Skip to main content
Log in

Laws of organization and chemical analysis: Blainville and Müller

  • Original Paper
  • Published:
History and Philosophy of the Life Sciences Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

When “general physiology” emerged as a basic field of research within biology in the early nineteenth century, Henri Ducrotay de Blainville (1777–1850) on the one hand and Johannes Peter Müller (1801–1858) on the other appealed to chemical analysis to account for the properties and operations of organisms that were observed to differ from what was found in inorganic compounds. Their aim was to establish laws of vital organization that would be based on organic chemical processes, but would also be of use to explain morphological and functional differences among life forms. The intent of this paper is to specify for each of these leading physiologists the different presuppositions that provided theoretical frameworks for their interpretation of what they conceived of as laws of organization underpinning the dynamics of vital phenomena. Blainville presumed that the properties of organic compounds depended on the chemical properties of their constitutive molecules, but combined according to patterns of functional development, and that the latter could only be inferred from an empirical survey of modes of organization across the spectrum of life forms. For Müller, while all vital processes involved chemical reactions, in the formative and functional operations of organisms, these reactions would result from the action of life forces that were responsible for the production of organic combinations and thus for vital and animal functions. As both physiologists set significant methodological patterns for their many disciples and followers, their respective quasi-reductionist and anti-reductionist positions need to be accounted for.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Only part of the Cours was published (de Blainville 1833). For an indication of the full range of issues covered, see the printed program of lessons, Plan du cours de physiologie générale et comparée fait à la faculté des sciences de Paris pendant les années 1829, 1830, 1831 et 1832, to be found in Clauzade (2009, Appendix 2, pp. 329–332). All translations from de Blainville (1833) are mine.

  2. Though he does not speak of “vitalism” in his Cours (de Blainville 1833), Blainville is critical of theories that identify the “principle of life” as a specific agent eliciting vital processes that are unconnected with the determining conditions of their material constituents. In so doing, he seems to be in agreement with François Magendie’s (1783–1855) criticism of the “vitalists” (Magendie 1809; Rey 2000, pp. 394–401).

  3. Blainville framed a notion of individual organism according to which it arises from generative organic matter and hierarchically develops more or less complex morphologies in harmonic connection with the conditions of its external milieu. For an analysis of this aspect of his physiology, see Balan (1979, p. 18) who quotes from Blainville (1833, II, p. 4): “Through this study, we get to understand that the relationship of functions to set arrangements of molecules and solids is one of the foremost conditions of functions. We thus get to know that such or such a form is required for the relations of organs to each other or of the same to the external world, and that on this account a perfect harmony exists between living beings and the circumstances in which they have to live”.

  4. To be more exact, Blainville’s conceptions were partly endorsed by August Comte (1798–1857) in lessons 40–44 of the Cours de philosophie positive. As mentioned by Clauzade: “What Comte owes to his friend, as acknowledged in a note to Lesson 40, is a general conception of biology as structured by extremely efficient methodological tools, at the first rank of which the distinction static/dynamic is to be found. It may be easily shown that the plan of the lessons on biology largely resumes that of Blainville’s lectures on physiology, and even original conceptions that Comte explicitly attributes to Bichat or Barthez are presented and eventually reorganized according to a Blainvillian framework” (Clauzade 2009, p. 90). In matters of scientific methodology, Blainville would avoid resorting to hypotheses involving vital principles that would act as special agents, but, at the same time, he believed that the consequences that could be drawn from empirical and experimental facts could not but conflict with the metaphysical tenets of his Christian spiritualism (Clauzade 2102).

  5. For translations of that work we shall refer to the English edition (Müller 1842) and, in some cases, to the French edition (Müller 1851). For passages only present in the latter, translations will be mine.

  6. Müller first introduced cellular explanations in his Ueber den feinern Bau und die Formen der krankhaften Geschwülste (Müller 1838; Rather 1978). He then revised his Handbuch to take account of Schwann’s cell theory, which he reinterpreted along his own tenets (Muller 1851, I, p. 7, 42; Löhff 1978; Duchesneau 1987, pp. 215–231).

