How objective is the notion of culpability? Suppose you think, as is common, that culpability is a matter of how poorly the actor engaged with the applicable reasons bearing on what to do.Footnote 1 Does this mean that the criminal law’s liability rules, if they are to reflect culpability in the way legal moralists think would be ideal,Footnote 2 should (or at least could) be concerned with all the specific motivations and individualized circumstances that led offenders to break the law? After all, such factors may have been a part of their actual engagement with reasons. However, this would sit uncomfortably with the common observation that criminal law doctrine (unlike sentencing) should abstract away from many sorts of individual circumstances and remain largely indifferent to one’s motivations for performing a criminal action (at least as the default position).Footnote 3

To capture the latter sort of view in a principled way (rather than merely seeing it as a result of practical limitations or compromises), in earlier work I defended an insufficient regard theory of criminal culpability that is more objective in certain respects than other views in the same tradition.Footnote 4 Insufficient regard views generally understand culpability in terms of one’s lack of due regard for, i.e. improper engagement with, the applicable reasons for action.Footnote 5 Rather than pegging culpability to the full level of insufficient regard that impelled the wrongdoer to act, I argued that it is better to take one’s level of culpability for an action to equal the degree of insufficient regard that the action manifests.Footnote 6

This, however, led Alec Walen to object that my view is too objective to be an account of criminal culpability and is better understood as a theory of criminal wrongs,Footnote 7 which tend to be understood in a more objective way.Footnote 8 This is an important challenge because it requires getting clearer about what wrongness and culpability are and what roles they are meant to play on a legal moralist picture of the criminal law. Still, I argue here that Walen’s objection ultimately is mistaken. Once we get clear on how wrongness and culpability are to be understood – though as criminal theorists we should ideally do this while remaining neutral on which substantive moral theory is correct – it becomes clear that my account is best seen as a theory of culpability. This is so even though the theory calculates degrees of culpability in a more objective way than other insufficient regard views.

The plan for this paper is as follows. Section 1 outlines what I take to be a fairly orthodox view among legal moralists about how wrongness and culpability are to be distinguished. This shows what theories of criminal wrongs or theories of culpability are supposed to be theories of. Section 2 motivates my Manifestation Account of criminal culpability and then presents Walen’s objection to it. Section 3 provides the core of my reply to Walen.

Finally, Sect. 4 moves beyond playing defense and aims to develop a more sophisticated version of the Manifestation Account. To help strengthen the case for thinking that the Manifestation Account is properly seen as a theory of culpability, I focus on the main area of criminal law doctrine where culpability comes apart from wrongness – namely, excuse cases. My earlier defense of the Manifestation Account is limited because it has nothing distinctive to say about the culpability of excused misconduct. Accordingly, the theory as presented earlier would be, if not outright false, at best incompatible with the orthodox view presented in Sect. 1, which takes excuses to accept wrongdoing but deny culpability. To solve this problem and enhance the theory’s explanatory value, Sect. 4 shows how to extend the Manifestation Account to account for the culpability of wrongs where a putatively excusing condition is in play. This not only fills a gap in the Manifestation Account but has the further benefit (explained in Sect. 5) of providing a unified reasons-based account of the main categories of misconduct in the criminal law, which shows what separates criminal wrongness from culpability both in justification cases and excuse cases. My aim through this discussion is to shed light on the distinct roles of wrongness and culpability in legal moralist theories of the criminal law and provide a better understanding of degrees of culpability of criminal wrongs – not only when justifications are at issue, but also when excuses are involved.

1 An Orthodox View of Wrongness and Culpability in Criminal Law

To set the stage, let me sketch what I take to be a fairly orthodox view of the role of wrongness and culpability in the criminal law. I won’t defend this view,Footnote 9 but merely introduce it to clarify the landscape against which the debate with Walen takes place. On this view, wrongness and culpability are distinct concepts with different roles to play in legislative decisions about which actions should be criminalized. Moral wrongness is a property of actions. To say an action is morally wrong is to say that it is decisively disfavored (or in some other binding sense not to be doneFootnote 10) by the full set of reasons that bear on how to behave under the circumstances according to the best moral theory.Footnote 11 Wrongness thus is about how strong the case in fact is against doing the action in question. Culpability (or equivalently moral blameworthiness) is a property of agents in respect of their actions. Culpability concerns not the actor’s character in general, but rather what one’s action says about how much lack of respect or concern for others (or their interests, rights or other important values) one acted with on the occasion in question. As Andrew Simester nicely puts it, culpability “arises not from doing the wrong thing, but from how D engages with the reasons why she ought not to have done it.”Footnote 12 In particular, “D becomes culpable for φ’ing when, in her engagement with the reasons she has not to φ, she was insufficiently motivated by – cared insufficiently about – the interests of others.”Footnote 13

