Skip to main content

Advertisement

Log in

Empathy and morality in behaviour readers

  • Published:
Biology & Philosophy Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

It is tempting to assume that being a moral creature requires the capacity to attribute mental states to others, because a creature cannot be moral unless she is capable of comprehending how her actions can have an impact on the well-being of those around her. If this assumption were true, then mere behaviour readers could never qualify as moral, for they are incapable of conceptualising mental states and attributing them to others. In this paper, I argue against such an assumption by discussing the specific case of empathy. I present a characterisation of empathy that would not require an ability to attribute mental states to others, but would nevertheless allow the creature who possessed it to qualify as a moral being. Provided certain conditions are met, a behaviour reader could be motivated to act by this form of empathy, and this means that behaviour readers could be moral. The case for animal morality, I shall argue, is therefore independent of the case for animal mindreading.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. I will use the term 'mindreading,' instead of 'theory of mind,' or 'ToM,' as Povinelli et al. usually call it, in order to avoid the theory-theory connotations of the latter term.

  2. ‘[A] subject lacking an f ToM [i.e. mindreading capabilities] would not have access to r-states [i.e. information] about his own internal cognitive states […]' (Penn and Povinelli 2007, p. 738).

  3. The importance of mindreading for the prediction of behaviour has been questioned by Andrews (2012). Povinelli et al. also acknowledge that, in humans, the attribution of mental states is used more often for explanation than for prediction (Gallagher and Povinelli 2012, p. 151).

  4. However, see Andrews (2013) for an account of autonomy that does not require mindreading.

  5. In Rowlands’ scheme, moral agency is gained through understanding and not through control. See “An empathic behaviour reader” section.

  6. Within Rowlands' scheme, morally laden emotions qualify as reasons, and are not mere causes, because they are emotions that involve content (see “The cognitive requirements of minimal moral empathy ” section).

  7. In making this assumption, I am bracketing several important critiques of Povinelli and colleagues' approach made on both theoretical and empirical grounds, for instance, Andrews (2005), Buckner (2014).

  8. Nothing in my argument turns on whether emotional contagion is indeed a form of empathy.

  9. These four conditions are sufficient for it to be an instance of empathy as a moral emotion, but they are not necessary. Other forms of empathy as a moral emotion may be conceived, some of which may be sufficient for a being to count as a moral agent, and not merely as a moral subject.

  10. But not all. See, for instance Zahavi and Overgaard (2012).

  11. The word ‘specific’ is important. At times, ‘mere’ emotional contagion gives way, not to a non-intentional form of personal distress, but one that has content. For instance, when a bird is startled and flies away, and immediately the rest of the flock follows it, the latter may be due to an emotional contagion that has yielded a state of fear directed towards the possibility of there being a predator around. Although this would be an emotion involving content, it would still be a form of personal distress, for the content involved has no relation whatsoever to the welfare of the conspecific who triggered the emotion.

  12. MME involves both factual content (“This creature is displaying distress behaviour”) and evaluative content (“This creature's distress is bad”). C does not need to be capable of explicitly entertaining the evaluative content of her emotion, but I am assuming that she is capable of entertaining the factual content, and thus, of believing something along the lines of, but not necessarily equivalent to, “This creature is displaying distress behaviour.” A case could perhaps be made for MME only requiring that the factual content be tracked, but I shall not follow this road, since Povinelli and colleagues' work strongly suggests that they would grant me this assumption (see “Behaviour reading versus mindreading” and “An empathic behaviour reader” sections).

  13. Note that the attribution of MME to Higgins not only relies on the badness of Jane's distress, but also, more importantly, on the experiential form that Higgins' emotional contagion takes. In being distressed that she is displaying distress behavior, he is experiencing Jane's distress (behaviour) as something distressful, i.e., as something bad.

  14. Moral subjecthood is not restricted to positive moral emotions. If Higgins were to possess some reliable mechanism that resulted in him rejoicing in the display of distress behaviour in others, and if this motivated him to contribute to their suffering, we would also have to conclude that he is a moral subject. In this case, the moral emotion Higgins would be a subject of might be labeled cruelty or schadenfreude. Note, however, that his lack of understanding would prevent Higgins from being held responsible for his behaviour.

