1 Introduction

These days, abolitionists like to speak at the level of grand idealizations. Consider, for instance, Dylan Rodríguez’s declaration: “Abolition is a dream toward futurity vested in insurgent, counter-Civilizational histories—genealogies of collective genius that perform liberation under conditions of duress.”Footnote 1 Or take Dorothy Roberts’s description: “Abolitionists are engaged in a collective project of radical speculative imagination.”Footnote 2 Or consider also Amna Akbar’s argument for “an abolitionist horizon,”Footnote 3 which takes as its starting point “a bold vision, grounded in the Black freedom struggle, for a radically different world.”Footnote 4 These sorts of abstractions are meant to provide a vision of radical social movements’ claim for abolition to guide change. But talk of “dreams,” “imaginations,” and “horizons” also brings to mind something different than the reality on the ground and masks prevailing problems within our system of policing.Footnote 5

What’s more is that this idealized discourse comes at a moment when political philosophers are growing increasingly skeptical of abstracting away from the intricacies of our current legal and political systems.Footnote 6 Focusing on political ideals is thought to distort the non-ideal features of our current society. And attempting to apply these political ideals to real-world circumstances is alleged to be imprudent. Footnote 7 Indeed, for many, the term “ideal theory” has been used to signify “useless, unrealistic, naïve, utopian—perhaps even ideological or dangerous—currents in contemporary political philosophy.”Footnote 8 Untenable visions about a radically different future, these theorists claim, have no proper place in theorizing about injustice.

To be clear, I’m not invested in whether views of police abolitionism as put forward by contemporary abolitionists constitute an “ideal theory.” As recent theorists have pointed out, the current debate about the ideal/non-ideal theory distinction “has reached dizzying heights of conceptual sophistication”Footnote 9 and what the labels “ideal” and “non-ideal” mean in this debate is “far from clear.”Footnote 10 Moreover, because there is a wide range of how one idealizes in normative theory, the ranked, categorical distinction that has become popular in political philosophy may be more properly characterized as a spectrum.Footnote 11 We should not, then, get too caught up in disputes about what counts as “ideal theory” here. What’s important for us is the strand of that debate which warns against the misuses of idealizations. Rather than using the phrase “ideal theory” to dismiss a position as utopian, the task of a theorist is to figure out which idealizations are being made, whether they are misleading, and whether the idealization could be counterproductive to achieving the desired state of affairs. This will be my focus.

In what follows, I point out some problems with the use of idealizations in recent abolitionist discourse.Footnote 12 My hope is that by getting a handle on how contemporary police abolitionists use idealizations, we might better understand the merits of the position being advanced. The problem is not that abolitionists invoke unreal idealizations per se. The problems are (a) that they have not done much to guard against objectionable forms of idealizations that hinder the abolitionist project and (b) that they have failed to tell us how to correctly use idealizations to advance our current state of policing. At bottom, my worry is that idealizations used by abolitionists are inconsistent with their activist agenda.Footnote 13 What abolitionists are doing is not merely a philosophical exploration of the issues. Instead, their activist position aims at providing proposals that would be beneficial to our present society.Footnote 14 By over-emphasizing the imaginative aspect of their project and underplaying the existing barriers to achieving their ideal, police abolitionists have done little to move us toward practical solutions to fix our broken system of policing.

2 What Police Abolition is not

Before highlighting the idealized discourse in abolitionist thought, we should clarify some common confusion about the abolitionist project. An obvious way to understand abolition is as a call for the immediate and unconditional end to something that is problematic. The slave abolition movement was about the immediate and unconditional termination of slavery.Footnote 15 The death penalty abolitionist movement calls for the immediate and unconditional end to state administered killings.Footnote 16 When something is unequivocally evil, and serves no good societal function, it cannot be put to any just use—and should be terminated straightaway.Footnote 17

