Skip to main content
Log in

Voting as a signaling device

  • Research Article
  • Published:
Economic Theory Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

In this paper, citizens vote in order to influence the election outcome and in order to signal their unobserved characteristics to others. The model is one of rational voting and generates the following predictions: (i) The paradox of not voting does not arise, because the benefit of voting does not vanish with population size. (ii) Turnout in elections is positively related to the importance of social interactions. (iii) Voting may exhibit bandwagon effects and small changes in the electoral incentives may generate large changes in turnout due to signaling effects. (iv) Signaling incentives increase the sensitivity of turnout to voting incentives in communities with low opportunity cost of social interaction, while the opposite is true for communities with high cost of social interaction. Therefore, the model predicts less volatile turnout for the latter type of communities.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. For a formal treatment, see Palfrey and Rosenthal (1985).

  2. An alternative interpretation of the second stage is that each citizen has already a network of friends and each one of them decides whether to increase the degree of interaction with her friends or not.

  3. See also the empirical result by Funk (2010) discussed below.

  4. For more complete surveys, see Aldrich (1993), Blais (2000), Dhillon and Peralta (2002), Feddersen (2004).

  5. For other papers which study the relation between social interactions and political participation, see for instance Schlozman et al. (1995) and Schram and Sonnemans (1996).

  6. In Sect. 4.3, we discuss implications of relaxing this assumption.

  7. Since voting for the other party is a weakly dominated strategy, we do not consider this strategy.

  8. For example, Huckfeldt et al. (2002) observe that the social network of an individual consists largely of people with similar political views. Mutz (2002) shows that people whose social networks involve more political disagreement are less likely to vote.

  9. In an earlier version of the paper (see Aytimur et al. 2012) we assumed that individuals derive utility from interacting with all neighbors, irrespectively of their party preference, and we obtained the same results. .

  10. While the formulation in (1) is chosen to capture the main features of a social interaction, it also helps to simplify the algebra that follows substantially. We should note, however, that our results do not depend critically on this specific formulation of the second-stage payoff; see Sect. 4.3.

  11. Using the same \(\alpha _{\tau (i)}\) in both periods means that the preferences for the election outcome and social interactions are perfectly correlated. While this appears to be a strong assumption, relaxing it would make the analysis much more involved, without being likely to yield interesting additional insights. The reason is that, as long as there is enough correlation between both preference parameters, the first-period behavior still has some informative value for the second period, and hence signaling is useful.

  12. This is a standard and natural assumption as long as individuals are ex ante equally likely to prefer either party. See also Goeree and Großer (2007).

  13. The assumption that the matching strategy does not depend on the individual’s own type (high or low) and own voting decision is not a restriction. The proof is available upon request.

  14. The analysis on all possible equilibria of the second-stage game is given in Aytimur et al. (2012). We omit the analysis of all other cases here either because they involve no signaling benefit (agents interact either with all agents or none) or because they are not possible when the first stage is considered (agents interact only with those who did not vote).

  15. Since it is enough for our purposes to know that \(\Pi (p)\) is differentiable and decreasing for all \(p \in (0,1)\), in order to save space, we do not reproduce it here and we refer the interested reader to Börgers (2004).

  16. The computations and more detailed explanations for (iv) and (v) are in the Appendix.

  17. As can be seen in the proof, the conditions mentioned in (i) to (iii) actually need only be satisfied at the cutoff value for the high types corresponding to the equilibrium under consideration. However, to facilitate interpretation, we state these inequalities globally.

  18. Expressing this condition in terms of the voting benefit of a high-type agent is sufficient, since the voting benefit of a low-type agent is proportional.

  19. Details are available from the authors upon request.

  20. For some recent papers on these topics see Iaryczower and Mattozzi (2012) and Morton and Myerson (2012).

References

  • Aldashev, G.: Political information acquisition for social exchange. Q. J. Political Sci. 5, 1–25 (2010)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Aldrich, J.: Rational choice and turnout. Am. J. Political Sci. 37, 246–278 (1993)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Aytimur, R.E., Boukouras, A., Schwager, R.: Voting as a Signaling Device. CESifo Working Paper 3700 (2012)

  • Blais, A.: To Vote or Not to Vote? The Merits and Limits of Rational Choice Theory. University of Pittsburgh Press, Pittsburgh (2000)

