Skip to main content

Advertisement

Log in

Ideological Struggle as Agonistic Conflict (Anti)Hypocrisy, Free Speech and Critical Social Justice

  • Original Article
  • Published:
Jus Cogens Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

This article addresses two questions: How should a ‘practical political theory’ approach the ideological struggle between advocates of critical social justice and defenders of free speech? And, what does this conflict tell us about the deficits of one particular tradition of practical political theory — namely, agonistic democracy? The paper’s purpose, then, is to illuminate a concrete contemporary phenomenon (i.e., the struggle between advocates of critical social justice and defenders of free speech) through the lens of agonistic theory and, conversely, to use this struggle as an impetus to carve out and address weaknesses in the theory of agonism.

I defend an ‘agonistic approach’ to the struggle against two alternatives — first, the claim that there is, conceptually, no ‘real’ conflict between social justice and free speech, and second, the strategy to ‘take sides’ in the conflict. By taking seriously the agonistic core idea that struggle and conflict can be valuable and productive expressions of plurality and inclusivity, I argue that this struggle should be approached as an agonistic conflict — as the welcome and important expression of a diversity of views on central social, moral and political questions.

I also show, however, how retaining the focus on the real-life struggle between advocates of critical social justice and free-speech sheds light on the inconsistencies of much agonistic thought. In particular, I will criticize those agonists who limit their conception of the ‘agon’ to respectful struggles (agonistic respect), and those who see the agon merely as a tool of emancipation for oppressed groups. Against these visions of agonism, I develop an anti-perfectionist, yet radical, account of agonism with the potential to serve as a guide in complex social and political conflicts.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. I stress ‘critical’ as the article does not engage with ‘social justice’ more generally, but a particular understanding of it. Advocates and opponents alike seem to agree on the label ‘critical social justice’. Robin diAngelo and Ozlem Sensoy — two advocates — define it as follows: ‘We use the term critical social justice. We do so in order to distinguish our standpoint on social justice from mainstream [social justice] standpoints. A critical approach to social justice refers to specific theoretical perspectives that recognize that society is stratified (i.e., divided and unequal) in significant and far-reaching ways along social group lines that include race, class, gender, sexuality, and ability. Critical social justice recognizes inequality as deeply embedded in the fabric of society (i.e., as structural), and actively seeks to change this’ (2017: xx).

  2. It is not my intention to treat these camps as homogenous groups as it is true that we find a variety of different voices within the camps. It is equally true, though, that there is a struggle between a group that strongly advocates ideals of social justice and one that seeks to defend free speech against what they see as the dangerous excesses of the former. The distinction between two camps is, thus, not only heuristically useful but also reflected on the ‘rough ground’ of politics.

  3. I think it is safe to assume that the readers of this journal are familiar with the basic tenets of agonism: Far from being a coherent theory, agonism is a tradition of thought that emphasizes the ethical and political value of certain forms of conflict (the agon), insists on the importance of human plurality, and adopts a tragic vision of politics. This triumvirate of plurality, struggle and tragedy leads, in the eyes of agonists, to non-domination: plurality creates perpetual agonistic struggles that are both an indicator and a creator of freedom. For book-length overviews of agonism, see Wingenbach (2011); Wenman (2013); for shorter introductions, Schaap (2007); Fossen (2008).

  4. Admittedly, I use McNay’s phrase here out of context; I will, however, engage with her potential objection in the Conclusion.

  5. Michael Freeden’s work (especially Freeden 1998) on ideology is particularly insightful. For a recent discussion on Shklar and ideology, see Bajohr (2020).

  6. For a fairly balanced discussion of how the conflict has evolved at University campuses with the rise of ‘no platforming’ since the 1970s, see Smith (2020a, b).