  15. For counter-arguments, see, e.g. DeGrazia (1996), Regan (2004), Rowlands (2009, 2012).

  16. At least the individuals that Kennett is interested in (see Kennett 2002, p. 345).

References

  • Andrews K (2005) Chimpanzee theory of mind: looking in all the wrong places? Mind Lang 20(5):521–536. doi:10.1111/j.0268-1064.2005.00298.x

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Andrews K (2012) Do apes read minds? Toward a new folk psychology. The MIT Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Andrews K (2013) Great ape mindreading: what’s at stake? In: Lanjouw A, Corbey R (eds) Humans and other animals: rethinking the species interface. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, pp 115–125

    Google Scholar 

  • Batson CD (2009) These things called empathy: eight related but distinct phenomena. In: Decety J, Ickes W (eds) The social neuroscience of empathy. MIT Press, Cambridge, pp 3–15

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Bekoff M (2008) The emotional lives of animals: a leading scientist explores animal joy, sorrow, and empathy—and why they matter (First Trade Paper Edition). New World Library, Novato

    Google Scholar 

  • Bekoff M, Pierce J (2010) Wild justice: the moral lives of animals. University of Chicago Press, Chicago

    Google Scholar 

  • Blackburn S (1993) Essays in quasi-realism. Oxford University Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Buckner C (2014) The semantic problem(s) with research on animal mindreading. Mind Lang 29(5):566–589

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Call J, Tomasello M (2008) Does the chimpanzee have a theory of mind? 30 years later. Trends Cognit Sci 12(5):187–192. doi:10.1016/j.tics.2008.02.010

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Carr L, Iacoboni M, Dubeau M-C, Mazziotta JC, Lenzi GL (2003) Neural mechanisms of empathy in humans: a relay from neural systems for imitation to limbic areas. Proc Natl Acad Sci 100(9):5497–5502. doi:10.1073/pnas.0935845100

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dapretto M, Davies MS, Pfeifer JH, Scott AA, Sigman M, Bookheimer SY, Iacoboni M (2006) Understanding emotions in others: mirror neuron dysfunction in children with autism spectrum disorders. Nat Neurosci 9(1):28–30. doi:10.1038/nn1611

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Davidson D (2001) Rational Animals. Oxford University Press, In Subjective, Intersubjective, Objective

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • De Vignemont F, Jacob P (2012) What is it like to feel another’s pain? Philos Sci 79(2):295–316. doi:10.1086/664742

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • De Vignemont F, Singer T (2006) The empathic brain: how, when and why? Trends Cognit Sci 10(10):435–441. doi:10.1016/j.tics.2006.08.008

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • De Waal FBM (2006) Morally evolved: primate social instincts, human morality, and the rise and fall of “veneer theory”. In: Ober J, Macedo S (eds) Primates and philosophers: how morality evolved. Princeton University Press, Princeton, pp 1–82

  • De Waal FBM (2008) Putting the altruism back into altruism: the evolution of empathy. Annu Rev Psychol 59:279–300. doi:10.1146/annurev.psych.59.103006.093625

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • DeGrazia D (1996) Taking animals seriously: mental life and moral status. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Di Pellegrino G, Fadiga L, Fogassi L, Gallese V, Rizzolatti G (1992) Understanding motor events: a neurophysiological study. Exp Brain Res 91(1):176–180

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dixon BA (2008) Animals, emotion & morality: marking the boundary. Prometheus Books, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Gallagher S, Povinelli DJ (2012) Enactive and behavioral abstraction accounts of social understanding in chimpanzees, infants, and adults. Rev Philos Psychol 3(1):145–169

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Goldman AI (2006) Simulating minds: the philosophy, psychology, and neuroscience of mindreading, 1st edn. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Hauser M (2001) Wild minds: what animals really think, New Ed edn. Penguin Books, London

  • Heyes C (1998) Theory of mind in nonhuman primates. Behav Brain Sci 21(1):101–114; discussion 115–148

  • Jabbi M, Swart M, Keysers C (2007) Empathy for positive and negative emotions in the gustatory cortex. NeuroImage 34(4):1744–1753. doi:10.1016/j.neuroimage.2006.10.032

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kennett J (2002) Autism, empathy and moral agency. Philos Q 52(208):340–357. doi:10.1111/1467-9213.00272

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Korsgaard CM (2004) Fellow creatures: Kantian ethics and our duties to animals. In: Peterson G (ed) Tanner lectures on human values, vol 25/26. University of Utah Press, Salt Lake City

    Google Scholar 

  • Korsgaard CM (2006) Morality and the distinctiveness of human action. In: Macedo S, Ober J (eds) Primates and philosophers: how morality evolved. Princeton University Press, Princeton