    Google Scholar 

  • Börgers, T.: Costly voting. Am. Econ. Rev. 94, 57–66 (2004)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brennan, G., Hamlin, A.: Expressive voting and electoral equilibrium. Public Choice 95, 149–175 (1998)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bufacchi, V.: Voting, rationality and reputation. Political Stud. 49, 714–729 (2001)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Castanheira, M.: Victory margins and the paradox of voting. Eur. J. Political Econ. 19, 817–841 (2003)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Coate, S., Conlin, M.: A group rule-utilitarian approach to voter turnout: theory and evidence. Am. Econ. Rev. 94, 1476–1504 (2004)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Coleman, J.: Foundations of Social Theory. Belknap Press of Harvard University Press, Cambridge (1990)

    Google Scholar 

  • Cox, G.W., Rosenbluth, F.M., Thies, M.F.: Mobilization, social networks, and turnout: evidence from Japan. World Politics 50, 447–474 (1998)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Degan, A.: Civic duty and political advertising. Econ. Theory 52, 531–564 (2013)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dhillon, A., Peralta, S.: Economic theories of voter turnout. Econ. J. 112, F332–F352 (2002)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Downs, A.: An Economic Theory of Democracy. Harper and Row, New York (1957)

    Google Scholar 

  • Edlin, A., Gelman, A., Kaplan, N.: Voting as a rational choice. Ration. Soc. 19, 293–314 (2007)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Engelen, B.: Solving the paradox: the expressive rationality of the decision to vote. Ration. Soc. 18, 419–441 (2006)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Feddersen, T.: Rational choice theory and the paradox of not voting. J. Econ. Perspect. 18, 99–112 (2004)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Feddersen, T., Sandroni, A.: A theory of participation in elections. Am. Econ. Rev. 96, 1271–1282 (2006)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fowler, J.: Turnout in a small world. In: Zuckerman, A. (ed.) The Social Logic of Politics: Personal Networks as Contexts for Political Behavior, pp. 269–287. Temple University Press, Philadelphia (2005)

    Google Scholar 

  • Fowler, J.: Altruism and turnout. J. Politics 68, 674–683 (2006)

    Google Scholar 

  • Funk, P.: Theory and Evidence on the Role of Social Norms in Voting. Working paper, Stockholm School of Economics (2005)

  • Funk, P.: Social incentives and voter turnout: evidence from the Swiss mail ballot system. J. Eur. Econ. Assoc. 8, 1077–1103 (2010)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gerber, A., Rogers, T.: Descriptive social norms and motivation to vote: everybody’s voting and so should you. J. Politics 71, 178–191 (2009)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gerber, A., Green, D., Larimer, C.: Social pressure and voter turnout: evidence from a large-scale field experiment. Am. Political Sci. Rev. 102, 33–48 (2008)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Goeree, J.K., Großer, J.: Welfare reducing polls. Econ. Theory 31, 51–68 (2007)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Großer, J., Schram, A.: Neighborhood information exchange and voter participation: an experimental study. Am. Political Sci. Rev. 100, 235–248 (2006)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Harsanyi, J.: Rule utilitarianism, rights, obligations and the theory of rational behavior. Theory Decis. 12, 115–133 (1980)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Herrera, H., Martinelli, C.: Group formation and voter participation. Theor. Econ. 1, 461–487 (2006)

    Google Scholar 

  • Huckfeldt, R., Johnson, P.E., Sprague, J.: Political environments, political dynamics, and the survival of disagreement. J. Politics 64, 1–21 (2002)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Iaryczower, M., Mattozzi, A.: The pro-competitive effect of campaign limits in non-majoritarian elections. Econ. Theory 49, 591–619 (2012)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kamenica, E., Egan Brad, L.: Voters, dictators, and peons: expressive voting and pivotality. Public Choice (Online), 1–18 (2012)

  • Kenny, C.B.: Political participation and effects from the social environment. Am. J. Political Sci. 36, 259–267 (1992)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Knack, S.: Civic norms, social sanctions, and voter turnout. Ration. Soc. 4, 133–156 (1992)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lake, R.L.D., Huckfeldt, R.: Social capital, social networks, and political participation. Political Psychol. 19, 567–584 (1998)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ledyard, J.: The pure theory of large two-candidate elections. Public Choice 44, 7–41 (1984)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Leighley, J.: Group membership and the mobilization of political participation. J. Politics 58, 447–463 (1996)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McClurg, S.D.: Social networks and political participation: the role of social interaction in explaining political participation. Political Res. Q. 56, 449–464 (2003)