  7. This is certainly true for liberals. John Rawls, for instance, enumerates and staunchly defends ‘freedom of speech’ as a basic liberty (1999: 53, 178, 195, 197). The Letter, too, ‘refuse[s] any false choice between justice and freedom, which cannot exist without each other’. Advocates of critical social justice, however, are highly critical of liberalism and argue that free speech can be a tool of domination and oppression.

  8. The fact that both camps tend to couch the conflict in these terms is simply a testament to its ideological nature.

  9. This is true even for radical authors such as Gavin Titley, who concludes that free speech ‘as it is currently understood functions as a structure of racialized coercion’ (2020: 137; emphasis added).

  10. I say one of the reasons as I will return to this point in the final section.

  11. Admittedly, Mouffe is attentive to the passions that shape political life and agonistic conflict (2005: 30; also Mihai 2014) and has even directly criticized Connolly’s conception of agonistic respect (2013: 13–14). Perhaps the objection I am levelling against agonists has the least force against Mouffe’s account. I cannot pursue this question further here; suffice it to say that I am sceptical of Mouffe’s particular claim that agonistic conflict should be imagined as ‘legitimate dissent among friends’.

  12. I respond to this objection in the Conclusion.

  13. My criticism here chimes with Teresa Bejan’s point that ‘modern civil silencers… set the deliberative bar quite high, placing constraints not only on the manner in which fundamental disagreements are conducted but also on what kinds of disagreements can take place, where, and with whom (2017: 148).

  14. Admittedly, not all agonists employ the idea of agonistic respect (or at least not explicitly); but this does not change the fact that many agonists do (either implicitly or explicitly). It is also worth mentioning that my argument differs from those who criticize the concept of ‘agonistic respect’. Mouffe, for instance, reprimands the idea of agonistic respect as too inclusive since it has — allegedly — precious little to say on exclusion (2013: 13–14). My point, however, is the exact opposite: I assert that the idea of agonistic respect is not inclusive enough. More fruitful, I think, is Mark Wenman’s critique that ‘the implication [of agonistic respect is] that we might find solutions to our present predicament in the civic virtues of agonistic respect and critical responsiveness, rather than in, say, a radical transformation of the present system of global inequality and domination’ (2013: 123). Now, Wenman’s call for a radical transformation of global structures is beyond the scope of this article; but I do insist that Connolly’s ethos of agonistic respect is counterproductive to the radical agonism I lay out.

  15. I say ‘many’, not ‘all’ because there are, undoubtedly, conflicts where the roles are seemingly more obvious; what I am talking about here are the countless ‘complex social conflicts’ in which a ‘good vs evil’ approach is simplistic, counterproductive, and dangerous. In this context, I should mention that a discussant who commented on a draft of this paper at a workshop urged me to ‘take sides with the oppressed’. This, however, presupposes that in the conflict between advocates of critical social justice and defenders of free speech, one side is oppressed and the other is the oppressor — it suggests, in other words, that this is not a ‘complex social conflict’. And, as stated, I strongly believe that this is a simplistic position.

References

  • Arendt H (2006). Eichmann in Jerusalem. New York, NY: Penguin Classics.

  • Bajohr H, Trimcev R (Eds.) (2018) Themenheft zur politischen Theorie von Judith N. Shklar, Zeitschrift für Politische Theorie, Vol. 218(2).

  • Bajohr, H (2020). On liberal disharmony: Judith Shklar and the ‘ideology of agreement’. Journal of the History of Ideas Blog. Online: https://jhiblog.org/2020/05/06/on-liberal-disharmony-judith-n-shklar-and-the-ideology-of-agreement/2020 (accessed 25 September 2021).

  • Bejan T (2017) Mere Civility: Disagreement and the Limits of Toleration. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press

  • Brown W (2008) Regulating Aversion: Tolerance in the Age of Identity and Empire. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press

  • Butler J (2017) The Limits of Free Speech? Academe blog, Online: https://academeblog.org/2017/12/07/free-expression-or-harassment/ (accessed 28 September 2021)-

  • Chambers S (2001). Language and Politics: Agonistic Discourse in the West Wing. CTHEORY. Online. Online: https://journals.uvic.ca/index.php/ctheory/article/view/14591 (accessed 05 August 2021).

