Skip to main content
Log in

How Much for the Child?

  • Published:
Ethical Theory and Moral Practice Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

In this paper we explore what sacrifices you are morally required to make to save a child who is about to die in front of you. It has been argued that you would have very demanding duties to save such a child (or any adult who is in similar circumstance through no fault of their own, for that matter), and some examples have been presented to make this claim seem intuitively correct. Against this, we argue that you do not in general have a moral requirement to bear more than moderate cost to save even a child who is just in front of you. Moreover, we explain why you have a much more demanding moral requirement in certain cases by appealing to the notions of undue risk and cost sharing.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Child Labour is defined by the ILO as “work that is harmful to children’s physical and mental development.” See http://www.ilo.org/ipec/Campaignandadvocacy/Youthinaction/C182-Youth-orientated/C182Youth_Background/lang-en/index.htm. Accessed 7 September, 2011.

  2. Just how high the required cost would be depends on the content of the special duties.

  3. That is, provided that Singer’s empirical assumptions about the potential of assistance to alleviate poverty are sound.

  4. A similar point is made by Arneson (Arneson 2004, 37) who writes “The mere fact of non-compliance by some does not automatically set an upper limit on the amount of sacrifice it is reasonable to demand of others who can provide cost-effective aid.”

  5. Compare Scanlon: “If you are presented with a situation in which you can prevent something very bad from happening, or alleviate someone’s dire plight, by making only a slight (or even moderate) sacrifice, then it would be wrong not to do so” (Scanlon 1998, 224).

  6. Unger writes: “Our intuitions on very many cases, both hypothetical and even actual, do nothing toward reflecting these Values, as they’re produced by powerfully Distortional Mental Tendencies that prevent us from responding in line with the Values”. (Unger 1996, 173–5)

  7. As for SAP2: Bob’s savings for retirement could be regarded as morally significant, and that is because it is more than required, more than moderate.

  8. Why does he have no insurance? Well, assume that if he had, the company would not cover damages caused by natural incidents, or that it would not cover them since Bob himself directed the avalanche towards his own new house.

References

Download references

Acknowledgments

An earlier version of this article was presented as seminars at the Australian National University and Charles Sturt University. We are grateful for comments received from audiences on those occasions, and especially to Stephanie Collins, Bashshar Haydar, Holly Lawford-Smith, Seth Lazar, Alejandra Mancilla, Leif Wenar, Luara Ferracioli and Ole Koksvik for written comments on earlier drafts. This article is part of a larger project on responsibilities to address poverty that has received financial support from the Australian Research Council and the Research Council of Norway.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Christian Barry.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Barry, C., Øverland, G. How Much for the Child?. Ethic Theory Moral Prac 16, 189–204 (2013). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10677-011-9325-4

Download citation

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10677-011-9325-4

Keywords

Navigation