Most contemporary police abolitionists don’t quite view things this way. This is partly because police actually do perform valuable societal functions. Even communities that fear the police often rely on police services. Indeed, the neighborhoods most subject to police violence are often the heaviest users of police services because they have few other resources.Footnote 18 Although police often do not do their job well, abolitionists appear to recognize that the most vulnerable in our society would be worse off even if we immediately and unconditionally dismantled them. Abolishing the police, say many abolitionists, does not mean an immediate destruction of police departments that would leave our communities vulnerable to violence.Footnote 19

But rejecting the immediate destruction of police isn’t merely about protecting the vulnerable from violence. Nor is it a concession to those who criticize the abolitionist’s focus on an institution resistant to political change. When abolitionists acknowledge that the destruction of police departments is inadequate, they are highlighting the shortcomings of a purely negative approach to abolition. Abolition is about more than destroying. For abolition to be successful, there must also be a positive mission to accompany the negative task. Contemporary abolitionists are quick to point out that the abolition project is not “a negative vision of abolition (i.e. fire all cops),” but rather a project aimed at “the creation of new non-police institutions empowered to supersede the police monopoly on violence reduction.”Footnote 20 The basic idea here is straightforward: in order for abolition to be workable, new institutions have to be introduced to incorporate the least well off into the social order. Indeed, some abolitionists go so far as to dismiss the negative project altogether and declare that “[w]e should understand abolition not as the ‘elimination of anything but…as the grounding of a new society.’”Footnote 21 Abolition, then, is not (merely) about abolition. It is about constructing new institutions to replace an old social order.

This point also shows why the contemporary abolitionists should not be grouped with libertarian or conservative theories advocating for a smaller state. There’s a long-standing libertarian tradition of advocating that the police function, much like everything else, should be privately provided—and, thus, we should abolish the public police force as we know it.Footnote 22 And some of the dialogue around policing these last few years has encouraged efforts by right-leaning organizations seeking support for establishing a smaller state footprint.Footnote 23 But the abolitionist I have in mind is not going to get on board with these types of programs. Rather than demanding something less from the state, the contemporary abolitionist is demanding something different.Footnote 24 As Akbar puts it, “[d]emands to divest from police and prisons are often accompanied by demands to invest in social provision and collective care: for example, housing, health care, and education. By demanding investments, these campaigns suggest alternate modes that the state can take to respond to all manner of currently criminalized social problems.”Footnote 25 On this view, government intervention is not the problem—the problem is the way the government intervenes. And the hope is that by divesting from policing resources we will open up opportunities for the state to invest in more equitable projects.Footnote 26 So, contrary to what is sometimes believed, what the contemporary abolitionist is striving for is unrelated to the projects by those seeking a minimal state.Footnote 27 Just as abolition is not a negative project to get rid of police immediately, it is also not a project geared at reducing government influence in our lives.

3 What is Police Abolitionism?

Understanding those features about the contemporary abolitionist helps clarify some things. We know that contemporary abolitionists are not merely putting forth a negative project that requires the immediate and unconditional destruction of police departments. We also know that they are not advancing a position that requires us to minimize the state’s presence in our lives. But, of course, that doesn’t tell us exactly what police abolition is. Defenders of police are quick to deride abolitionists as being unable to offer an alternative where the public feels safe.Footnote 28 And abolitionists cannot simply shrug off complaints about safety and carry on with their critique.

Nor do they want to. As the abolitionist writer Derecka Purnell puts it: “When people dismiss abolitionists for not caring about victims or safety, they tend to forget that we are those victims, those survivors of violence.”Footnote 29 Abolitionists want us to broaden our understanding of what makes us safe and question our reliance on police to perform the task.Footnote 30 To the abolitionist, policing in the United States is an extension of racialized chattel slavery that continues to keep Black people in their place in a racial capitalist society.Footnote 31 The task of the abolitionist is to situate police within our general history of racialized violence and advance demands for more equitable alternatives.Footnote 32

Yet this restatement doesn’t tell us exactly what police abolition is. It’s tough to get on board with a view that doesn’t provide a structured and clear vision of a radical change. Yes, the United States has a policing problem. Yes, fatal violence by the police is much more common in this country than other developed nations.Footnote 33 And, yes, disproportionate policing of marginalized communities creates and maintains concentrated inequality.Footnote 34 Most of us know this. And knowledge of these facts partly explains why a majority of Americans now report that our system of policing needs “major changes,” while only 6 percent say that no changes are needed at all.Footnote 35 The current support for change in policing is unprecedented.