    Google Scholar 

  • Monroe, A.D.: Urbanism and voter turnout: a note on some unexpected findings. Am. J. Political Sci. 21, 71–78 (1977)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Morton, R.B.: Groups in rational turnout models. Am. J. Political Sci. 35, 758–776 (1991)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Morton, R.B., Myerson, R.B.: Decisiveness of contributors’ perceptions in elections. Econ. Theory 49, 571–590 (2012)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mutz, D.C.: The consequences of cross-cutting networks for political participation. Am. J. Political Sci. 46, 838–855 (2002)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Oliver, J.E.: City size and civic involvement in metropolitan America. Am. Political Sci. Rev. 94, 361–373 (2000)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Overbye, E.: Making a case for the rational, self-regarding, ‘ethical’ voter.. and solving the ‘paradox of not voting’ in the process. Eur. J. Political Res. 27, 369–396 (1995)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Palfrey, T., Rosenthal, H.: Voter participation and strategic uncertainty. Am. Political Sci. Rev. 79, 62–78 (1985)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Posner, E.: Symbols, signals, and social norms in politics and the law. J. Leg. Stud. 27, 765–797 (1998)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Remmer, K.L.: Political scale and electoral turnout: evidence from the less industrialized world. Comp. Political Stud. 43, 275–303 (2010)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rotemberg, J.: Attitude-dependent altruism, turnout and voting. Public Choice 140, 223–244 (2009)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schlozman, K., Verba, S., Brady, H.: Participation’s not a paradox: the view from American activists. Br. J. Political Sci. 25, 1–36 (1995)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schram, A., Sonnemans, J.: Why people vote: experimental evidence. J. Econ. Psychol. 17, 417–442 (1996)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shachar, R., Nalebuff, B.: Follow the leader: theory and evidence on political participation. Am. Econ. Rev. 89, 525–547 (1999)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Taylor, C., Yildirim, H.: A unified analysis of rational voting with private values and group-specific costs. Games Econ. Behav. 70, 457–471 (2010)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Uhlaner, C.: Rational turnout: the neglected role of groups. Am. J. Political Sci. 33, 390–422 (1989)

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Aristotelis Boukouras.

Additional information

We thank the editor, Nicholas Yannelis, and two anonymous referees for their very helpful comments. We also thank David Stadelmann and Beat Hintermann for their useful comments and remarks. Seminar participants at the Universities of Marburg, Göttingen, Trondheim, TOBB University of Economics and Technology in Ankara, and at the 2012 annual meetings of Verein für Socialpolitik, Göttingen, and International Institute of Public Finance, Dresden, engaged in helpful discussions, for which we are grateful. Aristotelis Boukouras would also like to thank the Courant Research Centre of the Georg-August University Göttingen, where he was a postdoctoral researcher when this project started.

Appendix

Appendix

1.1 First-stage equilibrium

Proof of Proposition 1

(i) When we plot \(\mathcal B _H (c_H)\) on \(c_{\min }/\mu < c_H < c_{\max }\), the intersection \(c_H^*\) with the \(45^{\circ }\) line would be an interior equilibrium satisfying (6). By the continuity of \(\mathcal B _H (c_H)\) on the interval \([c_{\min }/\mu , c_{\max }]\), if \(\mathcal B _H (c_{\min }/\mu )>c_{\min }/\mu \) (i.e., the starting point is above the \(45^{\circ }\) line) and \(\mathcal B _H(c_{\max })<c_{\max }\) (i.e., the ending point is below the \(45^{\circ }\) line), then at least one such intersection exists. Moreover, since at least one intersection is such that \(\mathcal B _H(c_H)\) cuts the \(45^{\circ }\) line from above, a stable interior equilibrium exists if these two conditions are satisfied. In an interior equilibrium with signaling, the second period benefit is \(\frac{1}{2} w_2 p(n-1)[\lambda _H \alpha _H+(1-\lambda _H)\alpha _L-d]\). With the cutoff points \(c_H=c_{\min }/\mu \) and \(c_L=c_{\min }\), \(p=qF(c_{\min }/\mu )\) and \(\lambda _H=1\). With the cutoff points \(c_H=c_{\max }\) and \(c_L=\mu c_{\max }, \) \(p=q+(1-q)F(\mu c_{\max })\) and \(\lambda _H=\frac{q}{q+(1-q)F(\mu c_{\max })}\). Replacing \(p\) and \(\lambda _H\) in (5) and rearranging, one finds that \(\mathcal B _H (c_{\min }/\mu )>c_{\min }/\mu \) and \(\mathcal B _H(c_{\max })<c_{\max }\) are equivalent to inequalities (7) and (8).

