Skip to main content
Log in

On the need to redress an inadequacy in animal welfare science: toward an internally coherent framework

  • Published:
Biology & Philosophy Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

The time is ripe for a greater interrogation of assumptions and commitments underlying an emerging common ground on the ethics of animal research as well on the 3 R (replacement, refinement, reduction) approach that parallels, and perhaps even further shapes, it. Recurring pressures to re-evaluate the moral status of some animals in research comes as much from within the relevant sciences as without. It seems incredible, in the light of what we now know of such animals as chimpanzees, to deny that these animals are properly accorded high moral status. Barring the requirement that they be human, it is difficult to see what more animals such as chimpanzees would have to possess to acquire it. If the grounds for ascribing high moral status are to be non-arbitrary and responsive to our best knowledge of those individuals who possess the relevant features, we should expect that a sound ethical experimental science will periodically reassess the moral status of their research subjects as the relevant knowledge demands. We already can observe this reassessment as scientists committed to humane experimental science incorporate discoveries of enrichment tools and techniques into their housing and use of captive research animals. No less should this reassessment include a critical reflection on the possible elevation of moral status of certain research animals in light of what is discovered regarding their morally significant properties, characteristics or capacities, or so I will argue. To do anything short of this threatens the social and moral legitimacy of animal research.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. As explained by Van Sluyters et al.,

    • Replacement: Use of nonanimal systems or less-sentient animal species to partially or fully replace animals.

    • Reduction: Reduction in the number of animals utilized to the minimum required to obtain scientifically valid data.

    • Refinement: Use of a method that lessens or eliminates pain and/or distress and therefore enhances animal well-being (Van Sluyters et al. 2003: 10).

  2. For agency policies in these countries see: http://apc.homeoffice.gov.uk/; http://www.ccac.ca/en/CCAC_Main.htm; http://grants.nih.gov/grants/olaw/references/phspol.htm#principle.

  3. Frey, a well known proponent of a sliding-scale approach to animal moral status, adds quality of life to considerations of psychological capacities and complexity (Frey 2005), when assessing the moral value of an animal’s life.

  4. Of course, there will be shared ethical concerns. We can reasonably expect a concern to avoid causing undue stress or suffering, as well as for unnecessarily adversely affecting the well-being of the animal subject, her group or even the greater ecosystem (e.g., Sherwin et al. 2003; Sherwin 2006).

  5. By 2000 at least 23 countries regulated animal research, though to varying degrees (Orlans 2002), while by 2005 at least 30 countries regulated animal research (Taylor et al. 2008).

  6. Other moral limits clearly drawn from the greater socio-cultural context include the special consideration given animals from species commonly chosen as pets. Examples are provided by legislated special considerations for dogs, cats and horses (see Rollin 2006).

  7. For two examples of this type of argument see: the American Association for Laboratory Animal Science (2003); Botting and Morrison (1997).

  8. There are at least two distinct ways to understand a sliding-scale approach that might be at work here. One understanding would have it that the states or capacities that ground animals’ respective interests are importantly different relative to supporting cognitive or affective capacities. For example, pain in rats is qualitatively different from pain in dogs which is again different from pain in humans because of supporting cognitive or affective capacities that inform these qualitative differences (e.g., pain matters more to dogs than rats but less than to humans). A second understanding would have it that the relevant states or capacities supporting the relevant interests of any given animal may simply be qualitatively different as ‘one’s gaze’ moves across the relevant portion of the animal kingdom. Perhaps, for example, pain in rats has a lower degree of unpleasantness than in dogs, which is, in turn, of a lower degree of unpleasantness than in humans. These different understandings do not affect the substance of my concerns with this general approach to animal moral status.

  9. With regards to great ape experimentation Knight notes that, as of 2008, “legislative or policy bans or restrictions were in place within seven European countries, Japan, Australia and New Zealand” (Knight 2008: 11).

