Skip to main content

Advertisement

Log in

Embodying the Mind by Extending It

  • Published:
Review of Philosophy and Psychology Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

To subscribe to the embodied mind (or embodiment) framework is to reject the view that an individual’s mind is realized by her brain alone. As Clark (2008a) has argued, there are two ways to subscribe to embodiment: bodycentrism (BC) and the extended mind (EM) thesis. According to BC, an embodied mind is a two-place relation between an individual’s brain and her non-neural bodily anatomy. According to EM, an embodied mind is a threeplace relation between an individual’s brain, her non-neural body and her non-bodily environment. I argue that BC can be given a weak and a strong interpretation, according to whether it accepts a functionalist account of the contribution of the non-neural body to higher cognitive functions and a computational account of the contents of concepts and the nature of conceptual processing. Thus, weak BC amounts to an incomplete version of EM. To accept a weak BC approach to concepts is to accept concept-empiricism. I raise four challenges for concept-empiricism and argue that what is widely taken as evidence for concept-empiricism from recent cognitive neuroscience could only vindicate weak BC if it could be shown that the non-neural body, far from being a tool at the service of the mind/brain, could be constitutive of the mind. If correct, EM would seem able to vindicate the claim that both bodily and non-bodily tools are constitutive of an individual’s mind. I scrutinize the basic arguments for EM and argue that they fail. This failure backfires on weak BC. One option left for advocates of BC is to endorse a strong, more controversial, BC approach to concepts.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. For an extensive discussion of the distinction between the causal and the constitutive dependency of human perceptual experience upon bodily anatomy and action, cf. Block (2005) and Aizawa (2007).

  2. Dempsey and Shani (2012) calls it “strong embodiment”.

  3. In fact, one of the motivations for endorsing the view that the non-neural body makes a special contribution to the mind is to cast doubt on the extent to which the mind is really multiply realizable.

  4. Arguably, advocates of either the extended mind thesis or weak body-centrism should be inclined to call such representations mental (cf. Adams and Aizawa 2008 for a critique).

  5. I follow the standard philosophical practice of referring to concepts by using words in capital letters.

  6. The further question arises whether advocates of body-centrism should concede that bodily parts, which are not artifacts with intended functions, count as tools on a par with artifacts with intended functions. I consider this further question at the end of section 4.

  7. See section 4.2 for further discussion.

  8. Perception can be illusory, but if so, then the illusion is not actively caused by a deceiver. As Sperber (2001) and Sperber et al. (2010) have emphasized, humans have developed particular tools for assessing the reliability and trustworthiness of the sources of communicated information because they are vulnerable to deception via communication. I am aware that some philosophers in the Reidian tradition have argued for a close similarity between perceptually formed beliefs and communication-based beliefs (e.g. Millikan 1984 and Burge 1993), but I am not convinced.

  9. As I argue in section 4.2, the arguments for the extended mind thesis interestingly differ from Twin-Earth arguments for content-externalism. Notice also that the application of the extended mind thesis to human social cognition interestingly differs from the kind of social externalism advocated by Burge (1979), according to which what members of an individual’s community think may be constitutive of the contents of some of the individual’s thoughts. Burge’s social externalism has no externalist implications for the self.

References

  • Adams, F., and K. Aizawa. 2008. The bounds of cognition. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Aizawa, K. 2007. Understanding the embodiment of perception. The Journal of Philosophy 54(1): 5–25.

    Google Scholar 

  • Aziz-Zadeh, L., S.M. Wilson, G. Rizzolatti, and M. Iacoboni. 2006. Congruent embodied representations for visually presented actions and linguistic phrases describing actions. Current Biology 16: 1–6.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Barsalou, L.W. 1999. Perceptual symbol systems. Behavioral and Brain Sciences 22: 577–660.

    Google Scholar 

  • Barsalou, L.W., W.K. Simmons, A.K. Barbey, and C.D. Wilson. 2003. Grounding conceptual knowledge in modality-specific systems. Trends in Cognitive Sciences 7(2): 84–91.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bedny, M., and A. Caramazza. 2011. Perception, action, and word meanings in the human brain: the case from action verbs. Annals of the New York Academy of Sciences 1224: 81–95.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Block, N. 2005. Review of A. Noë Action in Perception. The Journal of Philosophy 52(5): 259–72.

