Skip to main content
Log in

Ostensive Learnability as a Test Criterion for Theory-Neutral Observation Concepts

  • Special Section Article: Theory-Ladenness
  • Published:
Journal for General Philosophy of Science Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

In the first part of my paper I discuss eight arguments in favour of the theory-dependence of observation: (1) realistic content, (2) guidance function of theories, (3) perception as cognitive construction, (4) expectation-dependence of perception, (5) theory-dependence of scientific data, (6) continuity between observational and theoretical concepts, (7) language-dependence, and (8) meaning holism. I argue that although these arguments make correct points, they do not exclude the existence of observations that are weakly theory-neutral in the sense that they don’t depend on acquired background knowledge. In the second part I suggest an experimental method, the method of ostensive learning experiments, by which the degree of theory- and language-independence of a concept can be tested.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Fig. 1
Fig. 2
Fig. 3
Fig. 4
Fig. 5
Fig. 6
Fig. 7

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. For arguments in this direction cf. Chalmers (1986, sec. 3.4); van Fraassen (1980, 56ff), Albert (1985, sec. II.8); Brewer and Lambert (2001, 182f.)

  2. That we don't regard the innate mechanisms of human vision as "theories" does not imply that we don't consider it as an important question to which extent these mechanisms construct an accurate image of the world. According to the findings of cognitive psychology, our visual image of the world that surrounds us is accurate in ordinary situations that were selectively relevant for our evolutionary ancestors to survive, but it may mislead us in situations that are exceptional from an evolutionary viewpoint.

  3. E.g., Putnam (1962), Shapere (1982), Kuipers (2000), Giere (1999), Adam (2004).

  4. An experiment of this sort has been performed by Hakan Beseoglu in Duesseldorf with students from high school and is not yet completed.

References

  • Adam, M. (2004). Why worry about theory-dependence? International Studies in the Philosophy of Science, 18, 117–132.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Albert, H. (1985). Treatise on critical reason. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Berlin, B., & Kay, P. (1999). Basic colour terms: Their universality and evolution. Stanford: CSLI Publications (orig. 1969)

    Google Scholar 

  • Brewer, W. F., & Lambert, B. L. (2001). The theory-ladenness of observation and the theory-ladenness of the rest of the scientific process. Philosophy of Science, 68, S176–S186. Proceedings.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brown, H. I. (1993). A theory-laden observation can test the theory. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 44, 555–559.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Carnap, R. (1928). Pseudoproblems in philosophy. In R. Carnap (2003). The logical structure of the world and pseudoproblems in philosophy (pp. 301–343). Chicago: Open Court.

  • Carnap, R. (1936/37). Testability and meaning. Philosophy of Science, 3, 419–471, and 4, 2–40.

  • Carnap, R. (1956). The methodological character of theoretical concepts. In H. Feigl & M. Scriven (Eds.), Minnesota studies in the philosophy of science (Vol. I, pp. 38–76). Minneapolis: Univ. of Minnesota Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Carnap, R. (1966). Philosophical foundations of physics. New York: Basic Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chalmers, A. F. (1986). What is this thing called science? Queensland: Univ. of Queensland Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Churchland, P. M. (1979). Scientific realism and the plasticity of mind. Cambridge: Cambridge Univ. Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Churchland, P. M. (1989). A neurocomputational perspective: The nature of the mind and the structure of science. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Churchland, P. S., and Sejnowski, T. (1992). The computational brain. Cambridge/Mass.: MIT Press.

  • Dancy, J. (1985). An Introduction to Contemporary Epistemology. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Davidoff, J., et al. (1999). Colour categories in a stone-age tribe. Nature, 398, 203–204.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Estany, A. (2001). The thesis of theory-laden observation in the light of cognitive psychology. Philosophy of Science, 68, 203–217.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Feyerabend, P. (1975). Against method. London: Verso (3rd ed. 1993, repr. 2002).

  • Fodor, J. (1984). Observation reconsidered. Philosophy of Science, 51, 23–43.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Forbes, E. G. (1983). The pre-discovery observations of Uranus. In G. Hunt (Ed.), Uranus and the outer planets (pp. 67–79). Cambridge: Cambridge Univ. Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Garnham, A., & Oakhill, J. (1994). Thinking and reasoning. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Giere, R. (1999). Science without laws. Chicago: Univ. of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Grossberg, S. (1980). How does a brain build a cognitive code? Psychological Review, 87, 1–51.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hanson, N. R. (1958). Patterns of discovery. Cambridge: Cambridge Univ. Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Helmholtz, H. von (1896/1910). Treatise on physiological optics. http://poseidon.sunyopt.edu/ BackusLab/Helmholtz/(German orig. 1896).

  • Hempel, C. G. (1966). Philosophy of natural sciences. Englewood Cliffs: Prentice Hall.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hempel, C. G. (1988). Provisos: A problem concerning the inferential function of scientific theories. In A. Grünbaum & W. Salmon (Eds.), The Limitations of Deductivism (pp. 19–36). Berkeley: University of California Press.

  • Kuhn, T. S. (1962). The structure of scientific revolutions. Chicago: Univ. of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kuipers, T. A. F. (2000). From instrumentalism to constructive realism. Dordrecht: Kluwer.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Kutschera, F.v., (1976). Philosophy of language. Dordrecht: Reidel.

    Google Scholar 

  • Martindale, C. (1991). Cognitive psychology. Pacific Grove: Cole Publication Company.

    Google Scholar 

  • Maxwell, G. (1962). The ontological status of theoretical entities. In H. Feigl & G. Maxwell (Eds.), Minnesota studies in the philosophy of science (Vol. III, pp. 3–27). Minneapolis: Univ. of Minnesota Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nagel, E. (1979). Teleology revisited and other essays. New York: Columbia University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Neurath, O. (1934). Radical physicalism and ‘the real world’. In: Neurath, O. (1983). Philosophical papers 1913–46 (pp. 100–104). Dordrecht: Reidel.

  • Popper, K. (1935/2002). Logic of discovery. London: Routledge 2002 (German orig. 1935).

  • Putnam, H. (1962). What theories are not. In E. Nagel, P. Suppes, & A. Tarski (Eds.), Logic, Methodology and Philo-sophy of Science (pp. 240–251). Stanford: Stanford Univ. Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pylyshyn, Z. (1999). Is vision continuous with cognition? Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 22, 341–365.

    Google Scholar 

  • Quine, W. V. O. (1951). Two dogmas of empiricism. Philosophical Review, 60, 20–43.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Quine, W. V. O. (1960). Word and object. Massachusetts: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Quine, W. V. O. (1974). The roots of reference. La Salle: Open Court Publ.

    Google Scholar 

  • Quine, W. V. O. (1992). Pursuit to truth. Cambridge, MA: Harvard Univ. Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rock, I. (1984). Perception. New York: Scientific American Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shapere, D. (1982). The concept of observation in science and philosophy. Philosophy of Science, 49, 485–525.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Van Fraassen, B. (1980). The scientific image. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Whorf, B.L. (1956). Language, thought and reality (ed. by J.B. Carroll). Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press.

  • Wittgenstein, L. (1945/2001). Philosophical Investigations. Oxford: Blackwell Publishing.

Download references

Acknowledgement

Work on this paper was supported by the DFG-grant SCHU1566/3-2 of the research group FOR 600 at the University of Duesseldorf.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Gerhard Schurz.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Schurz, G. Ostensive Learnability as a Test Criterion for Theory-Neutral Observation Concepts. J Gen Philos Sci 46, 139–153 (2015). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10838-015-9290-z

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10838-015-9290-z

Keywords

Navigation