This distinction between wrongness and culpability is typically thought to bear on the proper content of the criminal law in a number of ways. Most importantly, the orthodox view assumes that both the wrongness of some bit of conduct and its culpability are both, at the very least, requirements for properly criminalizing that conduct and making one who performs it liable to conviction (assuming no defense applies).Footnote 14 One might also think that wrongness or culpability, or perhaps both, are reasons that affirmatively support criminalization (perhaps only within the public sphere), although there is more debate about this claim.Footnote 15 I won’t assume this positive claim is necessarily a part of the orthodox view, though it can naturally supplement the negative constraints that will be the primary focus here. A further aspect of the orthodox view worth emphasizing is that justifications and excuses are also typically understood in terms of wrongness and culpability.Footnote 16 Justifications deny the all-things-considered wrongfulness of an action that is pro tanto wrong.Footnote 17 Excuses accept the all-things-considered wrongness of the conduct but instead deny the defendant’s culpability for it in order to exculpate her.Footnote 18 These distinctions in the orthodox view can be mapped onto the conceptual structure of the criminal law, such that 1) offense definitions would ideally correspond to pro tanto wrongs, 2) offenses that lack a justification (like necessity or self-defense) – i.e. the unlawful actions – would ideally correspond to wrongs simpliciter (or all things considered), and 3) unjustified offenses that also lack any excusatory defense (like duress) – for which one can be fairly convicted – would ideally track the wrongs simpliciter that also are culpable.Footnote 19

Given the many substantive views one might take in moral theory, can we say something more in general terms (i.e. without appealing to any substantive moral theory) about how wrongness differs from culpability? Perhaps the most important difference is that wrongness is often thought to be more objective in certain respects than the more agent-focused (or subjective) notion of culpabilityFootnote 20 – although strictly speaking this will depend on the specific substantive view of moral wrongness one favors. Still, I think we can fairly say that, at a minimum, the orthodox view takes it that the notion of wrongfulness relevant to criminalization is a function of not only the reasons that were epistemically available to the actor to reason from (or be motivated by, take into account, etc.) at the time in question, but sometimes also reasons that were not epistemically available to the actor at the time. These might include a range of considerations that the actor reasonably was unaware of or would not be expected to act in light of, but which the legislature properly may consider in deciding which conduct to prohibit – considerations like general deterrence and the expressive benefits of criminalization and punishment, and perhaps even considerations like the facts about how much harm one’s conduct actually goes on to cause (even if only due to luck).Footnote 21

What does this mean for how to understand the wrongness constraint on criminalization? There are two options. It turns on whether one thinks moral wrongness similarly can depend a least in part on such objective, non-agentially available reasons like those just sketched. If one does think non-agentially available reasons can bear directly on moral permissibility, then one can simply take moral wrongness on this more objective view to be a requirement for proper criminalization. Alternatively, if one has a more agent-centered or perhaps deontological view of moral wrongness (which does not look to considerations the actor could not take into account or reason from), then moral wrongness would merely be one consideration among many (sitting alongside deterrence, expressive benefits, etc.) that determine whether there is a sufficiently weighty positive case in favor of criminalizing the conduct. Thus, moral wrongness on this more agent-centered view would not be required for criminalization; rather, the constraint would be that the conduct to be criminalized must be what we might call a “bare wrong”Footnote 22i.e. an action that is decisively disfavored by the balance of the relevant reasons (whether available to the agent or not) that bear on how to behave on the occasion in question. Such a constraint requiring the bare wrongfulness (or objective unjustifiability) of the conduct is, I take it, the minimum that would be built into the orthodox view, which its adherents could accept regardless of their view of what makes act tokens morally wrong.Footnote 23 But those who would defend a more objective view of moral wrongness might also go further and say that their preferred form of moral wrongness is required for criminalization. I cannot take a substantive position on the difficult and contested concept of moral wrongness, so I prefer to say that the relevant constraint on criminalization according to the orthodox view is just that the conduct in question must be a bare wrong in order for it to be properly prohibited.