  10. This claim may seem too strong to some ethologists (see Kennedy 1992). However, that many humane experimentalists are willing to ascribe pain capacity to mammals and other vertebrates incurs attendant moral obligations (Beauchamp 1997).

  11. I must tread very carefully here so as not to imply a cognitive capacity implausibly ascribed to primates other than humans. We do well to allow for a continuum of self-cognizance that requires varying degrees of self-understanding (with or without an associated phenomenal consciousness) in a social space. This can include the ability to discriminate ‘self’ from other in contexts where territoriality or food possession is socially important through to what, in many humans, we regard as ‘full-blown’ self-consciousness (Bekoff and Sherman 2004; de Waal 2008).

  12. One need not have a conflict situation limited in description to aggressor and defender. Conciliatory responses to aggression are also important for this point (de Waal 1996).

  13. I acknowledge that learned helplessness can complicate the approach I am advocating here, as can other behavioural problems acquired while in laboratory contexts (see Brüne et al. 2006). These are the kinds of important details which require the consensus building efforts of stake holders, including those directly charged with the psychological well-being of the animals in question.

References

  • Allen C (2006) Ethics and the science of animal minds. Theor Med Bioeth 27:375–394

    Google Scholar 

  • Allen C, Bekoff M (2007) Animal minds, cognitive ethology, and ethics. J Ethics 11:299–317

    Google Scholar 

  • Allen C, Fuchs PN, Shriver A, Wilson HD (2005) Deciphering animal pain. In: Aydede M (ed) Pain: new essays on its nature and the methodology of its study. The MIT Press, Cambridge, pp 351–366

    Google Scholar 

  • American Association for Laboratory Animal Science (2003) The use of animals in biomedical research: improving human and animal health. http://www.aalas.org/pdf/improve_human_animal_health.pdf. Accessed 1 Aug 2010

  • American Veterinary Medical Association (2010) The veterinarian’s role in animal welfare. http://www.avma.org/products/animal_welfare/welfare.pdf. Accessed 5 Aug 2010

  • Amici F, Aurelli F, Call J (2008) Fission-fusion dynamics, behavioral flexibility, and inhibitory control in primates. Curr Biol 18:1415–1419

    Google Scholar 

  • Animal Behavior Society (2004) Animal behavior society handbook: handbook of the executive committee, committee chairs, liaisons, and representatives 2004–2007. http://www.animalbehavior.org/ABSHandbook/animal-behavior-society-handbook/HandbookFrontPage. Accessed 14 June 2010 (See Policy 27)

  • Anonymous (2010) Responsibility in the use of animals in bioscience research: expectations of the major research council and charitable funding bodies. http://www.nc3rs.org.uk/page.asp?id=871. Accessed 5 August 2010

  • Baier A (1991) A naturalist view of persons. Proc Address Am Philos Assoc 65(3):5–17

    Google Scholar 

  • Balls M (1995) Chimpanzee medical experiments: moral, legal and scientific concerns. Altern Lab Anim 23:607–614

    Google Scholar 

  • Barley J (2005) Balancing the needs of animals and science. Sch Sci Rev 87(319):105–110

    Google Scholar 

  • Barrett L, Henzi P, Dunbar R (2003) Primate cognition: from ‘what now?’ to ‘what if?’ Trends Cogn Sci 7(11):494–497

    Google Scholar 

  • Baumans V (2005) Science-based assessment of animal welfare: laboratory animals. Rev Sci Tech Off Int Epizoot 24(2):503–514

    Google Scholar 

  • Baylis F, Fenton A (2007) Chimera research and stem cell therapies for human neurodegenerative disorders. Camb Q Healthc Ethics 16:195–208

    Google Scholar 

  • Bayne K (2002) Development of the human-animal research bond and its impact on animal well-being. ILAR J 43(1):4–9

    Google Scholar 

  • Bear MF, Connors BW, Paradiso MA (2007) Neuroscience: exploring the brain, 3rd edn. Lippincott Williams and Wilkins, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Beauchamp T (1997) Opposing views on animal experimentation: do animals have rights? Ethics Behav 7(2):113–121