    Google Scholar 

  • Boulenger, V., A.C. Roy, Y. Paulignan, V. Deprez, M. Jeannerod, and T.A. Nazir. 2006. Cross-talk between language processes and overt motor behavior in the first 200 ms of processing. Journal of Cognitive Neuroscience 18: 1607–1615.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Boulenger, V., L. Mechtouff, S. Thobois, E. Broussolle, M. Jeannerod, and T. Nazir. 2008a. Word processing in Parkinson’s disease is impaired for action verbs but not for concrete nouns. Neuropsychologia 46(2): 743–756.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Boulenger, V., B.Y. Silber, A.C. Roy, Y. Paulignan, M. Jeannerod, and T. Nazir. 2008b. Subliminal display of action words interferes with motor planning: a combined EEG and kinematic study. Journal of Physiology 102: 130–136.

    Google Scholar 

  • Buccino, G., L. Riggio, G. Melli, F. Binkofski, V. Gallese, and G. Rizzolatti. 2005. Listening to action-related sentences modulates the activity of the motor system: a combined TMS and behavioral study. Cognitive Brain Research 24: 355–363.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Burge, T. 1979. Individualism and the mental. Midwest Studies in Philosophy 4: 73–121.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Burge, T. 1993. Content preservation. Philosophical Review 102: 457–488.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cardinali, L., F. Frassinetti, C. Brozzoli, C. Urquizar, A.C. Roy, and A. Farnè. 2009. Tool-use induces morphological updating of the body schema. Current Biology 19(12): R478.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chalmers, D. 2008. Foreword to A. Clark, Supersizing the mind, embodiment, action, and cognitive extension. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Clark, A. 1997. Being there: Putting brain, body and world together again. Cambridge: MIT.

    Google Scholar 

  • Clark, A. 2002. Minds, brains and tools. In Philosophy of mental representations, ed. H. Clapin, 66–90. Oxford: Clarendon.

    Google Scholar 

  • Clark, A. 2008a. Pressing the flesh: A tension in the study of the embodied, embedded mind? Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 76(1): 37–59.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Clark, A. 2008b. Supersizing the mind, embodiment, action, and cognitive extension. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Clark, A. 2009. Where is my mind? London Review of Book 31, 6, 26 March 2009.

    Google Scholar 

  • Clark, A., and D. Chalmers. 1998. The extended mind. Analysis 58(1): 7–19.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Crane, T. 1992. The nonconceptual content of experience. In The contents of experience, essays on perception, ed. T. Crane. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Dehaene, S., and L. Cohen. 2011. The unique role of the visual word form area in reading. Trends in Cognitive Sciences 5(6): 254–262.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dempsey, L., and I. Shani. 2012. Stressing the flesh: in defense of strong embodied cognition. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research.

  • Dennett, D.C. 1996. Kinds of minds. New York: Basic Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fodor, J.A. 1974. Special sciences. Synthese 28: 97–115.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fodor, J.A. 1975. The language of thought. New York: Crowell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fodor, J.A. 1983. The modularity of mind. Cambridge: MIT.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fodor, J.A. 1994. The elm and the expert. Cambridge: MIT.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fodor, J.A. 1998. Concepts, where cognitive science went wrong. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fodor, J.A. 2007. The revenge of the given. In Contemporary debates in philosophy of mind, ed. B.P. McLaughlin and J.D. Cohen. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fodor, J.A. 2009. Where is my mind? London Review of Books 31, 3, 12 February 2009.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gallagher, S. 2005. How the body shapes the mind. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Gallese, V., and G. Lakoff. 2005. The brain’s concepts: the role of the sensory-motor system in conceptual knowledge. Cognitive Neuropsychology 22: 455–479.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gallese, V., and C. Sinigaglia. 2011. What is so special about embodied simulation? Trends in Cognitive Sciences 11: 512–519.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Glenberg, A.M., and M.P. Kaschak. 2002. Grounding language in action. Psychonomic Bulletin & Review 9(3): 558–565.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Goldman, A., and F. de Vignemont. 2009. Is social cognition embodied? Trends in Cognitive Sciences 13(4): 154–159.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Haugeland, J. 1998. Mind embodied and embedded. In Having thought: Essays in the metaphysics of mind, ed. J. Haugeland, 207–240. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hauk, O., I. Johnsrude, and F. Pulvermüller. 2004. Somatotopic representation of action words in human motor and premotor cortex. Neuron 41: 301–307.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jacob, P. 2002. Review of Rowlands, M. The body in mind. Mind and Language 17(3): 325–331.