In addition, we have to make sure that this intersection \(c_H^*\) gives an equilibrium with signaling. This is the case if the two conditions \( \lambda _H \alpha _H + (1-\lambda _H) \alpha _L \ge d \) and \( (1-\lambda _L) \alpha _H + \lambda _L \alpha _L \le d \) hold for all \(c_H \in [c_{\min }/\mu , c_{\max }]\) (i.e., for all possible intersection points). These two conditions are equivalent to (9) holding for all \(c_H \in [c_{\min }/\mu , c_{\max }]\).

(ii) The lhs of inequality (7) is always positive. Hence, this inequality is satisfied for low enough \(c_{\min }\). The lhs of inequality (8) is bounded above by \(\alpha _H \big \{\frac{w_1}{2} + \frac{1}{2} w_2 (n-1)q(\alpha _H -d) \big \}\). Hence, this inequality is satisfied for high enough \(c_{\max }\).

The lhs of inequality (9) is lower than \((1-q)/q\) since \(F(\mu c_H)<F(c_H)\) for all \(c_H \in [c_{\min }/\mu , c_{\max }]\). Similarly, the rhs of inequality (9) is greater than \((1-q)/q\) since \(1-F(\mu c_H)>1-F(c_H)\) for all \(c_H \in [c_{\min }/\mu , c_{\max }]\). Then, for instance, if \(d\) is such that \(\frac{\alpha _H-d}{d-\alpha _L}=\frac{1-q}{q}\) (equivalently \(q\alpha _H+(1-q)\alpha _L=d\)), both conditions are satisfied. Hence, there is a neighborhood of values of \(d\) around \(q\alpha _H+(1-q)\alpha _L\) in which both conditions are satisfied. Note that this neighborhood for \(d\) is consistent with the fact that inequalities (7) and (8) hold for some parameter values, since the latter inequalities are satisfied by appropriate choice of \(c_{\min }\) and \(c_{\max }\), irrespective of \(d\). \(\square \)

1.2 Comparative statics

In this subsection of the Appendix, for the ease of exposition, we write \(c_H\) and \(c_L\) to denote the equilibrium cutoffs instead of \(c_H^*\) and \(c_L^*\).

Claim (iv): \(\frac{\mathrm{d}p^*}{\mathrm{d}q}>0\).

Proof

\(\mathrm{d} p^*/\mathrm{d} q\) is given by

$$\begin{aligned} \frac{\mathrm{d}p^*}{\mathrm{d}q}=F(c_H)-F(\mu c_H)+\frac{\mathrm{d} c_H}{\mathrm{d} q} \left[ qf(c_H)+(1-q)\mu f(\mu c_H) \right] \end{aligned}$$

We can compute \(\mathrm{d} c_H/\mathrm{d} q\) by using equations (11) and (12) where \(\partial \mathcal B _H / {\partial q}\) is given by

$$\begin{aligned} \frac{\partial \mathcal B _H}{\partial q}&= \alpha _H \Big \{\frac{w_1}{2}\Pi ^{\prime }(p)[F(c_H)-F(\mu c_H)]\\&\quad + \frac{w_2}{2}(n-1)\big [F(c_H)(\alpha _H-d) - F(\mu c_H)(\alpha _L-d)\big ]\Big \} \end{aligned}$$

Notice that the first term in \(\partial \mathcal B _H / {\partial q}\) is negative, while the second term is positive. If, for example, \(w_2 (w_1\)) is sufficiently large, one obtains \(\mathrm{d} c_H/\mathrm{d} q>0 (<0)\).