    Google Scholar 

  • Beauchamp T (2001) The failure of theories of personhood. In: Thomasma DC, Weisstub DN, Herve C (eds) Personhood and health care. Kluwer Academic Publishers, Netherlands, pp 59–69

    Google Scholar 

  • Bekoff M, Sherman PW (2004) Reflections on animal selves. Trends Ecol Evol 19(4):176–180

    Google Scholar 

  • Bloomsmith MA, Else JG (2005) Behavioral management of chimpanzees in biomedical research facilities: the state of the science. ILAR J 46(2):192–201

    Google Scholar 

  • Bloomsmith MA, Schapiro SJ, Strobert EA (2006) Preparing chimpanzees for laboratory research. ILAR J 47(4):316–325

    Google Scholar 

  • Botting JH, Morrison AR (1997) Animal research is vital to medicine. Sci Am February 1997:83–85

    Google Scholar 

  • Brazier M (1997) Report of the animal procedures committee for 1997. The Stationery Office, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Brüne M, Brüne-Cohrs U, McGrew WC, Preuschoft S (2006) Psychopathology in great apes: concepts, treatment options and possible homologies to human psychiatric disorders. Neurosci Biobehav Rev 30:1246–1259

    Google Scholar 

  • Cavalieri P, Singer P (eds) (1993) The great ape project: equality beyond humanity. Fourth Estate, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Coenen AML (2007) Consciousness without a cortex, but what kind of consciousness is this? Behav Brain Sci 30(1):87–88

    Google Scholar 

  • Cohen C (1986) The case for the use of animals in biomedical research. N Engl J Med 315(14):865–870

    Google Scholar 

  • Coleman K (2010) Caring for nonhuman primates in biomedical research facilities: scientific, moral and emotional considerations. Am J Primatol 71:1–6

    Google Scholar 

  • Conour LA, Murray KA, Brown MJ (2006) Preparation for animals in research—issues to consider for rodents and rabbits. ILAR J 47(4):283–293

    Google Scholar 

  • Crowley SJ, Allen C (2008) Animal Behavior. In: Ruse M (ed) The Oxford handbook of philosophy of biology. Oxford University Press, New York, pp 327–348

    Google Scholar 

  • Dawkins MS (1990) From an animal’s point of view: motivation, fitness, and animal welfare. Behav Brain Sci 13:1–9

    Google Scholar 

  • Dawkins R (1993) Gaps in the mind. In: Cavalieri P, Singer P (eds) The great ape project: equality beyond humanity. Fourth Estate, London, pp 80–87

    Google Scholar 

  • Dawkins MS (1998) Considering animal welfare from the animal’s point of view. In: Hart LA (ed) Responsible conduct with animals in research. Oxford University Press, New York, pp 132–141

    Google Scholar 

  • Dawkins MS (2006) A user’s guide to animal welfare science. Trends Ecol Evol 21(2):77–82

    Google Scholar 

  • Dawkins MS (2008) The science of animal suffering. Ethology 114:937–945

    Google Scholar 

  • de Waal FBM (1996) Conflict as negotiation. In: McGrew WC, Marchant LF, Nishida T (eds) Great ape societies. Cambridge University Press, New York, pp 159–172

    Google Scholar 

  • de Waal FBM (2005) A century of getting to know the chimpanzee. Nature 437:56–59

    Google Scholar 

  • de Waal FBM (2008) The thief in the mirror. PLOS Biol 6(8):1621–1622

    Google Scholar 

  • de Waal FBM (2011) What is an animal emotion? Ann N Y Acad Sci 1224:191–206

    Google Scholar 

  • de Waal FBM, Aureli F (1996) Consolation, reconciliation, and a possible cognitive difference between macaques and chimpanzees. In: Russon AE, Bard KA, Parker ST (eds) Reaching into thought: the minds of the great apes. Cambridge University Press, New York, pp 80–110