  7. Müller refers to the series of controversies that had arisen on this issue since the publication of John Turberville Needham’s (1713–1781) Nouvelles Recherches microscopiques (Needham 1750) and Lazzaro Spallanzani’s (1729–1799) reply in the Nouvelles Recherches sur les découvertes microscopiques et la génération des corps organisés (Needham 1769), but he cites in particular the more recent contributions of Carl August Sigismund Schultze (1795– 1877) and Christian Gottfried Ehrenberg (1795–1876).

  8. In fact, apart from the Kantian definition of organic body present in section 65 of the Kritik der Urteilskraft (Kant 1968, V, pp. 372–376), which he endorsed, Müller’s position was very different from Kant’s, for he would not distinguish, as Kant had done, between a legitimate reflective and regulative use of teleology in accounting for organic formative processes, and an undue appeal to causal efficient vital forces reaching beyond the limits of mechanistic explanations of physiological phenomena. On this account, full credit should not be granted to Timothy Lenoir’s interpretation (Lenoir 1982, pp. 140–155; Zammito 2012).

  9. On the varieties of vitalist traditions, and the diverse meaning of appeals to explanatory vital principles or forces, several studies can be relied on (Cimino and Duchesneau 1997; Nouvel 2011; Normandin and Wolfe 2013).

  10. On the specificity of the reference to vital force in Müller, see Florey (1995).

References

  • Balan, B. (1979). Organisation, organisme, économie et milieu chez Henri Ducrotay de Blainville. Revue d’histoire des sciences, 32(1), 5–24.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bernard, C. (1966). Leçons sur les phénomènes de la vie communs aux végétaux et aux animaux. Paris: Vrin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Blumenbach, J. F. (1781). Ueber den Bildungstrieb und das Zeugungsgeschäfte. Göttingen: J. C. Dieterich.

    Google Scholar 

  • Blumenbach, J. F. (1789). Zwo Abhandlungen über die Nutritionskraft welche von der Kayserlichen Academie der Wissenschaften in St. Petersburg den Preis getheilt erhalten haben. Die erste von Herrn Hofrath Blumenbach, die zwote von Herrn Prof. Born. Nebst einer fernern Erläuterung eben derselben Materie, von C. F. Wolff. St. Petersburg: Kayserliche Akademie der Wissenschaften.

  • Brooke, J. H. (1968). Wöhler’s urea and its vital force? A verdict from the chemists. Ambix, 15, 84–114.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cimino, G., & Duchesneau, F. (Eds.). (1997). Vitalisms from Haller to the Cell theory. Firenze: Leo S. Olschki.

    Google Scholar 

  • Clauzade, L. (2009). L’Organe de la pensée. Biologie et philosophie chez Auguste Comte. Besançon: Presses universitaires de Franche-Comté.

    Google Scholar 

  • Clauzade, L. (2012). La théorie cérébrale d’un naturaliste spiritualiste Henri-Marie Ducrotay de Blainville. Revue d’histoire des Sciences, 65(2), 237–257.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • de Blainville, H. D. (1833). Cours de physiologie générale et comparée. Paris: Germer-Baillière.

    Google Scholar 

  • Duchesneau, F. (1987). Genèse de la théorie cellulaire. Paris: Vrin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Duchesneau, F. (2014). Blumenbach on teleology and the laws of vital organization. Verifiche, 43(1–3), 113–135.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dutrochet, H. (1826). L’Agent immédiat du mouvement vital dans sa nature et dans son mode d’action chez les végétaux et chez les animaux. Paris: J.-B. Baillière.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ehrenberg, C. G. (1838). Die Infusionsthierchen als vollkommene Organismen. Leipzig: L. Voss.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Florey, E. (1995). Energiekonzepte und Vitalismus nach Johannes Müller. In H. J. Sandkühler (Ed.), Interaktionen zwischen Philosophie und empirischen Wissenschaften: Philosophie und Wissenschaftsgeschichte zwischen Francis Bacon und Ernst Cassirer (pp. 189–210). Frankfurt am Main: Lang.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kant, I. (1968). Kants Werke. Akademie-Ausgabe. Berlin: Walter de Gruyter.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lenoir, T. (1982). The Strategy of Life: Teleology and Mechanics in Nineteenth Century German Biology. Dordrecht: Reidel.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lohff, B. (1978). Johannes Müllers Rezeption der Zellentheorie in seinem Handbuch der Physiologie des Menschen. Medizinhistorisches Journal, 13, 247–258.

