Skip to main content
Log in

Silencing Desires?

  • Published:
Philosophia Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

In an overlooked section of his influential book What We Owe to Each Other Thomas Scanlon advances an argument against the desire-model of practical reasoning. In Scanlon’s view the model gives a distorted picture of the structure of our practical thinking. His idea is that there is an alternative to the “weighing behavior” of reasons, a particular way in which reasons can relate to each other. This phenomenon, which the paper calls “silencing”, is not something that the desire-model can accommodate, or so Scanlon argues. The paper first presents and interprets Scanlon’s challenge. After this, the paper argues, through the examination of three responses, that Scanlon is right in claiming that the model cannot accommodate the phenomenon as he describes it. However, the paper further argues that there is no need to accept Scanlon’s depiction of silencing: advocates of the model can give an alternative account of what happens in cases of silencing that is just as plausible as Scanlon’s own. Scanlon’s challenge is thus, the paper concludes, illegitimate. (169)

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. To my knowledge the only discussion is in Arkonovich (2001), section 4.

  2. Scanlon has other arguments against the desire-model, but these have received detailed discussion. See Arkonovich (2001), Shemmer (2007), Schroeder (2007), Copp and Sobel (2002), Macleod (2001), Sosa (2004).

  3. Admittedly, my understanding of practical reasoning, hence the connection between the two desire-models, presupposes the idea that practical deliberation is about reasons. This is not an undisputed thesis, but since, as far as I know, Scanlon himself adheres to it, I think there is no need to defend it in this paper. For a discussion and defense see Schroeder (2007), pp. 26–9; Goldman (2005), pp. 505–9 and (2006), p. 472.

  4. Although Scanlon (1998: 33–41) argues that seemings of reasons motivate in their own right, this need not falsify this claim. First, it is not clear that he thinks that only seemings can motivate; hence it is unclear whether he would hold that in the absence of normative seemings, no motivation is possible. It is more likely that he would instead point out that the result of subjective silencing is that the agent does not judge some consideration to be a reason that appears to him to be a reason; or that even if subjective silencing takes away both judgment and seeming, the temptations cited are either not desires or are urges that cannot provide reasons.

  5. As John McDowell (1978, 1979, 1998a, b) would suggest.

  6. Arkonovich (2001: 517–8) also advances this response. His idea is that, once we admit that it is not an ad hoc feature of desires in the subjective desire-model that they have a deliberative role, Scanlon’s challenge is disarmed. However, from the claim that desires have also a deliberative role, it does not follow that they have the particular role that a response to Scanlon’s challenge needs.

  7. Cf. Velleman (2000: 104) on Davidson’s (1980: 86) evaluative account of desire.

  8. This idea is inspired by G. H. von Wright’s (1963) account of preferences.

  9. Hubin’s words suggest that a version of Bernard Williams’ “one thought too many” argument may also be used to explain cases of swamping. The claim would be that it is unattractive to consider some consideration as a reason in the face of certain other reasons, even if these reasons apply to the case. This addition, however, is not about the structure of practical reasoning but about its content; hence it is of no interest to us.

References

  • Arkonovich, S. (2001). Defending desire: Scanlon’s anti-humeanism. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 63(3), 499–519.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Copp, D., & Sobel, D. (2002). Desires, motives, and reasons: Scanlon’s rationalistic moral psychology. Social Theory and Practice, 28(2), 243–276.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dancy, J. (2004). Ethics without principles. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Davidson, D. (1980). Intending. In his Essays on actions and events (pp. 83–103). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

  • Goldman, A. H. (2005). Reason internalism. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 71(3), 505–532.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Goldman, A. H. (2006). Desire based reasons and reasons for desires. The Southern Journal of Philosophy, 44, 469–488.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Grice, H. P. (1967). Logic and conversation. In his Studies in the way of words. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

  • Hubin, D. C. (1996). Hypothetical motivation. Noûs, 30(1), 31–54.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hubin, D. C. (1999). What’s special about humeanism. Noûs, 33(1), 30–45.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hubin, D. C. (2003). Desires, whims, and values. The Journal of Ethics, 7(3), 315–335.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McDowell, J. (1978). Are moral requirements hypothetical imperatives? Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, Supplementary Volume, 53, 13–29.

    Google Scholar 

  • McDowell, J. (1979). Virtue and reason. The Monist, 62(3), 331–350.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McDowell, J. (1998a). The role of eudaimonia in Aristotle’s ethics. In his Mind, value, and reality (pp. 3–23). Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

  • McDowell, J. (1998b). Some issues in Aristotle’s moral psychology. In S. Everson (Ed.), Ethics: Companion to ancient thought 4: Ethics (pp. 107–128). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Macleod, C. (2001). Making moral judgments and giving reasons. Canadian Journal of Philosophy, 31(2), 263–290.

    Google Scholar 

  • Noggle, R. (1999). Integrity, self, and the desire-based accounts of the good. Philosophical Studies, 96(3), 301–328.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Scanlon, T. M. (1998). What we owe to each other. Cambridge: Belknap.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schroeder, M. (2005). Realism and reduction: the quest for robustness. The Philosophers’ Imprint, 5(1), <www.philosophersimprint.org/005001/>

  • Schroeder, M. (2007). Slaves of the passions. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Schroeder, M. (2010). Value and the right kind of reason. In R. Shafer-Landau (Ed.), Oxford Studies in Metaethics, 5, 25–55.

  • Schroeder, M. (2011). Holism, weight, and undercutting. Noûs, 45(2), 328–344.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Seidman, J. (2005). Two sides of ‘silencing’. Philosophical Quarterly, 55(218), 68–77.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shemmer, Y. (2007). Desires as reasons. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 75(2), 326–348.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sosa, D. (2004). A big, good thing. Noûs, 38(2), 359–377.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Velleman, J. D. (2000). The guise of the good. In his The possibility of practical reason (pp. 99–122) New York: Oxford University Press.

  • Von Wright, G. H. (1963). The logic of preference. Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

This paper has benefited from the comments of audiences in Stockholm and Konstanz. My conversations, in these and other occasions, with Christoph Fehige were particularly instructive for writing the section on the idea of conditioning. I would also like to thank an anonymous referee of this journal for very helpful comments that have led to a major restructuring and revision of the paper. Research on this paper has been funded by a project grant of the German Research Foundation (Grant number: TA 820/1-1).

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Attila Tanyi.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Tanyi, A. Silencing Desires?. Philosophia 41, 887–903 (2013). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11406-012-9407-0

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Revised:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11406-012-9407-0

Keywords

Navigation