    Google Scholar 

  • de Waal FBM, Brosnan S (2006) Simple and complex reciprocity in primates. In: Kappeler PM, van Schaik CP (eds) Cooperation in primates and humans. Spinger, Berlin, pp 85–105

    Google Scholar 

  • DeGrazia D (1991) The moral status of animals and their use in research: a philosophical review. Kennedy Inst Ethics J 1(1):48–70

    Google Scholar 

  • DeGrazia D (1999) The ethics of animal research: what are the prospects for agreement? Camb Q Healthc Ethics 8:23–34

    Google Scholar 

  • DeGrazia D (2002) Animal rights: a very short introduction. Oxford University Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • DeGrazia D (2006) On the question of personhood beyond Homo sapiens. In: Singer P (ed) Defense of Animals: The Second Wave. Blackwell Publishing Ltd., Malden, pp 40–53

    Google Scholar 

  • Derbyshire SWG, Furedi A (1996) Do fetuses feel pain? ‘Fetal pain’ is a misnomer. Br Med J 313:795

    Google Scholar 

  • Diamond C (2004) Eating meat and eating people. In: Sunstein CR, Nussbaum MC (eds) Animal rights: current debates and new directions. Oxford University Press, New York, pp 93–107

    Google Scholar 

  • Donovan J (1996) Attention to suffering: a feminist caring ethic for the treatment of animals. J Soc Philos 27(1):81–102

    Google Scholar 

  • Driscoll JW, Bateson P (1992) Animals in behavioural research. In: Dawkins MS, Gosling M (eds) Ethics in research on animal behavior: readings from animal behaviour. Academic Press, London, pp 7–12

    Google Scholar 

  • Fenton A, Krahn T (2010) Interrogating the boundary of human-level and T moral status. AJOB Neurosci 1(2):61–63

    Google Scholar 

  • Fins J (2005) Rethinking disorders of consciousness: new research and its implications. Hastings Cent Rep 35(2):22–24

    Google Scholar 

  • Frey RG (2002) Justifying animal experimentation. Society 39(6):37–47

    Google Scholar 

  • Frey RG (2005) Animals and their medical use. In: Cohen AI, Wellman CH (eds) Contemporary debates in applied ethics. Blackwell Publishing, Malden, pp 91–103

    Google Scholar 

  • Garber JC, Barbee RW, Bielitzki JT, Clayton LA, Donovan JC, Hendriksen CFM, Kohn DF, Lipman NS, Locke PA, Melcher J, Quimby FW, Turner PV, Wood GA, Wurbel H (2010) Guide for the care and use of laboratory animals, 8th edn. The National Academies Press, Washington

    Google Scholar 

  • Glover V, Fisk N (1996) Do fetuses feel pain? We don’t know; better to err on the safe side from mid-gestation. Br Med J 313:796

    Google Scholar 

  • Goodall J (1995) Why is it unethical to use chimpanzees in the laboratory? Altern Lab Anim 23:615–620

    Google Scholar 

  • Greek CR, Greek JS (2003) Specious science: why experiments on animals harm humans. Continuum International Publishing Group Incorporated, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Green RM (2002) Benefiting from ‘Evil’: an incipient moral problem in human stem cell research. Bioethics 16(6):544–556

    Google Scholar 

  • Green RM (2008) Embryo and fetal research. In: Singer PA, Viens AM (eds) The Cambridge textbook of bioethics. Cambridge University Press, New York, pp 231–237

    Google Scholar 

  • Griffin G (2009) Establishing a three Rs programme at the Canadian council on animal care. Altern Lab Anim 37(Supp. 2):63–67

    Google Scholar 

  • Hart LA (1998) Responsible animal care and use: moving toward a less-troubled middle ground. In: Hart LA (ed) Responsible conduct with animals in research. Oxford University Press, New York, pp 3–17

    Google Scholar 

  • Herzog HA (2005) Dealing with the animal research controversy. In: Akins CK, Panicker S, Cunningham CL (eds) Laboratory animals in research and teaching. American Psychological Association, Washington, pp 9–29