However, we now show that total turnout always increases. Replacing the value of \(\mathrm{d} c_H/\mathrm{d} q\) in the above expression for \(\mathrm{d} p^*/\mathrm{d} q\), we find that \(\mathrm{d} p^*/\mathrm{d} q\) has the same sign as

$$\begin{aligned}&\bigg [F(c_H)-F(\mu c_H) \bigg ] \bigg [1-\alpha _H \Big \{ \frac{w_1}{2} \Pi ^{\prime }(p) \big [ qf(c_H)+(1-q)\mu f(\mu c_H) \big ]\\&\qquad + \frac{w_2}{2} (n-1) \big [ qf(c_H)(\alpha _H-d)+(1-q)\mu f(\mu c_H) (\alpha _L-d) \big ] \Big \} \bigg ] \\&\qquad + \bigg [qf(c_H)+(1-q)\mu f(\mu c_H)\bigg ] \bigg [\alpha _H \Big \{\frac{w_1}{2} \Pi ^{\prime }(p) \big [F(c_H)-F(\mu c_H) \big ]\\&\qquad + \frac{w_2}{2} (n-1) \big [F(c_H)(\alpha _H-d)-F(\mu c_H)(\alpha _L-d) \big ] \Big \} \bigg ] \end{aligned}$$

By lengthy but simple algebraic manipulations, it can be shown that the above expression and hence \(\mathrm{d} p^*/\mathrm{d} q\) are always positive. \(\square \)

Claim (v): \(\frac{\mathrm{d}p^*}{\mathrm{d}\alpha _H}>0\) but \(\frac{\mathrm{d}p^*}{\mathrm{d}\alpha _L}\) cannot be signed.

Proof

\(\frac{\partial \mathcal B _H}{\partial \alpha _H}\) is given by

$$\begin{aligned} \frac{\partial \mathcal B _H}{\partial \alpha _H}&= \Big \{\frac{w_1}{2}\Pi (p) + \frac{w_2}{2}(n-1)[qF(c_H)(\alpha _H-d)+(1-q)F(\mu c_H)(\alpha _L-d)]\Big \} \\&\quad +\alpha _H \Big \{\frac{w_1}{2}\Pi ^{\prime } (p) (1-q)f(\mu c_H)\Big (-\frac{\alpha _L c_H}{\alpha _H^2}\Big )\\&\quad + \frac{w_2}{2}(n-1)\Big [qF(c_H)+(1-q)f(\mu c_H)(\alpha _L-d)\Big (-\frac{\alpha _L c_H}{\alpha _H^2}\Big ) \Big ]\Big \} \end{aligned}$$

The term in the first bracket is the impact through the individual’s own preference parameter, and the term \(\frac{w_2}{2}(n-1)qF(c_H)\) is the impact of the partners’ parameter on the signaling benefit. The terms involving \( -\frac{\alpha _L c_H}{\alpha _H^2} \) are the effects of a decrease in the cutoff \(c_L\) on the electoral and signaling benefits, which occurs so as to maintain the relationship \(c_L=\mu c_H\) which must always hold in an equilibrium. Since all terms are positive, one has \(\mathrm{d}c_H/\mathrm{d}\alpha _H>0\).

Similar to \(\mathcal B _H(c_H)\), we define \(\mathcal B _L(c_L)\) as

$$\begin{aligned} \mathcal B _L (c_L)&\equiv B_L(c_L/\mu ,c_L) \nonumber \\&= \alpha _L\Big \{\frac{w_1}{2}\Pi (p) + \frac{w_2}{2}(n-1)\big [qF(c_L/\mu )(\alpha _H-d)+(1-q)F(c_L)(\alpha _L-d)\big ]\Big \} \end{aligned}$$
(16)

The second term in this benefit is the signaling benefit which increases after an increase in \(\alpha _H\). The electoral benefit in the first term decreases if and only if \(\Pi (p)\) increases. Thus, \(\mathrm{d} c_L/\mathrm{d} \alpha _H\) may be negative. However, if total turnouts \(p\) were to decrease, then \(\Pi (p)\), and hence all terms in (16), would increase, which together with \(\mathrm{d}c_H/\mathrm{d}\alpha _H>0\) yields a contradiction.