Yet there remains relatively little support for abolition.Footnote 36 Part of this is, no doubt, because of confusion about what abolition is. It’s easy to knock down a cartoon version of the phrase “abolish the police.” And, even among those who are sympathetic to the movement, there is divergent opinion about what the phrase means.Footnote 37 Some abolitionists go so far as to claim that “abolition may mean different things in different contexts.”Footnote 38 Others provide an anxiety-producing conception that makes abolitionism a hard position to pin down. Here’s Dylan Rodríguez:

Now and long before, abolition is and was a practice, an analytical method, a present-tense visioning, an infrastructure in the making, a creative project, a performance, a counterwar, an ideological struggle, a pedagogy and curriculum, an alleged impossibility that is furtively present, pulsing, produced in the persistent insurgencies of human being that undermine the totalizing logics of empire, chattel, occupation, heteropatriarchy, racial-colonial genocide, and Civilization as a juridical-narrative epoch.Footnote 39

Perhaps abolition is all those things to some. But I find it hard to understand—better yet scrutinize—all those ideas at once. Rattled off opinions about a moving target are unlikely to help the cause of fixing our broken system of policing. There’s no hope for a discourse of police abolitionism where the concept takes on so many positions.

But we needn’t get caught up in the many things that abolition could be. Even while recognizing the elusiveness of the position, most abolitionists acknowledge that there are general ideas embraced by many contemporary proponents of the position.Footnote 40 Two stand out. First, because the precursors to our current system of policing were slave patrols that surveilled Black people, any attempt at reform is futile—it would be senseless to expect our current police forces to be rid of racism against Black people.Footnote 41 As an evolution of these slave patrols, policing cannot be reformed.

It would be inaccurate, though, to suggest that slave patrols were the precursor to all modern police forces in the United States. The historical picture is much more intricate with the police taking many forms across space and time. Some historians suggest that three central frames explain the role of police in early American life: capitalism, racism, and xenophobia. Footnote 42 The police developed differently in different places partly to accommodate the demands of those in positions of power. Understanding the police as a form of class control in northern cities, and as a tool for settler colonialism in western cities, may be just as informative in understanding how police forms developed in response to social powers as understanding the role of police as slave patrols in southern and middle-ground cities.

Moreover, we should be careful of arguments that extract the current value of something based on its historical origin. We don’t reject a ban on smoking cigarettes in public just because Nazi Germany was the first to implement such a ban.Footnote 43 And it’s not appropriate to dismiss political positions simply because they were originally advanced by a hated politician. If we have independent reasons to believe that smoking in public is harmful, or that the political position is a reasonable one to adopt, then the origin of the position becomes less important. The so-called genetic fallacy warns against discrediting a theory, experience, or point of view simply based on its origin or originator.Footnote 44

Second, contemporary abolitionists appeal to idealizations to show the appeal of their position. I mentioned earlier that the abolitionist project is no longer framed merely as a negative project (“get rid of all cops”). It is instead based on a positive project aimed at creating “new non-police institutions.”Footnote 45 The use of idealizations to describe the positive project of abolition is a ubiquitous—yet overlooked—feature of contemporary abolitionist discourse. And these idealizations are often used to get around objections to the abolitionist position. For instance, when told that abolishing the police would leave the vulnerable worse off, the abolitionist tells us that abolition applies when favorable conditions are present that would make the police “obsolete.”Footnote 46 Or, when told that we would never reach a state where the police departments are completely eradicated, abolitionists suggest that we treat the abolitionist ideal as an endpoint that we should try to approximate.Footnote 47 Sometimes, abolitionists are reluctant to say what positive responses would be needed in this idealized state. Though the abolitionist ideal is a society without police, they claim that to make it easier to understand the kinds of alternative responses that are needed we must first remove police from our communities.Footnote 48 Even when acknowledging this paradoxical position, the recommendation from abolitionists remains the same: take incremental steps to abolish the police, even if it won’t occur in our lifetime.Footnote 49

