenas (2007). One consequence of this is the third conclusion above.

Eighth, I conclude that the concept of autopoiesis is not in contraposition to that of self-reproduction (in contrast, for example, to Cornish-Bowden and Cárdenas 2007) and that the homeostatic autopoietic systems described by the majority of the formalizations of the concept (Maturana and Varela 1972; 1980; Varela et al. 1974; Varela 1979; McMullin and Varela 1997; Varela 2000; McMullin 2004; Letelier et al. 2003, 2006; Cornish-Bowden et al. 2007; Cornish-Bowden and Cárdenas 2007) are only particular cases of an autopoietic system, which do not correspond to the systems which characterized the origin of life, which in turn implies that homeostatic autopoiesis is an evolutionary derived, not primitive property.

Ninth, I conclude that an autopoietic system is not a system which maintains the properties of its organization (type) constant, in contrast to Maturana and Varela (1973, 1980), due to which I reject the term ‘organizational invariance’ of Letelier et al. (2003, 2006) and Cornish-Bowden et al. (2007) as a formalization of the concept of autopoiesis.

Tenth, I conclude that the so-called problem of ‘infinite regression’ of Rosen (1959), Letelier et al. (2003, 2006) and Cornish-Bowden and Cárdenas (2008) is a pseudo-problem produced by not distinguishing between the concepts of ‘individual identity’ (quantitative) and ‘qualitative identity’.