    Google Scholar 

  • Lurz RW (2009) If chimpanzees are mindreaders, could behavioral science tell? Toward a solution of the logical problem. Philos Psychol 22(3):305–328. doi:10.1080/09515080902970673

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lurz RW (2011) Mindreading animals: the debate over what animals know about other minds. MIT Press, Cambridge

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Maibom HL (2009) Feeling for others: empathy, sympathy, and morality. Inquiry 52(5):483–499

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Masserman J, Wechkin S, Terris W (1964) “Altruistic” behaviour in rhesus monkeys. Am J Psychiatry 121(6):584–585

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Michael J (2014) Towards a consensus about the role of empathy in interpersonal understanding. Topoi 33(1):157–172. doi:10.1007/s11245-013-9204-9

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • O’Connell SM (1995) Empathy in chimpanzees: evidence for theory of mind? Primates 36(3):397–410. doi:10.1007/BF02382862

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Panksepp J (2004) Affective neuroscience: the foundations of human and animal emotions, 1st edn. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Penn DC, Povinelli DJ (2007) On the lack of evidence that non-human animals possess anything remotely resembling a “theory of mind”. Philos Trans R Soc Lond Ser B Biol Sci 362(1480):731–744. doi:10.1098/rstb.2006.2023

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Penn DC, Povinelli DJ (2013) The comparative delusion: the “behavioristic”/“mentalistic” dichotomy in comparative theory of mind research. In: Terrace HA, Metcalfe J (eds) Agency and joint attention. Oxford University Press, Oxford, pp 62–81

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Penn DC, Holyoak KJ, Povinelli DJ (2008) Darwin’s mistake: explaining the discontinuity between human and nonhuman minds. Behav Brain Sci 31(2):109–130; discussion 130–178. doi:10.1017/S0140525X08003543

  • Povinelli DJ (1998) Can animals empathize? Maybe not. Sci Am 9:67–75

    Google Scholar 

  • Povinelli DJ, Vonk J (2003) Chimpanzee minds: suspiciously human? Trends Cognit Sci 7(4):157–160

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Povinelli DJ, Vonk J (2004) We don’t need a microscope to explore the chimpanzee’s mind. Mind Lang 19(1):1–28

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Preston SD, de Waal FBM (2002) Empathy: its ultimate and proximate bases. Behav Brain Sci 25(1):1–20; discussion 20–71

  • Prinz J (2011) Is empathy necessary for morality? In: Coplan A, Goldie P (eds) Empathy: philosophical and psychological perspectives. Oxford University Press, Oxford, pp 211–229

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Regan T (2004) The case for animal rights. University of California Press, Berkeley

    Google Scholar 

  • Rizzolatti G, Craighero L (2004) The mirror-neuron system. Annu Rev Neurosci 27:169–192. doi:10.1146/annurev.neuro.27.070203.144230

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rowlands M (2002) Animals like us, 1st edn. Verso, London

  • Rowlands M (2009) Animal rights: moral theory and practice, 2nd edn. Palgrave Macmillan, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Rowlands M (2012) Can animals be moral?. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Stich SP (1979) Do animals have beliefs? Australas J Philos 57:15–28

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tschudin A (2006) Dumb animals, deaf humans? In: Hurley S, Nudds M (eds) Rational animals?. Oxford University Press, Oxford, pp 413–438

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Wechkin S, Masserman J, Terris W (1964) Shock to a conspecific as an aversive stimulus. Psychon Sci 1:17–18

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wispé L (1986) The distinction between sympathy and empathy: to call forth a concept, a word is needed. J Pers Soc Psychol 50(2):314–321. doi:10.1037/0022-3514.50.2.314

  • Zahavi D, Overgaard S (2012) Empathy without isomorphism: a phenomenological account. In: Decety J (ed) Empathy: from bench to bedside. MIT Press, Cambridge, pp 3–20

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

This work was supported by the Spanish Ministry of Economy and Competitiveness, under Grants BES-2012-052504 and FFI2011-23267. I would also like to thank Kristin Andrews, Álex Díaz, José A. Gascón, Javier González de Prado, Mark Rowlands, Cristian Saborido, Kim Sterelny, and two anonymous reviewers for their comments and suggestions. Additionally, this material benefitted from discussion at the 2013 SEFA and SIFA meetings, as well as the IV PBCS workshop.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Susana Monsó.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Monsó, S. Empathy and morality in behaviour readers. Biol Philos 30, 671–690 (2015). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10539-015-9495-x

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10539-015-9495-x

Keywords

Navigation