These examples aren’t all that’s out there. The champions of contemporary abolitionism enthusiastically encourage us to use our radical speculative imagination.Footnote 50 And once we start to use our imagination, it takes us many places. Abolitionism has become a position where grand idealizations are meant to guide us to a better future, and the presence of these idealizations permeates abolition talk.

The puzzle here, though, is that contemporary abolitionism is also, primarily, an activist stance—it’s a call for us to engage with the realities of a racist, violent, and destructive system that is resistant to change. A common belief among political philosophers concerned with these same issues is that gross idealizations help ground oppressive social relations and obstruct progress for racial minorities and other subjugated groups.Footnote 51 Indeed, some theorists have claimed that the “ideal society approach” is representative of a conservative platform that abstains from more progressive remedies to injustice.Footnote 52 For this reason, one may not expect to find such ideals in discourse guiding a radical social movement. The abstractions that have become common in abolitionist discourse may distort the actual problems in our system of policing.

If we conclude that these idealizations are central to the abolitionist picture, does it follow that the position could be dismissed as excessively utopian—and, hence, not helpful for an activist agenda? Not quite. Again, abolitionism is primarily an activist position. And even while encouraging us to use our imagination, abolitionists are careful to point out that they are not “naïve dreamers.”Footnote 53 The abolitionist aims to ground their position in actual experience. Indeed, abolitionists criticize conventional accounts of “legal justice” for speaking in idealized terms that are at odds with actual legal processes.Footnote 54 Though an idealized version of our constitutional rights seems to provide protection, see what happens when one gets stopped by a police officer who discovers a warrant from an unpaid parking ticket.Footnote 55 Sure, abolitionism is “committed to a set of ideals.”Footnote 56 But these ideals are meant to guide the practical.

Maybe that solves the puzzle. But I still can’t shake the feeling that some of the grand idealizations in abolitionist discourse disserve the position. So far, I have only gestured at ways that idealizations could be counterproductive to achieving practical solutions. The account of abolition discussed in the last two sections is an attractive position when you consider it as a dualistic picture guided by ideals to end a system partly linked to slave patrols. It is less attractive when we look at the objectionable forms of idealization attached to the abolitionist project and see the ways that they could be counterproductive in practice. So, let’s take a closer look at these idealizations in the next section.

4 The Ideal of Police Abolition

My focus is on how abolitionism guides us in solving our current problems of policing rather than whether the idealizations they invoke adequately depict a just society. Is it a given that an ideal society would be a policeless society? Not really. But it seems to be a common assumption. Some theorists deny that an ideal society would have a need for the police, or even criminal justice in general.Footnote 57 The thought here is that idealized societies provide no means for governmental figures to administer justice. As James Madison notoriously declared, “If men were angels, no government would be necessary.”

Still, it’s a debatable assumption. Given our limitations as humans, it is possible that morally perfect people would have good-faith disagreements about issues of moral concern.Footnote 58 It seems possible that some of those disagreements exist in the criminal realm. And societies that attempt to eradicate harmful conduct entirely may only be able to do so by having us give up individual liberties.Footnote 59 At least, this seems to be the lesson of various science fiction books and movies. Rather than utopias, crimeless societies often appear as dystopias where there is no room for individual choice.Footnote 60 And societies that adopt a treatment ideology to deal with wrongdoing appear as paternalistic societies that treat autonomous beings as patients.Footnote 61 Does any of this mean that police must be the ones that respond to the harmdoing? Not quite. Abolitionists have thoughts about the right people to address these harms, and perhaps this project could be put forward without violating our basic liberties. Still, it’s worth acknowledging that a society in which police are obsolete may not be as utopian as some initially make it out to seem. More should be said about why an ideal society would be a policeless one. (But I won’t be the one to say much more about it here.)

