Skip to main content
Log in

The Mystery of the Triceratops’s Mother: How to be a Realist About the Species Category

  • Original Article
  • Published:
Erkenntnis Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Can we be realists about a general category but pluralists about concepts relating to that category? I argue that paleobiological methods of delineating species are not affected by differing species concepts, and that this underwrites an argument that species concept pluralists should be species category realists. First, the criteria by which paleobiologists delineate species are ‘indifferent’ to the species category. That is, their method for identifying species applies equally to any species concept. To identify a new species, paleobiologists show that interspecies processes, such as phenotypic plasticity (including pathology), sexual dimorphism, or ontogenetic diversity, are a worse explanation of the variance between specimens than intraspecies processes. As opposed to operating under a single or plurality of species concepts, then, paleobiologists use abductive inferences, which would be required regardless of any particular species concept. Second, paleobiologists are frequently interested in large-scale, long-term morphological patterns in the fossil record, and resolving the fine-grained differences which result from different species concepts is irrelevant at those scales. I argue that this claim about paleobiological practice supports what I call ‘indifference realism’ about the species category. The indifference realist argues that when legitimate investigation is indifferent to a plurality of concepts, we should be realists about the category those concepts pertain to.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Fig. 1
Fig. 2

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. But see Sober (1984), Wilkins (2003, 2009), Hull (1988), Ghiselin (1987).

  2. For instance, Kitcher (1984), Mishler and Brandon (1987), Dupré (1999), Ereshefsky (2001), Reydon (2004), O'Malley and Dupré (2007).

  3. See Mayr (1942), Dobzhansky (1937), Paterson (1985) and Ghiselin (1987) for variations.

  4. See Avise and Wollenberg (1997) and Baum and Shaw (1995).

  5. Again, this is an extremely simplified discussion, see Andam et al. (2010), Bapteste and Burian (2010), Bapteste et al. (2009) and Ereshefsky (2010) for more details on the relationship between species concepts, eukaryotes and other asexual organisms.

  6. A good place to look for skepticism about such a link is Kyle Stanford’s work, for instance his (2006).

  7. I skate over some subtlety here. Ereshefsky (2001) has pointed out that, if we don’t think there is an interesting difference between species and higher taxa, this is a kind of species anti-realism. If that is right, then my argument is for taxa-category realism, rather than species-category realism. I am comfortable with this—realism about some category is fine with me: I won’t quibble about whether we get to call them ‘species’. I return to these points in 6.4.

  8. Speculating about extreme changes in dinosaur life-stages has become de-rigour. It has been suggested, for instance, that the enormous sauropods both led very different lives in their juvenile and adult stages, for instance it has been speculated that they switched from fast-growing endothermy to relaxed ectothermy mid-life (Farlow 1990). It has also been suggested that Tyrannosaurus rex had two distinctive ontogenetic stages, a juvenile stage characterized by fast running speeds and feathers, and a slow, featherless adult packing a major bite (see Currie 1998; Erickson et al. 2004).

  9. Indeed, Schott et al. (2011) suggest this of pachycephalosaurus.

  10. See Schulte et al. (2010) for a view which emphasizes the role of the impact, and Archibald et al. (2010) for a view which sees it as one cause amongst many.

  11. See Roberts et al (in press) for discussion of the phenomenon.

  12. Pian et al. (2013), for example, introduce a new extinct platypus species, Odurodon tharalkooschild, largely on the basis that its enormous size outruns the expected phenotypic range of any other platypus.

  13. A nice case of an objection to species delineation on the basis of pathology is the suggestion in Barham (2004) that Homo floresiensis, the so-called ‘Hobbits’, are merely humans exhibiting microcephaly. In fact, taxonomy is the subject of voracious debate in paleoanthropology: see, for instance, the back and forth between Ian Tattersal and Matt Cartmill, which concluded with the memorable Tattersall (2013).

  14. Thanks to an anonymous referee for distinguishing between ‘indifference’ and ‘irrelevence’.

  15. Brandon Holter has suggested to me that indifference could come in degrees: that is, the identification criteria could matter more on some concept than others. He points to the ‘mate recognition’ species concept, whereby species are delineated via mating preferences which restrict gene-flow. Assuming the recognised features are morphological (rather than, say, hormonal), these criteria may matter more for that species concept than, say, a phylogenetic one. Formally, I take indifference to be binary, but I don’t think this matters for the argument herein.

  16. One way of stating this would be to claim that S forms a monophyletic clade of which f is a member, or that S is an historical individual of which f is a part.

  17. There is, in fact, one case of fossil organisms caught in an extremely extended coitus interruptus: a group of Eocene turtles (see Joyce et al. 2012).

  18. Note that paleobiologists frequently represent this information in terms of higher-taxa categories. This is typically because the fossil record is sometimes less biased when considered by genus or family.

  19. Thanks to David Leibesman for highlighting this problem.

  20. An analogous move is suggested in Lewis (1978).

  21. It may turn out that some paleobiological claims are indeterminate on this kind of view, and as David Leibesman has pointed out to me, this might involve exploring whether vagueness might undermine the link between practice and ontology.