    Google Scholar 

  • Herzog HA, Galvin S (1997) Common sense and the mental lives of animals: an empirical approach. In: Mitchell RW, Thompson NS, Miles HL (eds) Anthropomorphism, anecdotes and animals. State University of New York Press, New York, pp 237–253

    Google Scholar 

  • Højgaard L, Makarow M (2009) ESF-EMRC position on the proposal for a directive on the protection of animals used for scientific purposes: 2nd edition March 2009. http://www.esf.org/research-areas/medical-sciences/activities/science-policy/animal-protection-in-biomedical-research.html. Accessed 5 Aug 2010

  • Hutchinson E, Avery A, VandeWoude S (2005) Environmental enrichment for laboratory rodents. ILAR J 46(2):148–161

    Google Scholar 

  • Jamieson D (1993) Great apes and the human resistance to equality. In: Cavalieri P, Singer P (eds) The great ape project: equality beyond humanity. Fourth Estate, London, pp 223–227

    Google Scholar 

  • Joint Working Group on Refinement (2001) Laboratory birds: refinements in husbandry and procedures. Lab Anim 35(Supp 1):1–163

    Google Scholar 

  • Kennedy JS (1992) The new anthropomorphism. Cambridge University Press, New York

  • King L, Rowan AN (2005) The mental health of laboratory animals. In: McMillan FD (ed) Mental health and well-being of animals. Blackwell Publishing Professional, Iowa, pp 259–276

    Google Scholar 

  • Klein HJ, Bayne KA (2007) Establishing a culture of care, conscience, and responsibility: addressing the improvement of scientific discovery and animal welfare through science-based performance standards. ILAR J 48(1):3–11

    Google Scholar 

  • Knight A (2008) The beginning of the end for chimpanzee experiments? Philos Ethics Humanit Med 3(16):1–14

    Google Scholar 

  • LaFollette H, Shanks N (1996) Brute science: dilemmas of animal experimentation. Routledge, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Lonsdorf EV, Ross SR, Matsuzawa T (2010) The mind of the chimpanzee: ecological and experimental perspectives. The University of Chicago Press, Chicago

    Google Scholar 

  • Lutz CK, Novak MA (2005) Environmental enrichment for nonhuman primates: theory and application. ILAR J 46(2):178–191

    Google Scholar 

  • Markowtiz H, Eckert K (2005) Giving power to animals. In: McMillan FD (ed) Mental health and well-being in animals. Blackwell Publishing Professional, Iowa, pp 201–209

    Google Scholar 

  • McMillan FD (2005) The concept of quality of life in animals. In: McMillan FD (ed) Mental health and well-being in animals. Blackwell Publishing Professional, Iowa, pp 183–200

    Google Scholar 

  • Merker B (2007) Consciousness without a cerebral cortex: a challenge for neuroscience and medicine. Behav Brain Sci 30(1):63–81

    Google Scholar 

  • Mitani JC (2006) Reciprocal exchange in chimpanzees and other primates. In: Kappeler PM, van Schaik CP (eds) Cooperation in primates and humans. Spinger, Berlin, pp 107–119

    Google Scholar 

  • Nelson RJ, Mandrell TD (2005) Enrichment and nonhuman primates: ‘First, Do No Harm’. ILAR J 46(2):171–177

    Google Scholar 

  • Newton-Fisher NE (2006) Female coalitions against male aggression in wild chimpanzees of the budongo forest. Int J Primatol 27(6):1589–1599

    Google Scholar 

  • Nishida T, Hosaka K (1996) Coalition strategies among adult male chimpanzees of the Mahale Mountains, Tanzania. In: McGrew WC, Marchant LF, Nishida T (eds) Great ape societies. Cambridge University Press, New York, pp 114–134