Let’s also assume, then, that the abolitionist ideal of a policeless society is a worthy goal to pursue. I’m more interested in how we are meant to use this abolitionist ideal for guidance. Contemporary abolitionists seem to think that the abolitionist ideal offers a solid framework for pursuing practical projects. But I question whether this is true for three reasons.

One: Even if abolition is a desirable goal to pursue, we should be on guard for arguments suggesting that approximate, or second-best, arrangements are also desirable. Understandably, some abolitionists have taken a more cautious approach when advocating for permissible ways to fix the problems of policing in our society. Sometimes this appears as a straightforward endorsement of “partial abolition.” Eduardo Bautista Duran and Jonathan Simon, for instance, argue that “partial abolition” projects are an overlooked feature in abolitionist discourse—yet it could help make complete abolition more imaginable.Footnote 62 Other times it appears as theorists backtracking to criminal law minimalism when faced with the challenges of abolitionism.Footnote 63 And recently, many abolitionists have been advocating for “defunding the police” as a step toward abolition.Footnote 64 Indeed, some abolitionists suggest that we should pursue abolition even if we have no chance of ever achieving it.Footnote 65

At first glance, these positions appear unproblematic. When certain goals feel out of reach, it seems appropriate to think that a desirable outcome would be a feasible approximation of the goal. So, if we have this ideal of ridding the workplace of race-based discrimination, then a feasible approximation—say, significantly reducing racial discrimination—would be a desirable outcome if eradicating racial discrimination can’t yet be achieved.Footnote 66 Or, more simply: if you cannot submit your paper by the deadline, a desirable outcome would be to submit it as close to the deadline as possible. The further the submission is from the initial deadline, the less acceptable the tardiness may become. When we are unable to achieve our goals, regardless of how lofty, feasible approximations might seem like the next best thing. Even if we can’t reach the horizon, perhaps we should still get as high up on the hill as possible.

The problem with these partial abolitionist strategies, though, is that they risk leaving out a crucial element. As David Estlund reminds us, “a car with a missing brake pedal is approximately like a car with a brake pedal, but most of the value is missing.”Footnote 67 The theorem of the second best (or the fallacy of approximation) shows that there is no necessary connection between hitting some distant normative target and moving in its direction.Footnote 68 This is because the value contribution of any set of features may be dependent on other features that are not present. Thus, to use a popular example, one should not assume that taking two of three prescribed pills is better than taking one (or none). The chemical interaction of the pills may make it the case that taking two of the pills will cause your body to react in a way that is worse than if you had refrained from taking the pills altogether.Footnote 69

The question then becomes whether there are ways in which partial abolition could make things similarly worse off. One possibility is that abolitionists could succeed in eliminating target institutions but not in replacing them with the alternative institutions that they say are necessary for their transformative project.Footnote 70 As Christy Lopez puts it, “[o]fficials can answer calls to ‘defund the police’ and claim they are doing the people’s will without putting a penny into the services those same people are demanding.”Footnote 71 Indeed, that is what we already see occurring in some places.Footnote 72 Officials are merely following a common playbook in this country where they divest from a disputed function without reinvesting in the necessary resources.Footnote 73 Partial abolition would likely make things worse off if the abolished institutions are not replaced with the necessary substitutes.