  • Connolly W (2005) Pluralism. London, UK: Duke University Press

  • Daqing W (2010) On the Ancient Greek Αγων. Procedia: Social and Behavioral Sciences, Vol. 2(5), pp 6805–6812.

  • Douthat R (2020) Opinion. 10 Theses about cancel culture. The New York Times, 14 July 2020. Online: https://www.nytimes.com/2020/07/14/opinion/cancel-culture-.html (accessed 2 August 2021).

  • Freeden M (1998) Ideologies and Political Theory: A Conceptual Approach. Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press.

  • Gatta G (2018) Rethinking Liberalism for the 21st Century: The Skeptical Radicalism of Judith Shklar. Routledge, London

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Gatta, G (2020), Liberalism for dark times: Judith Shklar versus populist constituencies, Global Intellectual History. https://doi.org/10.1080/23801883.2020.1826083

  • Grossman, N (2020). Free speech defenders don’t understand the critique against them. Medium. Online: https://arcdigital.media/free-speech-defenders-dont-understand-the-critique-against-them-4ed8327c0879 (accessed 15 August 2021)

  • Haidt J, Lukianoff G (2017) The Coddling of the American Mind: How Good Intentions and Bad Ideas are Setting Up a Generation for Failure. New York, NY: Penguin

  • Hall S (1988) ‘“The Toad in the Garden”: Thatcherism among the Theorists’. In Marxism and the Interpretation of Culture, edited by Cary Nelson and Lawrence Grossberg, pp 35–74. Urbana, Ill.: University of Illinois Press.

  • Harper’s Magazine (2020). A Letter on Justice and Open Debate. Online: https://harpers.org/a-letter-on-justice-and-open-debate/ (accessed 12 September 2021).

  • Hess A (2018) The meaning of exile: Judith N Shklar’s maieutic discourse. Eur J Soc Theory 21(3):288–303

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Laclau, E and Mouffe, C (2014). Hegemony and Socialist Strategy: Towards a Radical Democratic Politics. 2nd edition. London, UK: Verso.

  • Manavis S (2020) Cancel Culture Does Not Exist. The New Statesman. Online: https://www.newstatesman.com/science-tech/2020/07/cancel-culture-does-not-exist (accessed 11 August 2021).

  • McNay, L (2014). The Misguided Search for the Political, Cambridge, UK: Polity.

  • Mihai M (2014) Theorizing Agonistic Emotions. Parallax 20(2):31–48

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mouffe C (ed.) (1999) The Challenge of Carl Schmitt. London, UK: Verso.

  • Mouffe C (2005) On the Political. New York, NY: Routledge.

  • Mouffe, C (2013) Agonistics: Thinking the World Politically. London, UK: Verso.

  • Moyn S (2019) ‘Before – and Beyond – the Liberalism of Fear’. In Between Utopia and Realism: The Political Thought of Judith N. Shklar, edited by Samantha Ashenden and Andreas Hess, pp 24–46. Philadelphia, PA: University of Pennsylvania Press.

  • Moyn S (2020) Abuse of the power to cancel is why I signed the letter. The Guardian, 8 July 2020. Online: https://www.theguardian.com/commentisfree/2020/jul/08/is-free-speech-under-threat-cancel-culture-writers-respond (accessed 2 August 2021)

  • Müller JW (2008) Fear and freedom: on cold war liberalism. Eur J Polit Theo 7(1):45–64

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Özlem, S and DiAngelo, R (2017). Is Everyone Really Equal? An Introduction to Key Concepts in Social Justice Education. 2nd edition. New York, NY: Teachers College Press.