    Google Scholar 

  • Olfert ED, Cross BM, McWilliam AA (1993) Guide to the care and use of experimental animals, vol 1, 2nd edn. Canadian council on animal care. http://www.ccac.ca/en/CCAC_Programs/Guidelines_Policies/PDFs/ExperimentalAnimals_GDL.pdf. Accessed 30 Aug 2010

  • Orlans FB (2002) Ethical themes of national regulations governing animal experiments: an international perspective. In: Gluck JP, DiPasquale T, Orlans FB (eds) Applied ethics in animal research: philosophy, regulation, and laboratory applications. Purdue University Press, West Lafayette, pp 131–147

    Google Scholar 

  • Overall KL, Dyer D (2005) Enrichment strategies for laboratory animals from the viewpoint of clinical veterinary behavioral medicine: emphasis on cats and dogs. ILAR J 46(2):202–216

    Google Scholar 

  • Perry P (2007) The ethics of animal research: a UK perspective. ILAR J 48(1):42–46

    Google Scholar 

  • Plous S (1996) Attitudes toward the use of animals in psychological research and education: results from a national survey of psychology majors. Psychol Sci 7(6):352–358

    Google Scholar 

  • Pluhar E (2006) Experimentation on humans and nonhumans. Theor Med Bioeth 27(4):333–355

    Google Scholar 

  • Poole T (1997) Happy animals make good science. Lab Anim 31:116–124

    Google Scholar 

  • Pound P, Ebrahim S, Sandercock P, Bracken MB, Roberts I (2004) Where is the evidence that animal research benefits humans? Br Med J 328:514–517

    Google Scholar 

  • Rachels J (1993) Why darwinists should support equal treatment for other apes. In: Cavalieri P, Singer P (eds) The great ape project: equality beyond humanity. Fourth Estate, London, pp 152–157

    Google Scholar 

  • Rachels J (2004) Drawing Lines. In: Sunstein CR, Nussbaum MC (eds) Animal rights: current debates and new directions. Oxford University Press, New York, pp 162–174

    Google Scholar 

  • Regan T (2005) Empty cages: animal rights and vivisection. In: Cohen AI, Wellman CH (eds) Contemporary debates in applied ethics. Blackwell Publishing, Malden, pp 77–90

    Google Scholar 

  • Rennie AE, Buchanan-Smith HM (2006) Refinement of the use of non-human primates in scientific research. Part III: refinement of procedures. Anim Welf 15:239–261

    Google Scholar 

  • Robinson V (2005) Finding alternatives: an overview of the 3 Rs and the use of animals in research. Sch Sci Rev 87(319):1–4

    Google Scholar 

  • Rollin B (2006) The regulation of animal research and the emergence of animal ethics: a conceptual history. Theor Med Bioeth 27:285–304

    Google Scholar 

  • Rollin B (2007) Overcoming Ideology: why it is necessary to create a culture in which the ethical review of protocols can flourish. ILAR J 48(1):47–53

    Google Scholar 

  • Sandercock P, Roberts I (2002) Systematic reviews of animal experiments. Lancet 360:586

    Google Scholar 

  • Schuppli CA, Fraser D, McDonald M (2004) Expanding the three Rs to meet new challenges in humane animal experimentation. Altern Lab Anim 32:525–532

    Google Scholar 

  • Shapiro K (2000) Evaluation of animal model research. In: Balls M, Van Zeller A-M, Halder ME (eds) Progress in the reduction, refinement and replacement of animal experimentation. Part B. Elsevier Science, New York, pp 1541–1551

    Google Scholar 

  • Sherwin CM (2006) Guidelines for the treatment of animals in behavioural research and teaching. Anim Behav 71:245–253

    Google Scholar 

  • Sherwin CM (2007) Validating refinements to laboratory housing: asking the animals. National Centre for the Replacement, Refinement and Reduction of Animals in Research. http://www.nc3rs.org.uk/downloaddoc.asp?id=603&page=759&skin=0. Accessed 24 Aug 2010