Another possibility could be that, as critics of the defund movement have argued, reducing police funding in many municipalities would result in worse—not better—policing.Footnote 74 Abolitionists sometimes suggest that smaller police departments would lead to less violence. Mariame Kaba, for instance, notes “an immediate demand we can all make: Cut the number of police in half and cut their budget in half. Fewer police officers equals fewer opportunities for them to brutalize and kill people.”Footnote 75 But it’s not clear that a smaller police force means less police violence.Footnote 76 It could instead mean veteran officers fleeing and being replaced with officers who are overworked, underpaid, and underqualified.Footnote 77 Or it could mean that some police departments “make up for their inability to offer competitive wages and benefits by insulating officers from disciplinary oversight and accountability.”Footnote 78 Indeed, when Vallejo, California cut its budget in half after the financial crisis of 2008 we did not see police violence decrease. Instead, the number of fatal shootings by police (as well as other misconduct) drastically increased.Footnote 79 As one resident of Vallejo put it, “Do I really want a man or woman who’s worked 16 hours straight, with a gun in their hand, with state-sanctioned ability to take my life, who is tired—do I want that person authorized to police me?” The answer is obvious: no.

Treating partial abolition, then, as desirable because it approximates abolition may be counterproductive to abolitionists’ goals. It simply cannot be assumed that removing some obstacles without removing them all would improve matters. Indeed, given that contemporary abolitionism’s positive posture is based on lessons about what happens when the abolitionist ideal is not fully satisfied, it is surprising that so many abolitionists rely on approximation arguments.Footnote 80 If we are settling for a second-best scenario because the abolitionist horizon is unreachable, it might be better for us to get our heads out the clouds.

Two: Abolitionists ought to take more care in explaining the conditions of application of their view. Conditions of application are circumstances under which prescriptions hold.Footnote 81 If a view prescribes that “One ought to abide by the law if most of one’s fellow citizens comply with it,” then the duty to abide is conditional on circumstances of widespread compliance.Footnote 82 Without other’s compliance, the view does not give us much guidance on when, if ever, we should obey the law.

A similar lack of guidance is present within some abolitionists’ views. I mentioned earlier that many abolitionists do not just want to get rid of police—they want to make the police obsolete. In defending this position, abolitionists often speak of their project as one that defers the elimination of police until other substitutes are in place; in other words, we should get rid of all police departments, if the police are obsolete. Consider Mariame Kaba’s claim responding to the often-invoked criticism that immediate abolitionism would leave communities unsafe: “We are not abandoning our communities to violence. We don’t want to just close police departments. We want to make them obsolete.”Footnote 83 Rachel Herzing makes a similar statement: “[T]he only way to stop the violence of policing is to make the cops obsolete.”Footnote 84 But, strictly speaking, none of this tells us what we are required to do before the police are obsolete. Presumably, we would have in the back of our minds other institutions that would replace our current police forces. As one proponent of abolitionism puts it: “As we abolish policing, what we need to think about is what other systems we can put in place to make sure people are getting their needs met.”Footnote 85 Fair enough. But should we be doing more than thinking? Inaction is sometimes defended by abolitionists on the grounds that we need to remove police from our communities to make it easier to understand the kinds of alternative responses that are needed.Footnote 86 But then there’s a catch-22: we can’t get rid of the police until we succeed in replacing it with substitutes; but we can’t succeed in replacing it with substitutes until we get rid of the police.Footnote 87 Forms of idealization that condition police abolition on achieving a world that looks very different than ours does not provide sufficient guidance of what we should do before the radical changes to our basic structure are in place. And for those who think it’s appropriate to “build models today that can represent how we want to live in the future,”Footnote 88 see the perils of second-best and approximation arguments above.Footnote 89

Three: We should bear in mind the feasibility constraints in abolition discourse. This is not to suggest that every theory needs to be sensitive to the likelihood that it would be adopted. If a theory is purely evaluative, for instance, feasibility constraints may not be an adequate way to assess its validity. It’s no response to an evaluative theory to point out that persons won’t live up to their moral obligations. This is especially true if the demandingness of a theory is merely a by-product of people’s weakness of will or selfishness.Footnote 90 As David Estlund has argued, “ought implies can” does not mean “ought implies will.”Footnote 91

So, if abolitionism is merely meant to be evaluative—and not action-guiding—then feasibility insensitivity is irrelevant.Footnote 92 The ideal of abolition would be used as a criterion to assess the “badness” or “unjustness” of our current system of policing.

