Skip to main content

Advertisement

Log in

Negative mechanistic reasoning in medical intervention assessment

  • Published:
Theoretical Medicine and Bioethics Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Traditionally, mechanistic reasoning has been assigned a negligible role in standard EBM (evidence-based medicine) literature, although some recent authors have argued for an upgrade. Even so, the mechanistic reasoning that has received attention has almost exclusively been positive—both in an epistemic sense of claiming that there is a mechanistic chain and in a health-related sense of there being claimed benefits for the patient. Negative mechanistic reasoning has been neglected, both in the epistemic and in the health-related sense. I distinguish three main types of negative mechanistic reasoning and subsume them under a new definition of mechanistic reasoning in the context of assessing medical interventions. This definition is wider than a previous suggestion in the literature. Each negative type corresponds to a range of evidential strengths, and it is argued that there are differences with respect to typical evidential strengths. The variety of negative mechanistic reasoning should be acknowledged in EBM, and it presents a serious challenge to proponents of so-called medical hierarchies of evidence.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Of course, an inference about an outcome not related to a medical intervention, e.g., an inference referring to the laws of gravitation, could be due to mechanistic reasoning, but hardly in the present context of interest.

  2. It could be noted that several writers seem to take for granted that certain reasoning in which no mechanism is presented still qualifies as mechanistic. For example, Howick, Glasziou, and Aronson in spite of the denial in their own definition that such reasoning is mechanistic, write that “[m]any EBM proponents accept mechanistic reasoning…for…ruling out implausible hypotheses” [5, p. 433].

  3. Quotation and medical claims taken from a manufacturer’s webpage, www2.valkee.com/uk/ [accessed September 18, 2014].

  4. For example, they should not be interpreted to entail that a single study of a type higher up in the hierarchy always outweighs any number of studies belonging to types further down.

References

  1. OCEBM Levels of Evidence Working Group. 2011. The Oxford Centre for Evidence-Based Medicine 2011 levels of evidence, http://www.cebm.net/wp-content/uploads/2014/06/CEBM-Levels-of-Evidence-2.1.pdf. Accessed Nov. 5, 2015.

  2. Straus, S.E., W.S. Richardson, P. Glasziou, and R.B. Haynes. 2005. Evidence-based medicine: how to practice and teach EBM, 3rd ed. Edinburgh: Elsevier.

    Google Scholar 

  3. Guyatt, G., and D. Rennie (eds.). 2002. Users guides to the medical literature: a manual for evidence-based clinical practice. Chicago: American Medical Association Press.

    Google Scholar 

  4. Howick, J. 2011. The philosophy of evidence-based medicine. Wiley-Blackwell and BMJ Books.

  5. Howick, J., P. Glasziou, and J.K. Aronson. 2010. Evidence-based mechanistic reasoning. Journal of the Royal Society of Medicine 103: 433–441.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  6. La Caze, A. 2011. The role of basic science in evidence-based medicine. Biology & Philosophy 26(1): 81–98.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  7. Howick, J., P. Glasziou, and J.K. Aronson. 2013. Can understanding mechanisms solve the problem of extrapolating from study to target populations (the problem of ‘external validity’)? Journal of the Royal Society of Medicine 106: 81–86.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  8. Clarke, B., D. Gillies, P. Illari, F. Russo, and J. Williamson. 2013. The evidence that evidence-based medicine omits. Preventive Medicine 57(6): 745–747.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  9. Clarke, B., D. Gillies, P. Illari, F. Russo, and J. Williamson. 2014. Mechanisms and the evidence hierarchy. Topoi 33(2): 339–360.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  10. Goodman, S.N., and J. Gerson. 2013. Mechanistic evidence in evidence-based medicine: a conceptual framework. Agency for Healthcare Research and Quality. AHRQ Publication No. 13-EHC042-EF. http://www.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/books/NBK154584/pdf/Bookshelf_NBK154584.pdf. Accessed Nov. 5, 2015.

  11. Andersen, H. 2012. Mechanisms: What are they evidence for in evidence-based medicine? Journal of Evaluation in Clinical Practice 18(5): 992–999.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  12. Bluhm, R. 2013. Physiological mechanisms and epidemiological research. Journal of Evaluation in Clinical Practice 19(3): 422–426.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  13. Osimani, B. 2014. Hunting side effects and explaining them: Should we reverse evidence hierarchies upside down? Topoi 33(2): 295–312.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  14. Illari, P.M., and J. Williamson. 2012. What is a mechanism? Thinking about mechanisms across the sciences. European Journal for Philosophy of Science 2: 119–135.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  15. Steel, D. 2008. Across the boundaries: extrapolation in biology and social science. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  16. Hesslow, G. 1976. Two notes on the probabilistic approach to causality. Philosophy of Science 43(2): 290–292.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  17. Turner, A.J. 2012. Evidence based medicine, ‘placebos’ and the homeopathy controversy. PhD Diss.: University of Nottingham.

    Google Scholar 

  18. Hammerstrøm, K.T., and A. Bjørndal. 2011. If there are no randomised controlled trials, do we always need more research? [editorial]. Cochrane Database of Systematic Reviews. http://www.cochranelibrary.com/editorial/10.1002/14651858.ED000024. Accessed Nov. 5, 2015.

  19. Lee, A., and L.T.Y. Fan. 2009. Stimulation of the wrist acupuncture point P6 for preventing postoperative nausea and vomiting. Cochrane Database of Systematic Reviews 2009(2): CD003281.

    Google Scholar 

  20. Kelly, T. 2006. Evidence. In The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy (Fall 2008 Edition), ed. E.N. Zalta. http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2008/entries/evidence/. Accessed Nov. 5, 2015.

  21. Nordenstrom, J. 2007. Evidence-based medicine in Sherlock Holmes’ footsteps. Malden, MA: Blackwell Publishing.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  22. Stegenga, J. 2014. Down with the hierarchies. Topoi 33(2): 313–322.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  23. Hansson, S.O. 2014. Why and for what are clinical trials the gold standard? Scandinavian Journal of Public Health 42(Suppl. 13): 41–48.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Jesper Jerkert.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Jerkert, J. Negative mechanistic reasoning in medical intervention assessment. Theor Med Bioeth 36, 425–437 (2015). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11017-015-9348-2

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11017-015-9348-2

Keywords

Navigation