Skip to main content
Log in

Hans Albert’s Systematic Approach to Critical Rationalism

  • Research Paper
  • Published:
Homo Oeconomicus Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

On occasion of Hans Albert’s 100-th anniversary the paper addresses a wider audience of philosophers, political scientists and economists who are broadly interested in critical rationalism but not well acquainted with Albert’s systematization of the Popperian philosophical program. Laying out Albert’s intellectual career and his critical realism, fallibilism and methodological revisionism puts him on the present intellectual PPE map as a philosopher-economist in his own right. Beyond contributions to the “Positivismusstreit” and his seminal work on “Model Platonism” in economics, in particular his views on technological thinking and the role of institutions in science have wide ranging, still underappreciated implications.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Albert is known as Streiter (“fighter”), who loves being part of Kontroversen (“disputes”) or Auseinandersetzungen (“polemics”). See Zimmer and Morgenstern (2011).

  2. Already in Treatise on Critical Reason, Albert criticizes “the idea of a double truth” (i.e. scientific and religious) as “dualistic metaphysic” (i.e. realistic and transcendent). Albert points out that “the motive for choosing such a strategy is easy to see: although one is in certain possession of the truth, one has a fear of critical examination and would rather sacrifice the elementary morality of thought—that is, logic—than risk the loss of this presumably certain possession” (Albert 1985, p. 133–134). For the latest detailed criticism of religion see: Albert (2013).

  3. See Münchhausen trilemma below.

  4. Albert considers Heidegger’s initial question about being (Seinsfrage)—or about the meaning of being—to be completely unclear. To answer this question, Heidegger created the so-called fundamental ontology, which makes “being” the foundation of everything. Albert considers Heidegger’s fundamental ontology to be a misunderstanding of the nature of logic, and thus a “fundamental error” (Grundirrtum). Furthermore, Albert uncompromisingly criticizes Heidegger’s way of expression, which he considers “empty music of words” (begriffslose Wortmusik). See: Albert (2000), p. 121. Speaking of music in this context Hans Albert is particular fond of the musical comment on Heidegger: https://www.youtube.com/watch?v=3goPOfcu-JI.

  5. English translation Treatise on Critical Reason by Mary Varney Rorty, published in 1985.

  6. Albert was in contact with other critical rationalists like John Watkins, Imre Lakatos, Alan Musgrave and Joseph Agassi. Critical rationalists whom he directly influenced as professor in Mannheim are e.g. Alfred Bohnen, Axel Bühler, Volker Gadenne and Herbert Keuth.

  7. The young Popper was also strongly influenced by Kant—see his first unpublished writing Die beiden Grundprobleme der Erkenntnistheorie (1931–1933). See Popper (1994), resp. 2008.

  8. Wootton (2016) confirms that a critical realist conception of science was underlying the so called „scientific revolution“ that preceded the Enlightenment.

  9. For more details about the Positivismusstreit see Adorno et al. (1972) or e.g. Paitlova (2019).

  10. The trilemma is inspired by Jakob Friedrich Fries (who is also mentioned by Popper in his Logic of Scientific Discovery). Fries formulated a trilemma in which statements can be accepted either: dogmatically, supported by infinite regress or based on perceptual experience. Fries rejected the first two possibilities and chose the third option. For more see https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/M%C3 %BCnchhausen_trilemma.

  11. See also Albert (1985, p. 98).

  12. Albert refers to Popper’s term “myth of framework”, because pure theory of knowledge is based on assumptions that determine the framework of the preferred form of thought. Such frameworks seem inviolable only because they rule out methodological revisionism.

  13. For more see Adorno et al. (1972).

  14. For example, the lack of self-criticism of critical rationalism is blamed by the prominent critic of Albert in the German speaking countries—Gerhard Ebeling who devoted an entire book Kritischer Rationalismus? (1973) to the critique of Albert’s Traktat über kritische Vernunft. And Hans Albert replied in a similarly detailed way: in the book Theologische Holzwege. Gerhard Ebeling und der rechte Gebrauch der Vernunft (1973).

  15. Hans and Gretel Albert translated Musgrave (1993) into German. Since Hans Albert thinks of it as presenting critical rationalism at its best, Alan Musgrave’s arguments are prominently invoked subsequently.

  16. Andersson further argues that in principle, logic remains open to criticism; see Andersson (1998).

  17. See Popper (2005, p. 3). Musgrave (2009, p. 205) sees it more comprehensively: “We need a logic of discovery, a logic of justification, and a logic of criticism.” “The logic of” is here meant loosely as “the way things work”. Of course, the workings of science involve also logic in a strict sense, but not only logic.

  18. See footnote 3.

  19. Alluding to the title of an early book in the field; (Lumsden and Wilson 2005).

References

  • Adorno, T. W., Albert, Hans, Dahrendorf, Ralf, H., Jürgen, P., Harald, and Popper Karl (1972). Der Positivismusstreit in der deutschen Soziologie. Frankfurt am Main: Luchterhand. (English translation: The Positivist dispute in German sociology. Heinemann, 1976.).