Yet mere evaluation is not the aim of abolitionists. Abolitionists are quick to point out that they are advancing “a strategy toward fundamental transformation.”Footnote 93 For the abolitionist, the ideal system of the police is none at all. “In this way,” Akbar tells us, “[abolition] invites a dialectical relationship between radical imagination and practical projects.”Footnote 94 And this makes sense. The theoretical argument for police abolition is meant to support a movement that is responding to the racist, violent, and other injustices in our system of policing. The motivation for the abolitionist ideal is not just to track the morally correct answer.

It seems wrong, then, to conclude that feasibility-sensitivity could be ignored by abolitionists. Abolitionists should not advance principles that are counterproductive if adopted as part of our existing institutions and laws. If one could predict harmful consequences or a greater lack of compliance from advancing a just position, one has reason to advance a modified version of that position. For instance, it could be true that in a just society the richest segment of the population is taxed at 70 percent.Footnote 95 Yet if one could foresee that such a tax rate would likely result in a significant amount of tax evasion, tax avoidance, and the wealthy relocating to places with a more favorable tax regime, then we have reason to tax the rich more modestly. Or, it could also be true, as Peter Singer has argued, that morality requires us to give away any surplus income to combat global poverty. But if the demandingness of this prescription would likely result in people not donating to reduce global poverty—or, even worse, if it is likely to lead to people ignoring the cause altogether—then we have reasons not to advance such an extreme request.

My point is merely that feasibility-sensitivity matters to positions that purport to be action-guiding.Footnote 96 Since abolitionism is primarily an activist position, it cannot over-rely on using idealizations to suggest a correct answer to what a system of policing looks like in a just society. As such, abolitionists need to say more about whether the ideal state of affairs they advocate for is not only possible, but also likely to happen. We can’t get on with imagining, envisaging, and dreaming without ever anchoring these aspirations to what people are likely to do on the ground.

5 Why not Repair?

For the reasons stated above, I do not think that the idealizations invoked in abolitionist discourse provide a solid framework for pursuing an activist agenda. Understanding the use, and misuse, of idealizations in abolitionist discourse helps us realize the ways in which the imaginative part of abolitionist discourse can be counterproductive to eradicating our current policing problems. Specifically, I have pointed out how the idealizations invoked by abolitionists risk being counterproductive with respect to abolitionists’ activist goals: they 1) suggest that if abolition is desirable, approximating abolition is also desirable; 2) fail to clarify what the condition of applications of their view is; and 3) operate without the feasibility-sensitivity that one should expect from a non-evaluative position. This is not to say that the abolitionist program is not amenable to developing an alternative framework that is less reliant on “radical speculative imagination.” But it does mean that the abolitionist’s own exposition of what they’d like to achieve has inherent problems that need to be resolved.

To be clear, when I advocate for a program less reliant on speculative imagination, I am not encouraging an excessive pragmatism that attracts as broad a basis of political support as possible. Even though a majority of the country agrees that policing needs “major changes,” the actual changes that tend to get broad support are those advancing community policing techniques or changing practices to establish greater accountability for the few “bad apples” that abuse their power.Footnote 97 These sorts of modifications don’t provide the substantive changes that abolitionists are interested in.

Instead, what I have in mind is a program that has desirable goals, clear applicability now, and sensitivity to feasibility constraints. One model for this could be based on repair. A repair agenda is sometimes rejected in abolitionist circles as inadequate because it purportedly ignores history and distracts from impactful work.Footnote 98 By centering repair, the argument goes, we are both assuming that the police could be fixed and tying up resources that could be spent toward solving other societal problems. As one community activist put it, “Our police is not working—we need to replace it with something new. It’s more than a repair.”Footnote 99 That more is usually abolition or transformation.