  22. Naturally, for epistemic anti-realists such as Stanford and Rosenberg, this is less pressing. Although, if they are realists about various taxa which species concept pick out, there remains a tension.

  23. Marc Ereshesfsky raised this objection.

  24. I am thankful to an anonymous referee for raising this objection.

  25. This kind of objection could be made via appeal to work from the philosophy of mind on disjunctive properties. Hilary Putnam (1967), Block and Fodor (1972), Fodor (1974) have argued that disjunctive kinds are illegitimate. In that context, the argument centers on the nature of multiple-realizability: a large number of different substrates, in different arrangements, could potentially have what it takes to be a particular propositional attitude. It is likely, for instance, that a different neural correlate is involved with my thinking x than for your thinking x. However, it seems as if we can think the same x, that is, our xs can have the same content. If so, then either propositional attitudes should be characterized functionally (or in some other non-reductive way), or the identity theorist may accept a disjunction of those various substrates as a real kind. In rejecting identity-theory, then, philosophers of mind have argued against admitting disjunctive kinds into our ontology.

  26. Marc Ereshefsky raised this objection.

  27. Thanks to an anonymous referee for raising this objection.

References

  • Andam, C. P., Williams, D., & Gogarten, J. P. (2010). Natural taxonomy in light of horizontal gene transfer. Biology and Philosophy, 25(4), 589–602.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Archibald, J. D., Clemens, W. A., Padian, K., Rowe, T., Macleod, N., Barrett, P. M. et al. (2010). Cretaceous extinctions: multiple causes. Science (New York, NY), 328(5981), 973–975.

  • Avise, J. C., & Wollenberg, K. (1997). Phylogenetics and the origin of species. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences, 94(15), 7748–7755.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bapteste, E., & Burian, R. M. (2010). On the need for integrative phylogenomics, and some steps toward its creation. Biology and Philosophy, 25(4), 711–736.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bapteste, E., O’Malley, M. A., Beiko, R. G., Ereshefsky, M., Gogarten, J. P., Franklin-Hall, L., et al. (2009). Prokaryotic evolution and the tree of life are two different things. Biology Direct, 4(1), 34.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Barham, L. (2004). Some initial informal reactions to publication of the discovery of Homo floresiensis and replies from Brown & Morwood. Before Farm, 4, 1–7.

    Google Scholar 

  • Baum, D. A., & Shaw, K. L. (1995). Genealogical perspectives on the species problem. Experimental and molecular approaches to plant biosystematics, 53, 289–303.

    Google Scholar 

  • Benton, M. J. (1999). The history of life: large databases in palaeontology. In Numerical Palaeobiology (pp. 249–283). NY: Wiley.

  • Block, N. J., & Fodor, J. A. (1972). What psychological states are not. The Philosophical Review, 81, 159–181.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brigandt, I. (2003). Species pluralism does not imply species eliminativism. Philosophy of Science, 70(5), 1305–1316.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Currie, P. J. (1998). Possible evidence of gregarious behavior in tyrannosaurids. Gaia, 15, 271–277.

    Google Scholar 

  • De Queiroz, K. (1999). The general lineage concept of species and the defining properties of the species category. In R. Wilson (Ed.), Species: New Interdisciplinary Essays (pp. 49–89). Boston: MIT.

  • Dobzhansky, T. (1937). Genetics and the origin of species. New York: Columbia University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dupré, J. (1993). The disorder of things: Metaphysical foundations of the disunity of science. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dupré, J. (1999). On the impossibility of a monistic account of species. In R. A. Wilson (Ed.), Species: New interdisciplinary essays (pp. 3–22). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ereshefsky, M. (1998). Species pluralism and anti-realism. Philosophy of Science, 65(1), 103–120.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ereshefsky, M. (2001). The poverty of the linnaean hierarchy: A philosophical study of biological taxonomy. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Ereshefsky, M. (2010). Microbiology and the species problem. Biology and Philosophy, 25(4), 553–568.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Erickson, G. M., Makovicky, P. J., Currie, P. J., Norell, M. A., Yerby, S. A., & Brochu, C. A. (2004). Gigantism and comparative life-history parameters of tyrannosaurid dinosaurs. Nature, 430(7001), 772–775.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Farlow, J. O. (1990) Dinosaur energetics and thermal biology. In Weishampel, D., & Osmolska (Eds.), The Dinosauria (pp. 43–55). Berkely: University of California Press.

  • Fodor, J. A. (1974). Special sciences (or: the disunity of science as a working hypothesis). Synthese, 28(2), 97–115.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Funk, D. J., & Omland, K. E. (2003). Species-level paraphyly and polyphyly: Frequency, causes, and consequences, with insights from animal mitochondrial DNA. Annual Review of Ecology, Evolution, and Systematics, 34, 397–423.