    Google Scholar 

  • Albert, H. (1973). Theologische Holzwege. Gerhard Ebeling und der rechte Gebrauch der Vernunft. Tübingen: Mohr Siebeck.

    Google Scholar 

  • Albert, H. (1982). Die Wissenschaft und die Fehlbarkeit der Vernunft. Tübingen: Mohr Siebeck.

    Google Scholar 

  • Albert, H. (1985). Treatise on critical reason (translated by Mary Varney Rorty). Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Albert, H. (1987). Kritik der reinen Erkenntnislehre. Das Erkenntnisproblem in realistischer Perspektive. Tübingen: Mohr Siebeck.

    Google Scholar 

  • Albert, H. (1989). Die Möglichkeit der Erkenntnis. In K. Salamun (Ed.), Karl R. Popper und die Philosophie des kritischen Rationalismus (pp. 3–18). Amsterdam: Rodopi.

    Google Scholar 

  • Albert, H. (1991). Traktat über kritische Vernunft (5., verbesserte und erweiterte Auflage). Tübingen: Mohr Siebeck.

    Google Scholar 

  • Albert, H. (2000). Kritischer Rationalismus. Vier Kapitel zur Kritik illusionären Denkens. Tübingen: Mohr Siebeck.

    Google Scholar 

  • Albert, H. (2010a). In Kontroversen verstrickt. Vom Kulturpessimismus zum kritischen Rationalismus. Münster: LIT Verlag.

    Google Scholar 

  • Albert, H. (2010b). The economic tradition and the constitution of science. Public Choice, 144, 401–411.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Albert, H. (2011). Kritische Vernunft und rationale Praxis. Tübingen: Mohr Siebeck.

    Google Scholar 

  • Albert, H. (2013). Kritik des theologischen Denkens. Münster: LIT Verlag.

    Google Scholar 

  • Albert, M. (2019). Karl Popper und die Verfassung der Wissenschaft. In G. Franco (Ed.), Handbuch Karl Popper (pp. 1–17). Wiesbaden: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Andersson, G. (1998). Die Kritisierbarkeit der Logik. In V. Gadenne (Ed.), Kritischer Rationalismus und Pragmatismus. Amsterdam: Rodopi.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bartley, W. W. (1984). The retreat to commitment. London: Open Court Publishing.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ebeling, G. (1973). Kritischer Rationalismus? Zu Hans Alberts Traktat über kritische Vernunft. Tübingen: Mohr Siebeck.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kant, I. (1998). Critique of pure reason (Translated and edited by P. Guyer & A. W. Wood). Cambridge: Immanuel Kant.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lumsden, C. J., & Wilson, E. O. (2005). Genes, mind, and culture: the coevolutionary process. Harvard: World Scientific Publishing Company.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Musgrave, A. (1993). Common sense, science and scepticism: A historical introduction to the theory of knowledge. New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Musgrave, A. (2004). How Popper [Might Have] solved the problem of induction. Philosophy, 79, 19–31.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Musgrave, A. (2009). Popper and hypothetico-deductivism. In D. M. Gabbay, J. Woods, & S. Hartmann (Eds.), Handbook of the history of logic. Volume 10: Inductive logic. Amsterdam: Elseiver.

    Google Scholar 

  • Paitlova, J. (2019). Das Wertfreiheitsproblem und die Holzwege des Positivismusstreits. Aufklärung und Kritik, 3, 38–50.

    Google Scholar 

  • Popper, K. (1994). Die beiden Grundprobleme der Erkenntnistheorie (English translation: The two fundamental problems of theory of knowledge, Routledge 2008). Tübingen: Mohr Siebeck.

    Google Scholar 

  • Popper, K. (1999). All life is problem solving. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Popper, K. (2005). The logic of scientific discovery. London: Routledge.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Wendel, H. J. (1996). Fallibilismus und Letztbegründung. Über notwendige Voraussetzungen und die Kontingenz von deren Erkenntnis. In V. Gadenne & H. J. Wendel (Eds.), Rationalität und Kritik (pp. 29–55). Tübingen: Mohr Siebeck.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wohlgemuth, M. (2012). Wettbewerb als Entdeckungs- und Widerlegungsverfahren. Hans Alberts Plädoyer für einen konsequenten Fallibilismus. In G. Franco (Ed.), Der kritische Rationalismus als Denkmethode und Lebensweise (pp. 255–275). Klagenfurt/Wien: Kitab Verlag.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wootton, D. (2016). The invention of science: A new history of the scientific revolution. New York: Harper.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zimmer, R., & Morgenstern, M. (Eds.). (2011). Gespräche mit Hans Albert. Münster: LIT Verlag.

Download references

Acknowledgements

This study was funded by Grantová Agentura České Republiky (Grant number 18-08239S).

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Jitka Paitlová.

Additional information

Publisher’s note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Paitlová, J. Hans Albert’s Systematic Approach to Critical Rationalism. Homo Oecon 39, 3–24 (2022). https://doi.org/10.1007/s41412-021-00107-2

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Revised:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s41412-021-00107-2

Keywords

JEL Classification

Navigation