  • Rawls J (1999) A Theory of Justice. Revised edition. Cambridge, MA: The Belknap Press of Harvard University Press.

  • Ross L (2019) Opinion. I’m a black feminist. I think call-out culture is toxic. The New York Times, 17 August 2019. Online: https://www.nytimes.com/2019/08/17/opinion/sunday/cancel-culture-call-out.html (accessed 23 August 2021).

  • Sabl, A (2019). ‘Judith Shklar, Ordinary Vices’. In Jacob Levy, The Oxford Handbook of Classics in Contemporary Political Theory, Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press. Epub ahead of print. https://doi.org/10.1093/oxfordhb/9780198717133.013.5.

  • Schaap A (ed.) (2009). Law and Agonistic Politics. New York, NY: Routledge.

  • Shinko R (2008) Agonistic peace: a postmodern reading. Millennium 36(3):473–491

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shklar JN (1957) After Utopia: The Decline of Political Faith. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.

  • Shklar JN (1984) Ordinary Vices. Boston, MA: Belknap Press of Harvard University Press.

  • Shklar JN (1986) Legalism: Law, Morals, and Political Trials. New edition. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

  • Shklar JN (1990) The Faces of Injustice. Reprint edition. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press.

  • Shklar, J N (1998). Political Thought and Political Thinkers. Edited by Stanley Hoffmann. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press.

  • Smith B (2020) Moral Cruelty and the Left. Tablet. Online: https://www.tabletmag.com/sections/arts-letters/articles/judith-shklar-politics-of-fear (accessed 17 August 2021).

  • Smith E (2020) No Platform: A History of Anti-Fascism, Universities and the Limits of Free Speech. New York, NY: Routledge.

  • Stanley J (2018) When Fascists weaponize free speech absolutism. Literary Hub (blog). Online: https://lithub.com/when-fascists-weaponize-free-speech-absolutism/ (accessed 27 July 2021).

  • The Objective (2020) A More Specific Letter on Justice and Open Debate. Online: https://theobjective.substack.com/p/a-more-specific-letter-on-justice (accessed 7 September 2021).

  • Titley G (2020) Is Free Speech Racist? Cambridge, UK: Polity.

  • Tully J (2008) Public Philosophy in a New Key: Democracy and Civic Freedom Volume 1. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press

  • Tully J (2008) Public Philosophy in a New Key: Imperialism and Civic Freedom Volume 2. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.

  • Watson E (2020) The origin of woke: how the death of woke led to the birth of cancel culture. Okayplayer. Online: https://www.okayplayer.com/culture/woke-cancel-culture-meaning.html (accessed 23 August 2021).

  • Wenman M (2013) Agonistic Democracy. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.

  • Westphal M (2018) Die Normativität Agonaler Politik: Konfliktregulierung und Institutionengestaltung in der Pluralistischen Demokratie. Berlin, GER: Nomos.

  • Wingenbach E (2011) Institutionalizing Agonistic Democracy: Post-Foundationalism and Political Liberalism. New York, NY: Routledge.

  • Yack B (ed.) (1996) Liberalism without Illusions: Essays on Liberal Theory and the Political Vision of Judith N. Shklar. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press.

Download references

Acknowledgements

I have presented earlier versions of this paper to the POLEMO research group on legal, political, and social theory at Central European University as well as at the Institute for Philosophy and Social Theory at the University of Belgrade. I am grateful to the participants for their feedback, ideas, and criticism. Moreover, I would like to thank the anonymous reviewers of Jus Cogens for their feedback. The usual disclaimer applies.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Christof Royer.

Ethics declarations

Conflict of interest

The author declares no competing interests.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Royer, C. Ideological Struggle as Agonistic Conflict (Anti)Hypocrisy, Free Speech and Critical Social Justice. Jus Cogens 3, 257–278 (2021). https://doi.org/10.1007/s42439-021-00046-1

Download citation

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s42439-021-00046-1

Keywords

Navigation