  • Ghiselin, M. (1987). Species concepts, individuality, and objectivity. Biology and Philosophy, 2, 127–143.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Horner, J. R., & Lamm, E. T. (2011). Ontogeny of the parietal frill of Triceratops: A preliminary histological analysis. Comptes Rendus Palevol, 10(5), 439–452.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hull, D. (1988). Science as a Process. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Joyce, W. G., Micklich, N., Schaal, S. F., & Scheyer, T. M. (2012). Caught in the act: The first record of copulating fossil vertebrates. Biology Letters, 8(5), 846–848.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kitcher, P. (1984). Species. Philosophy of Science, 51, 308–333.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, D. (1978). Truth in fiction. American Philosophical Quarterly, 15(1), 37–46.

    Google Scholar 

  • Longrich, N. R., & Field, D. J. (2012). Torosaurus is not Triceratops: Ontogeny in chasmosaurine ceratopsids as a case study in dinosaur taxonomy. PLoS ONE, 7(2), e32623.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Maiorino, L., Farke, A. A., Kotsakis, T., & Piras, P. (2013). Is Torosaurus Triceratops? Geometric morphometric evidence of late maastrichtian ceratopsid dinosaurs. PLoS ONE, 8(11), e81608.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mayr, E. (1942). Systematics and the origin of species from the viewpoint of a zoologist. New York: Columbia University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mishler, B., & Brandon, R. (1987). Individuality, pluralism, and the phylogenetic species concept. Biology and Philosophy, 2, 397–414.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • O’Malley, M., & Dupré, J. (2007). Size doesn’t matter: Towards a more inclusive philosophy of Biology. Biology and Philosophy, 22, 155–191.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Paterson, H. (1985). The recognition concept of species. In Vrba (Ed.), Species and speciation (pp. 21–29). Pretoria: Transvall Museum.

  • Pian, R., Archer, M., & Hand, S. J. (2013). A new, giant platypus, Obdurodon tharalkooschild, SP. Nov. (Monotremata, Ornithorhynchidae) from the Riversleigh world heritage area, Australia. Journal of Vertebrate Paleontology, 33, 1255–1259.

  • Putnam, H. (1967). Psychological predicates. In W. Capitan & D. Merrill (Eds.), Art, Mind, and Religion (pp. 37–48). Pittsburgh: University of Pittsburgh Press.

  • Reydon, T. A. C. (2004). Why does the species problem still persist? BioEssays, 26, 300–305. doi:10.1002/bies.10406.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Roberts, E. M., Sampson, S. D., Deino, A., & Bowring, S. (in press). The Kaiparowits Formation: A remarkable record of Late Cretaceous terrestrial environments, ecosystems and evolution in Western North America. In A. L. Titus and M. A. Loewen (Eds.), Advances in western interior late cretaceous paleontology and geology. Bloomington: Indiana University Press.

  • Rosenberg, A. (1994). Instrumental Biology or the Disunity of Science. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

  • Scannella, J. B., & Horner, J. R. (2010). Torosaurus Marsh, 1891, is Triceratops Marsh, 1889 (Ceratopsidae: Chasmosaurinae): Synonymy through ontogeny. Journal of Vertebrate Paleontology, 30(4), 1157–1168.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Scannella, J. B., & Horner, J. R. (2011). ‘Nedoceratops’: An example of a transitional morphology. PLoS ONE, 6(12), e28705.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schott, R. K., Evans, D. C., Goodwin, M. B., Horner, J. R., Brown, C. M., & Longrich, N. R. (2011). Cranial ontogeny in Stegoceras validum (Dinosauria: Pachycephalosauria): A quantitative model of pachycephalosaur dome growth and variation. PLoS ONE, 6(6), e21092.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schulte, P., Alegret, L., Arenillas, I., Arz, J. A., Barton, P. J., Bown, P. R., et al. (2010). The Chicxulub asteroid impact and mass extinction at the Cretaceous-Paleogene boundary. Science, 327(5970), 1214–1218.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sober, E. (1984). Sets, species, and natural kinds: A reply to Philip Kitcher’s ‘species’. Philosophy of Science, 51, 334–341.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stanford, P. (1995). For Pluralism and Against Realism about Species. Philosophy of Science 62, 70–91.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stanford, P. K. (2006). Exceeding our grasp: Science, history, and the problem of unconceived alternatives. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

  • Tattersall, I. (2013). Higher taxa: Reply to cartmill. Evolutionary Anthropology, 22, 293.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Turner, D. D. (2009). How much can we know about the causes of evolutionary trends? Biology and Philosophy, 24(3), 341–357.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Turner, D. D. (2011). Paleontology: A philosophical introduction. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Wilkins, J. (2003). How to be a chaste species pluralist-realist. Biology and Philosophy, 18, 621–638.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wilkins, J. (2009). Species: The history of the idea. Berkeley: University of California Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

Brandan Holter, David Liebesman, Marc Ereshefsky and two anonymous referees provided extremely helpful feedback, as did the audience at the 2014 Boston Colloquim on philosophy of paleontology.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Adrian Mitchell Currie.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Currie, A.M. The Mystery of the Triceratops’s Mother: How to be a Realist About the Species Category. Erkenn 81, 795–816 (2016). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10670-015-9769-3

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10670-015-9769-3

Keywords

Navigation