    Google Scholar 

  • Magendie, F. (1809). Quelques idées générales sur les phénomènes particuliers aux corps vivants. Bulletin des sciences médicales, 4, 145–170.

    Google Scholar 

  • McLaughlin, P. (1982). Blumenbach und der Bildungstrieb. Medizinhistorisches Journal, 17, 357–372.

    Google Scholar 

  • Müller, J. P. (1834–1838). Handbuch der Physiologie des Menschen für Vorlesungen. Coblenz: J. Holscher.

  • Müller, J. P. (1838). Ueber den feinern Bau und die Formen der krankhaften Geschwülste. Berlin: Reimer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Müller, J. P. (1842). Elements of Physiology, transl. William Baly. London: Taylor and Walton.

    Google Scholar 

  • Müller, J. P. (1851). Manuel de physiologie, trad. A. J. L. Jourdan. Paris: J.-B. Baillière.

  • Needham, J. T. (1750). Nouvelles Recherches microscopiques. Paris: L. E. Ganeau.

  • Needham, J. T. (1769). Nouvelles Recherches sur les découvertes microscopiques et sur la génération des corps organisés. Paris: Lacombe.

    Google Scholar 

  • Normandin, S., & Wolfe, C. (2013). Vitalism and the Scientific Image in Post-Enlightenment Life Science, 1800–2010. Dordrecht: Springer.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Nouvel, P. (dir.). (2011). Repenser le vitalisme. Histoire et philosophie du vitalisme. Paris: Presses Universitaires de France.

  • Rather, L. J. (1978). The Genesis of Cancer. A Study in the History of Ideas. Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Reil, J. C. (1910). Von der Lebenskraft. Leipzig: J. A. Barth.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rey, R. (2000). Naissance et développement du vitalisme en France de la deuxième moitié du 18 e siècle à la fin du Premier Empire. Oxford: Voltaire Foundation.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rudolphi, C. A. (1807). Anatomie der Pflanzen. Berlin: Myliussische Buchhandlung.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schultze, C. A. S. (1828). Mikroskopische Untersuchungen über des Herrn Robert Brown’s Entdeckung lebender, selbst im Feuer unzerstörbarer Theilchen in allen Körpern und über Erzeugung der Monaden. Carlsruhe: Herder.

  • Schwann, T. (1839). Mikroskopische Untersuchungen über die Uebereinstimmung in der Struktur und dem Wachstum der Thiere und Pflanzen. Berlin: Sander'schen Buchhandlung.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schwann, T. (1847). Microscopical Researches into the Accordance in the Structure and Growth of Animals and Plants. London: Sydenham Society.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stahl, G. E. (1708). Theoria medica vera. Halle: Literis Orpĥanotrophei.

    Google Scholar 

  • von Baer, C. E. (1828). Ueber Entwickelungsgeschichte der Thiere. Königsberg: Beobachtungen und Reflexionen.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wöhler, F. (1828). Ueber künstliche Bildung des Harnstoffs. Annalen der Physik und Chemie, 88(2), 253–256.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Zammito, J. H. (2012). The Lenoir thesis revisited: Blumenbach and Kant. Studies in the History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences, 43, 120–132.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to François Duchesneau.

Additional information

This paper is part of the topical collection “Organic/Organization/Organism. Essays in the history and philosophy of chemistry and biology.”

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Duchesneau, F. Laws of organization and chemical analysis: Blainville and Müller. HPLS 38, 20 (2016). https://doi.org/10.1007/s40656-016-0122-1

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s40656-016-0122-1

Keywords

Navigation