    Google Scholar 

  • Machery, E. 2006. Two dogmas of neo-empiricism. Philosophy Compass 1(4): 398–412.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Machery, E. 2007. Concept empiricism: A methodological critique. Cognition 104: 19–46.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mahon, B.Z., and A. Caramazza. 2008. A critical look at the embodied cognition hypothesis and a new proposal for grounding conceptual content. Journal of Physiology 102: 59–70.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mahon, B.Z., and A. Caramazza. 2009. A concepts and categories: A cognitive neuropsychological perspective. Annual Review of Psychology 60: 27–51.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Maravita, A., and A. Iriki. 2004. Tools for the body (schema). Trends in Cognitive Sciences 8(2): 79–86.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Margolis, E., S. Laurence. 2006. Concepts. Stanford Encylopedia of Philosophy, plato.stanford.edu/entries/concepts/

  • McCandliss, B.D., L. Cohen, and S. Dehaene. 2003. The visual word form area: Expertise for reading in the fusiform gyrus. Trends in Cognitive Sciences 7(7): 293–299.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McDowell, J. 1994. Mind and world. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Millikan, R. 1984. Language, thought, and other biological categories. Cambridge: MIT.

    Google Scholar 

  • Noë, A. 2004. Action in perception. Cambridge: MIT.

    Google Scholar 

  • Prinz, J. 2005. The return of concept empiricism. In Categorization and cognitive science, eds. H. Cohen, C. Leferbvre. Elsevier.

  • Pulvermüller, F. 2005. Brain mechanisms linking language and action. Nature Review Neuroscience 6: 576–582.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pulvermüller, F., O. Hauk, V.V. Nikulin, and R.J. Ilmoniemi. 2005. Functional interaction of language and action: a TMS study. European Journal of Neuroscience 21: 793–797.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Putnam, H. 1967. The nature of mental states. In Mind, language and reality, philosophical papers, vol. 2, ed. Putnam, H. (1975). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

  • Putnam, H. 1975. The meaning of ‘meaning’. In Mind, language and reality, philosophical papers, vol. 2, ed. H. Putnam. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Rizzolatti, G., and L. Craighero. 2004. The mirror neuron system. Annual Review of Neuroscience 27: 169–92.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rowlands, M. 1999. The body in mind. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Rowlands, M. 2010. The new science of the mind. Cambridge: MIT.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sato, M., L. Cattaneo, G. Rizzolatti, and V. Gallese. 2007. Numbers within our hands: modulation of corticospinal excitability of hand muscles during numerical judgment. Journal of Cognitive Neuroscience 19(4): 684–693.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shapiro, L. 2004. The mind incarnate. Cambridge: MIT.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shapiro, L. 2007. The embodied cognition research programme. Philosophy Compass 2(2): 338–346.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sperber, D. 2001. An evolutionary perspective on testimony and argumentation. Philosophical Topics 29: 401–413.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sperber, D., F. Clément, C. Heintz, O. Mascaro, H. Mercier, G. Origgi, and D. Wilson. 2010. Epistemic vigilance. Mind and Language 25(4): 359–393.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tettamanti, M., G. Buccino, M.C. Saccuman, G. Gallese, M. Danna, P. Scifo, F. Fazio, G. Rizzolatti, S.F. Cappa, and D. Perani. 2005. Listening to action-related sentences activates fronto-parietal motor circuits. Journal of Cognitive Neuroscience 17(2): 273–281.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Willems, R.M., P. Hagoort, and D. Casasanto. 2009. Body-specific representations of action verbs: neural evidence from right- and left-handers. Psychological Science 21(1): 67–74.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wilson, M. 2002. Six views of embodied cognition. Psychonomic Bulletin & Review 9(4): 625–636.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wilson, R., L. Foglia. 2011. Embodied cognition. Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/embodied-cognition/

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Pierre Jacob.

Additional information

Earlier versions of this paper were presented as comments on Ian Hacking’s third Descartes Lecture, at the University of Tilburg, on October 8, 2010; at the Conference on Embodied Mind: Perspectives and Limitations at the Radboud University in Nijmegen, on October 28, 2010; at the Workshop on New Directions in Cognitive Science at the University of Bucharest on June 20, 2011. I am grateful to Stephan Hartmann, Harold Bekkering and Radu Bogdan for inviting me to deliver a paper at these meetings. I am also grateful to Ian Hacking, Martin Kusch, Guenther Knoblich, Nathalie Sebanz, Dan Dennett, Nicholas Humphrey, Dan Sperber, Frédérique de Vignemont for discussions on the topic of this paper. I am grateful to two anonymous referees for this Journal for their useful criticisms and especially to Adrian Alsmith for his acute criticisms and comments. This work was supported by a grant from the French ministry of research (ANR-BLAN SOCODEV). I dedicate this paper to the memory of my friend Marc Jeannerod who died on July 1, 2011.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Jacob, P. Embodying the Mind by Extending It. Rev.Phil.Psych. 3, 33–51 (2012). https://doi.org/10.1007/s13164-012-0087-2

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s13164-012-0087-2

Keywords

Navigation