  • Sherwin CM, Christiansen SB, Duncan IJ, Erhard HW, Lay DC Jr, Mench JA, O’Connor CE, Petherick JC (2003) Guidelines for the ethical use of animals in applied ethology studies. Appl Anim Behav Sci 81:291–305

    Google Scholar 

  • Shewmon DA, Holmes GL, Byrne PA (1999) Consciousness in congenitally decorticate children: developmental vegetative state as self-fulfilling prophecy. Dev Med Child Neurol 41:364–374

    Google Scholar 

  • Society for Neuroscience (2003) Translational neuroscience accomplishments. http://www.sfn.org/skins/main/pdf/gpa/translational.pdf. Accessed 24 June 2010

  • Steiner G (2007) Cosmic holism and obligations toward animals: a challenge to classical liberalism. J Animal L Ethics 2(1):1–20

    Google Scholar 

  • Stumpf RM (2011) Chimpanzees and bonobos: inter- and intraspecies diversity. In: Campbell CJ, Fuentes A, MacKinnon KC, Bearder SK, Stumpf RM (eds) Primates in perspective, 2nd edn. Oxford University Press, New York, pp 340–356

    Google Scholar 

  • Suran M, Wolinsky H (2009) The end of monkey research? EMBO Rep 10(10):1080–1082

    Google Scholar 

  • Taylor K, Gordon N, Langley G, Higgins W (2008) Estimates for worldwide laboratory animal use in 2005. Altern Lab Anim 36:327–342

    Google Scholar 

  • Tomasello M, Call J (1997) Primate cognition. Oxford University Press, New York

  • Tooley M (1998) Personhood. In: Kuhse H, Singer P (eds) A companion to bioethics. Blackwell Publishing Ltd, Malden, pp 117–126

    Google Scholar 

  • van Sluyters RC, Ballinger M, Bayne K, Cunningham C, Degryse A, Dubner R, Evans H, Gdowski MJ, Knight R, Mench J, Nelson RJ, Parks C, Stein B, Toth L, Zola S (2003) Guidelines for the care and use of mammals in neuroscience and behavioral research. The National Academies Press, Washington

    Google Scholar 

  • Varner G (1994) The prospects for consensus and convergence in the animal rights debate. Hastings Cent Rep 24(1):24–28

    Google Scholar 

  • von Rohr CR, Burkart JM, van Schaik CP (2011) Evolutionary precursors of social norms in chimpanzees: a new approach. Biol Philos 26:1–30

    Google Scholar 

  • Waitt C, Buchanan-Smith HM (2002) The effects of caretaker-primate relationships on primates in the laboratory. J Appl Anim Welf Sci 5(4):309–319

    Google Scholar 

  • Walport M, Borysiewicz L, Kell D, Denegri S, Dyer R, Festing S, Applebee K, Brinsmead C, Burnand A (2009) UK bioscience sector declaration of concern on the revision of EU directive 86/609 on animal experimentation. http://www.bbsrc.ac.uk/web/FILES/Reviews/animal_experimentation_declaration_of_concern.pdf. Accessed 5 Aug 2010

  • Wise SM (2004) Animal rights, one step at a time. In: Sunstein CR, Nussbaum MC (eds) Animal rights: current debates and new directions. Oxford University Press, New York, pp 19–50

    Google Scholar 

  • Zurlo J, Rudacille D, Goldberg AM (1996) The three Rs: the way forward. Environ Health Perspect 104(8):878–880

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

Research was funded by the Canadian Institutes of Health Research, NNF 80045 “States of Mind: Emerging Issues in Neuroethics”. Thanks also to Letitia Meynell, a symposium audience from the Neuroscience Institute at Dalhousie University (particularly Alan Fine), and an anonymous reviewer at Philosophy and Biology for feedback on certain points or arguments.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Andrew Fenton.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Fenton, A. On the need to redress an inadequacy in animal welfare science: toward an internally coherent framework. Biol Philos 27, 73–93 (2012). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10539-011-9291-1

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10539-011-9291-1

Keywords

Navigation