Skip to main content
Log in

The Philosophy of Biomimicry

  • Research Article
  • Published:
Philosophy & Technology Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

The philosophy of biomimicry, I argue, consists of four main areas of inquiry. The first, which has already been explored by Freya Mathews (2011), concerns the “deep” question of what Nature ultimately is. The second, third, and fourth areas correspond to the three basic principles of biomimicry as laid out by Janine Benyus (1997). “Nature as model” is the poetic principle of biomimicry, for it tells us how it is that things are to be “brought forth” (poiēsis). “Nature as measure” is the ethical principle of biomimicry, for it tells us that Nature places ethical limits or standards on what it is possible for us to accomplish. And “Nature as mentor” is the epistemological principle of biomimicry, for it affirms that Nature is the ultimate source of truth, wisdom, and freedom from error. Within this overall framework, I argue that seeing Nature as physis—understood as “self-production” or “self-placing-into-the-open”—constitutes the requisite ground for the poetic, ethical, and epistemological principles of biomimicry, and that biomimicry thus conceived involves a new philosophical paradigm, which I call “enlightened naturalism”.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. See Lepora et al. (2013) for an attempt to quantify this “surge of interest” within scientific publications.

  2. Interestingly, it is certainly not out of the question to imitate or draw inspiration from these organisms so as to generate energy and capture valuable materials from hydrothermal vents.

  3. Mathews also attributes the faculty of “willing” to autopoietic entities other than biological individuals, such as rivers, hence her argument that we need to ask such questions as “what does the river want us to desire?” and then to adapt ourselves accordingly (Mathews 2011, 16).

  4. This is not to say that mutatis mutandis, Mathew’s principle of least resistance could not potentially be integrated into the theoretical framework of the present article, most obviously with respect to the final section of the article (Nature as mentor), where I discuss the question of cooperation.

  5. The same is also true of quantum mechanics.

  6. See Fukuyama (1993) for an analysis of the role progress in physics has played in the spread of liberal democracy.

  7. In La Nouvelle Alliance (1986), for example, Ilya Prigogine and Isabelle Stengers explicitly argue that thanks in large part to non-equilibrium thermodynamics the physical sciences are in the process of rediscovering physis.

  8. An important example of this is D’Arcy Wentworth Thompson’s On Growth and Form (1961)—widely regarded as an important precursor to biomimicry—which analyses in considerable detail how such universal physical laws as gravity affect the form of both living beings and artefacts.

  9. In keeping with Maturana and Varela’s view that autopoiesis is the defining characteristic of “life”, it is generally argued that anything else that is autopoietic is also “alive”. If, however, one equates autopoiesis not with life, but rather with Nature in the sense of physis, it is possible to see certain ecological and physical phenomena as autopoietic without considering them “alive”.

  10. This is in keeping both with Foucault’s remark that “knowledge is not made for understanding; it is made for cutting” (Foucault 1984, 88), but also with the etymology of the word “science”, a word which originally meant “cutting”.

  11. It is interesting to note that both Benyus and Forbes, the authors of the two most important books to date on biomimicry and bio-inspiration, both have backgrounds in literature or poetry. Benyus has a degree in English literature and Forbes has worked as editor of the Poetry Review and also edited Scanning the Century: The Penguin Book of the Twentieth Century in Poetry. In keeping with this, both authors regularly evoke the “poetry” of Nature.

  12. This claim is significantly complicated by Aristotle’s argument that all change—including the “self-changing” of living beings—can ultimately be traced back to an “unmoved mover” or “unchanging changer” (see Aristotle 2000), and that this primary entity constitutes a “model” imitated by the celestial cycles, which are themselves a “model” imitated by the cycle of the seasons, themselves a model for the circular generation of living beings (see Aubenque 1962, 497–502). One plausible explanation for these complications is Heidegger’s claim that Aristotle’s thought is situated at a historical crossroads between the original Pre-Socratic understanding of Being or Nature as physis qua “self-generation” or “self-placing-into-appearance” and the metaphysical tradition, which originates primarily with Plato (Heidegger 1998).