From (16), we obtain

$$\begin{aligned} \frac{\partial \mathcal B _L}{\partial \alpha _L}&= \Big \{\frac{w_1}{2}\Pi (p) + \frac{w_2}{2}(n-1)[qF(c_L/\mu )(\alpha _H-d)+(1-q)F(c_L)(\alpha _L-d)]\Big \}\nonumber \\&\quad + \alpha _L \Big \{\frac{w_1}{2}\Pi ^{\prime }(p) q f(c_L/\mu )\Big (\frac{-c_L \alpha _H}{\alpha _L^2}\Big ) \nonumber \\&+ \frac{w_2}{2}(n-1)\Big [(1-q)F(c_L)+q f(c_L/\mu )(\alpha _H-d)\Big (\frac{-c_L \alpha _H}{\alpha _L^2}\Big )\Big ]\Big \} \end{aligned}$$
(17)

The last term in (17) expresses the impact of an increase in \(\alpha _L\) via the associated change in the share of high-type agents among the interaction partners and is negative. If the weight \(w_2\) on signaling is large and if the density of cost \(f(c_L/\mu )\) happens to be large at the original equilibrium, then (17) may turn negative, so that \(\mathrm{d}c_L/\mathrm{d} \alpha _L\) need not be positive. \(\square \)

Proof of Proposition 3 First, we derive the thresholds \(d_H\) and \(d_L\) from the two conditions given at the end of Sect. 3.1 as a function of the cutoff value \(c_H\) for the high types in the equilibrium under consideration. To do this, we substitute the relevant values for \(\lambda _H\) and \(\lambda _L\) into \(\lambda _H \alpha _H + (1-\lambda _H)\alpha _L \ge d\) and \((1-\lambda _L)\alpha _H + \lambda _L\alpha _L \le d\):

$$\begin{aligned}&d_H \!=\! \lambda _H\alpha _H\!+\!(1-\lambda _H)\alpha _L\\&\quad \Rightarrow \, d_H \!=\! \frac{qF(c_H)}{qF(c_H)\!+\!(1\!-\!q)F(\mu c_H)}\alpha _H\!+\!\left( 1\!-\!\frac{qF(c_H)}{qF(c_H)\!+\!(1\!-\!q)F(\mu c_H)}\right) \alpha _L \\&\quad \Rightarrow \, d_H \!=\! \frac{\alpha _HqF(c_H)\!+\!\alpha _L(1-q) F(\mu c_H)}{qF(c_H)\!+\!(1-q)F(\mu c_H)}\quad \quad \end{aligned}$$

Similarly:

$$\begin{aligned} d_L=(1-\lambda _L)\alpha _H+\lambda _L\alpha _L \, \Rightarrow \, d_L=\frac{\alpha _Hq(1-F(c_H))+\alpha _L(1-q)(1-F(\mu c_H))}{q(1-F(c_H))+(1-q)(1-F(\mu c_H))} \end{aligned}$$

For part (i), suppose that \( f(c_H)/F(c_H) \ge \mu f(\mu c_H)/F(\mu c_H) \). One has

$$\begin{aligned}&\frac{f(c_H)}{F(c_H)} > (=) \frac{\mu f(\mu c_H)}{F(\mu c_H)} \, \Leftrightarrow \, (\alpha _H-\alpha _L)f(c_H)F(\mu c_H) > (=) (\alpha _H-\alpha _L)\mu f(\mu c_H)F(c_H) \\&\quad \Leftrightarrow \, \alpha _Hf(c_H)F(\mu c_H)\!+\!\alpha _L\mu f(\mu c_H)F(c_H) \!>\! (=) \alpha _H\mu f(\mu c_H)F(c_H) \!+\!\alpha _L f(c_H)F(\mu c_H)\quad \quad \end{aligned}$$