But there is no reason to think that a repair framework must rest on tossing money at police departments in order to solve our problems. There’s also no reason that the repair framework rests on repairing the police force that we currently have. The goal here is to repair our society, not (just) the police. To fix our problems, we have to go beyond policing. A reparative framework that focuses on eliminating oppression, establishing institutions that allow us to be treated as equal under the law, and creating a society where persons relate to each other as equals in their day-to-day lives would get us pretty close to eradicating a lot of the problems that concern abolitionists. An approach that centers repair, I would suggest, would be both more theoretically sound and politically effective than relying on imaginative thinking in the way that contemporary abolitionists seem to.

Sometimes, too, I get the sense that some activists would agree.Footnote 100 Though not as present as imaginative thinking, the notion of repair often makes its way into discourse criticizing police violence. For instance, when two activist groups in Chicago—Black People Against Police Torture and the National Conference of Black Lawyers—addressed systematic police torture, they “insisted on characterizing the relief sought as ‘reparations.’”Footnote 101 By centering reparation, the groups were able to call to mind “the racialized character of the violence.”Footnote 102 The notion of repair and reparation links the experience of police violence to the long legacies of racial violence in this country—and, thus, fits as a proper framework to incorporate our response to police violence.Footnote 103 The fit seems so natural that even those who criticize the repair agenda still invoke the concept when recommending solutions to our policing problems.Footnote 104 Critics seem to think that a reparative framework is inadequate. But maybe it is less so if we revise the target of repair to incorporate our broader relations with all social and political institutions in our society.

Does any of this mean that there is no room for imaginative thinking when discussing the problems of the oppressed? Not quite.Footnote 105 There’s something to be said for the imaginative approach in some instances. Advancing a long-term revolutionary vision could, among other things, help remind activists what they want to build—and not just what they want to knock down. My goal here is not to crush people’s dreams. And, I admit, I still find it somewhat hard to agree with Charles Mills’s claim that historically subordinated groups have always viewed “glittering ideals as remote and unhelpful.”Footnote 106 If anything, the opposite is closer to the truth. There is a long history of “escapism,” where historically subordinated groups used stories, games, and dreams to help manage their pain and oppression. And optimism about the future has appeared to be the go-to move for oppressed groups trying to envision a situation better than the one they currently face.Footnote 107 There are various examples in Black political thought: from Howard Thurman’s claim that you “never scale down your dreams to the level of that which is your immediate experience” to Barack Obama’s “audacity of hope” that is insistent upon us believing that “America can change” and working to reclaim “the American Dream.” Indeed, an appeal to glittering ideals arguably forms the heart of Martin Luther King’s “I Have a Dream” speech, which is today lauded as the high point of the civil rights movement and serves as a lesson on how to mobilize people to mitigate the causes of injustice.

But perhaps there is a different lesson that we can take. One of King’s main concerns was that America had defaulted on its “promissory note” that “all men—yes, black men as well as white men—would be guaranteed the unalienable rights of life, liberty, and the pursuit of happiness.” In a lesser-known sermon, King seems to become weary of relying on dreams: “Ultimately we all die not having received what was promised. Our dreams are constantly tossed and blown by staggering winds of disappointment.”Footnote 108 Still, he maintains his prophetic optimism, noting our “power to absorb the most excruciating pain without losing our sense of hope,”Footnote 109 and reminds the congregation that “God will take care of us.”Footnote 110 But what if we want to cash in that promissory note sooner? What do we say to the victim of police violence who follows Malcolm X and exclaims “I don’t see any American dream; I see an American nightmare”?Footnote 111 Smoothly murmuring “keep hope alive” and a pat on the back may get a sullen person through the day, but it isn’t the sort of thing that should guide a social movement. Right here, right now, there are problems of policing that need to be addressed. And some of these problems may be distorted by appealing to grand idealizations, or—as some have resorted to—analyzing dialogues with “a 49-year-old black man, self-described ‘Wakandan,’ from LA.”Footnote 112 But if abolitionists prefer to continue to focus on dreams, speculative imaginations, and horizons without appreciating their distorting effects, then so be it. They just shouldn’t be too surprised when those dreams are tossed and blown by the staggering winds of disappointment.