  13. According to Richard Capobianco, Heidegger himself thought that we should take physis as measure. Indeed, Capobianco even goes so far as to claim that “[t]he core matter for Heidegger—and for those inclined to his thinking—is that physis is the measure, not Dasein.” (Capobianco 2014, 63)

  14. There are certain exceptions to this rule, such as junk or harmful DNA, but these are necessarily exceptions, for once they rise beyond a certain critical threshold they will destroy the autopoietic entity in which they reside. A similar point goes for the linear, extractive technologies of contemporary humans. It is the scale at which they operate which explains their destructiveness.

  15. There is no suggestion in their text that Braungart and McDonough chose the example of the cherry tree because of the role it has played in the history of philosophy. Indeed, the choice would appear to be entirely serendipitous.

References

  • Aristotle. (1996). Poetics. Trans. M. Heath. London: Penguin.

  • Aristotle. (2000). Physics. Trans. R. Waterfield. Oxford: OUP.

  • Aubenque, P. (1962). Le problème de l’être chez Aristote. Paris: PUF.

    Google Scholar 

  • Auerbach, E. (1953). Mimesis: the representation of reality in Western literature. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Benyus, J. (1997). Biomimicry: innovation inspired by nature. New York: Harper Perennial.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bowler, P. (2009). Evolution: the history of an idea. Berkeley and Los Angeles: University of California Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Braungart, M., & McDonough, W. (2009). Cradle to cradle: re-making the way we make things. London: Vintage.

    Google Scholar 

  • Capobianco, R. (2014). Heidegger’s way of being. Toronto: University of Toronto Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Capra, F. (1997). The web of life. London: Harper Collins.

    Google Scholar 

  • Commoner, B. (1971). The closing circle: nature, man, and technology. New York: Alfred Knopf.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dawkins, R. (1989). The selfish gene. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dicks, H. (2011). The self-poetizing earth: Heidegger, Santiago theory, and Gaia theory. Environmental Philosophy, 8(1), 41–61.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dicks, H. (2014). Aldo Leopold and the ecological imaginary: the balance, the pyramid, and the round river. Environmental Philosophy, 11(2), 175–209.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Feuerbach, L. (1843). Principles of the philosophy of the future. Resource Document. Marxist Internet Archive. https://www.marxists.org/reference/archive/feuerbach/works/future/future0.htm. Accessed 05 August 2015.

  • Forbes, P. (2005). The gecko’s foot: bio-inspiration—engineered from nature. London: Fourth Estate.

    Google Scholar 

  • Foucault, M. (1979). What is an author? In J. V. Harari (Ed.), Textual strategies: perspectives in poststructuralist criticism (pp. 141–160). Ithaca: Cornell University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Foucault, M. (1984). Nietzsche, genealogy, history. In P. Rabinow (Ed.), The Foucault Reader (pp. 76–100). New York: Pantheon.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fournier, M. (2011). Quand la nature inspire la science : Histoire des inventions humaines qui imitent les plantes et les animaux. Toulouse: Editions Plume de Carotte.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fukuyama, F. (1993). The end of history and the last man. New York: Avon Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Girard, R. (1978). Des choses cachées depuis la fondation du monde. Paris: Editions Grasset et Fasquelle.

    Google Scholar 

  • Harman, J. (2013). The shark’s paintbrush: biomimicry and how nature is inspiring innovation. Ashland: White Cloud Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Heidegger, M. (1993). The question concerning technology. In D. F. Krell (Ed.), Basic writings (pp. 311–341). Oxford: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Heidegger, M. (1995). Being and time. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Heidegger, M. (1998). On the essence and concept of physis in Aristotle’s Physics B, 1. In W. McNeill (Ed.), Pathmarks (pp. 183–230). Cambridge: CUP.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Heidegger, M. (2000). Introduction to metaphysics. Yale: Yale University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kant, I. (1988). Fundamental principles of the metaphysic of morals. New York: Prometheus.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kauffman, S. (1995). At home in the universe: the search for the laws of self-organization and complexity. Oxford: OUP.