Multiplying both sides by \(q(1-q)\) and adding  \(\alpha _Hq^2f(c_H)F(c_H)\)  and  \(\alpha _L(1-q)^2\mu f(\mu c_H)F(\mu c_H)\)  on both sides yields:

$$\begin{aligned}&\alpha _Hq^2f(c_H)F(c_H)+ \alpha _Hq(1-q)f(c_H)F(\mu c_H) \\&\qquad +\alpha _Lq(1-q)\mu f(\mu c_H)F(c_H) +\alpha _L(1-q)^2\mu f(\mu c_H)F(\mu c_H)\\&\quad > (=)\alpha _Hq^2f(c_H)F(c_H)+\alpha _Hq(1-q)\mu f(\mu c_H)F(c_H)\\&\qquad +\alpha _Lq(1-q) f(c_H)F(\mu c_H)+\alpha _L(1-q)^2\mu f(\mu c_H)F(\mu c_H)\\&\quad \Leftrightarrow \big [\alpha _Hqf(c_H)+\alpha _L(1-q)\mu f(\mu c_H)\big ]\big [qF(c_H)+(1-q)F(\mu c_H)\big ]\\&\quad > (=) \big [\alpha _HqF(c_H)+\alpha _L(1-q) F(\mu c_H)\big ]\big [qf(c_H)+(1-q)\mu f(\mu c_H)\big ] \\&\quad \Leftrightarrow \frac{\alpha _Hqf(c_H)+\alpha _L(1-q)\mu f(\mu c_H)}{qf(c_H)+(1-q)\mu f(\mu c_H)}~> (=)~ \frac{\alpha _HqF(c_H)+\alpha _L(1-q) F(\mu c_H)}{qF(c_H)+(1-q)F(\mu c_H)} \\&\quad \Leftrightarrow \tilde{\alpha } ~> (=) d_H \end{aligned}$$

From the lines above, we conclude more specifically that

$$\begin{aligned} \frac{f(c_H)}{F(c_H)} ~~> (=)~~ \frac{\mu f(\mu c_H)}{F(\mu c_H)} \, \Leftrightarrow \,\tilde{\alpha } ~>(=)~ d_H \end{aligned}$$

When \(\tilde{\alpha }\) is greater than (resp. equal to) \(d_H\), this implies that any value of \(d\) that satisfies the equilibrium conditions also satisfies \(d < \tilde{\alpha }\) (resp. \(d \le \tilde{\alpha }\)). Hence \(\frac{d^2c_H^*}{\mathrm{d}w_1 \mathrm{d}w_2} > 0\) (resp. \(\ge 0\)).

For part (ii), note first that the above argument implies \(\tilde{\alpha } < d_H\). Furthermore, substitute in the proof above the terms \(1-F(c_H)\) and \(1-F(\mu c_H)\) for the terms \(F(c_H)\) and \(F(\mu c_H)\), respectively, and iterate the same steps. Then, we obtain:

$$\begin{aligned}&\frac{f(c_H)}{1-F(c_H)} >(=) \frac{\mu f(\mu c_H)}{1-F(\mu c_H)}\\&\quad \Leftrightarrow \, \frac{\alpha _Hqf(c_H)+\alpha _L(1-q)\mu f(\mu c_H)}{qf(c_H)+(1-q)\mu f(\mu c_H)} >(=) \frac{\alpha _Hq(1-F(c_H))+\alpha _L(1-q)(1- F(\mu c_H))}{q(1-F(c_H))+(1-q)(1-F(\mu c_H))} \\&\quad \Leftrightarrow \, \tilde{\alpha } > (=)d_L\quad \end{aligned}$$

When \(\tilde{\alpha }\) is greater than \(d_L\), the cost of the match \(d\) may satisfy \(d < \tilde{\alpha }\) or not. This depends on the other parameters of the model. Hence, either  \(\frac{d^2c_H^*}{\mathrm{d}w_1 \mathrm{d}w_2} \!\ge \! 0\)  or  \(\frac{d^2c_H^*}{\mathrm{d}w_1 \mathrm{d}w_2} \!<\! 0\). When \(\tilde{\alpha }\) is equal to \(d_L, d \ge \tilde{\alpha }\). Hence, \(\frac{d^2c_H^*}{\mathrm{d}w_1 \mathrm{d}w_2} \le 0\).

Finally, part (iii) follows from part (ii). This is because when the initial condition of part (ii) does not hold, then \(\tilde{\alpha } < d_L\), which implies that the condition \(d \le \tilde{\alpha }\) is mutually exclusive with the equilibrium conditions.\(\square \)

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Aytimur, R.E., Boukouras, A. & Schwager, R. Voting as a signaling device. Econ Theory 55, 753–777 (2014). https://doi.org/10.1007/s00199-013-0764-0

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s00199-013-0764-0

Keywords

JEL Classification

Navigation