    Google Scholar 

  • Latour, B. (1999). Politiques de la nature: Comment faire entrer les sciences en démocratie. Paris: Editions la Découverte.

    Google Scholar 

  • Latour, B. (2011). Pasteur: guerre et paix des microbes, suivi de Irréductions. Paris: Editions la Découverte.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lepora, N. F., Verschure, P., & Prescott, T. J. (2013). The state of the art in biomimetics. Bioinspiration and Biomimetics. doi:10.1088/1748-3182/8/1/013001.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lovelock, J. (2014). A rough ride to the future. London: Allen Lane.

    Google Scholar 

  • Margulis, L. (1998). The symbiotic planet: a new look at evolution. London: Weidenfeld and Nicolson.

    Google Scholar 

  • Margulis, L., & Sagan, D. (1995). What is life? Berkeley and Los Angeles: University of California Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Marx, K. (1977). The German ideology. In D. McLellan (Ed.), Karl Marx’s selected writings (pp. 159–191). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mathews, F. (1991). The ecological self. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mathews, F. (2011). Towards a deeper philosophy of biomimicry (pre-publication version), Organization & Environment, 24(4). Resource Document. http://www.freyamathews.net/downloads/Biomimicry.pdf. Accessed 26 May 2015.

  • Maturana, H., & Varela, F. (1980). Autopoiesis and cognition: the realization of the living. Dordrecht: Reidel.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Miller, P. (2010). Smart swarm. London: Harper Collins.

    Google Scholar 

  • Morin, E. (1977). La méthode: Tome 1, la nature de la nature. Paris: Editions du Seuil.

    Google Scholar 

  • Morton, T. (2009). Ecology without nature: rethinking environmental aesthetics. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Myers, W. (2014). Biodesign: nature, science, creativity. London: Thames and Hudson.

    Google Scholar 

  • Papanek, V. (1985). Design for the real world: human ecology and social change. London: Thames and Hudson.

    Google Scholar 

  • Plato. (1941). The republic. Trans. B. Jowett. New York: The Modern Library.

  • Prigogine, I., & Stengers, I. (1986). La nouvelle alliance. Paris: Gallimard.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ricoeur, P. (1983). Temps et récit: Tome 1, l’intrigue et le récit historique. Paris: Editions du Seuil.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rorty, R. (1991). Objectivity, relativism, and truth: philosophical papers (Vol. 1). Cambridge: CUP.

    Google Scholar 

  • Serres, M. (1977). La naissance de la physique dans le texte de Lucrèce : fleuves et turbulences. Paris: Editions du Minuit.

    Google Scholar 

  • Thompson, D. W. (1961). On growth and form. Cambridge: CUP.

    Google Scholar 

  • Todd, N. J., & Todd, J. (1993). From ecocities to living machines: principles of ecological design. Berkeley: North Atlantic Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Varela, F., Thompson, E., & Rosch, E. (1993). The embodied mind: cognitive science and human experience. Cambridge: The MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Vincent, J. F., Bogatyreva, O. A., Bogatyrev, N. R., Bowyer, A., & Pahl, A. K. (2006). Biomimetics: its practice and theory. Journal of the Royal Society Interface. doi:10.1098/rsif.2006.0127.

    Google Scholar 

  • Vogel, S. (2000). Cats’ paws and catapults: mechanical worlds of people and nature. New York: W.W. Norton.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wahl, D.C. (2006). Bionics vs biomimicry: From control of nature to sustainable participation in nature. WIT Transactions on Ecology and the Environment, Vol 87, doi: 10.2495/DN060281.

Download references

Acknowledgments

I would like to thank the LabEx IMU (Intelligence des Mondes Urbains) of the University of Lyon for funding the post-doctoral fellowship on “biomimetic cities” within which this research was carried out.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Henry Dicks.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Dicks, H. The Philosophy of Biomimicry. Philos. Technol. 29, 223–243 (2016). https://doi.org/10.1007/s13347-015-0210-2

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s13347-015-0210-2

Keywords

Navigation