Unlike the notion of bare wrongness that the orthodox view (at a minimum) requires for criminalization, culpability is assumed to be a function only of the reasons bearing on how to behave that were epistemically available to the actor to reason from (or be motivated by, etc.) on the occasion in question – particularly how defective the agent’s engagement with these reasons was shown to be by the misconduct performed.Footnote 24 Generally it is assumed that conduct must also be culpable (not just wrong in the relevant sense) in order for it to be properly criminalized and punished (ideally that each act token of the proscribed type of conduct be culpable). Further, the amount of criminal blame and punishment that the defendant becomes liable to upon conviction must be proportionate to their culpability for the action they were convicted of.Footnote 25 At a minimum, the culpability of an action (understood in terms of the quality of the actor’s engagement with the reasons available to her to take account of when acting) sets the upper limit on the amount of criminal blame and punishment that may fairly be imposed for this action pursuant to a conviction,Footnote 26 although some think that wrongness might also be an independent ingredient in the amount of criminal blame that is deserved (e.g. if some less harmful forms of culpable wrongdoing might deserve less punishment than equally culpable but unluckily more harmful conduct).

2 Walen’s Objection to My Theory of Culpability

The orthodox view as just described serves as the backdrop to Walen’s objection to my theory, which was intended to be a theory of culpability in the above sense. Let me briefly explain the view before explaining Walen’s objection.

2.1 The Manifestation Account of Culpability

Following the insufficient regard line of theories of culpability,Footnote 27 the Manifestation Account I defended previously says that a prohibited action is criminally culpable to the degree that it manifests insufficient regard for the interests, rights and values that are properly protected by the law.Footnote 28 Insufficient regard is understood in terms of the defects one’s action reveals in how one attached weight to the reasons that exist in the circumstances as one believes them to be.Footnote 29 That is, an action is culpable to the extent it displays a valuation of reasons that diverges from the correct weights the law ideally says should be ascribed to the reasons available for one to reason from or be motivated by on this occasion.

The distinctive aspects of my view are motivated by the observation, as Walen puts it, that “there is often a mismatch between how bad a person’s will was and the amount of blame the criminal law assigns them. Two people with equally bad wills may commit different crimes, or two people may commit equally grave crimes with different levels of bad will.”Footnote 30 This makes trouble for simple versions of the insufficient regard view (or quality of will theory). The most important competitor to my view is the Causal Account, which takes an offense’s culpability to equal the amount of insufficient regard the agent possessed and that was causally active in producing the action. The Causal Account says we find an act’s culpability by comparing the difference between the agent’s actual valuation of reasons and the valuation of reasons the law takes as correct.Footnote 31 Consider an unjustified act of theft, for exampleFootnote 32:

Theft–Causal Account

Agent

Pro

Contra

Culpability (degree of error) on the Causal Account

Perfectly law-abiding citizen’s valuation

1

10

0

Offender’s valuation

20

2

(20–1) + (10–2) = 27

The perfectly law-abiding citizen’s valuation is the weight the law recognizes as attaching to the reasons in favor of the prohibited act (Pro) and the reasons against (Contra). The degree of difference between this and the agent’s actual valuation is then determined as indicated in the table to arrive at an overall assessment of the action’s culpability.

Trouble arises for the Causal Account when the defendant harbors tremendous ill will towards her victims, which causes her to perform the crime, but the crime itself is not especially serious. Perhaps the actor commits only a minor offense because this is all she could do on this occasion to harm her victim. If more harm had been possible, suppose she would have inflicted it. In the case reflected in the table, suppose the actor hates the victim and would impose suffering and death if only she could. Instead, the only harm she can impose in this instance (without getting caught and punished, perhaps) is to steal the victim’s car. That explains the numbers in the table: the actor sees 20 units of benefit to the action given that it harms the person she hates and she sees little (just 2 units of cost due to the risk of getting caught) that counts against it.

It is implausible, as the Causal Account implies, that the large amount of ill will the agent possesses and acts from means her action is tremendously culpable regardless of what that action is or involves. The Causal Account overestimates this action’s culpability. Because auto theft is less serious compared to the tremendous ill will the offender acted from, the theft does not fully manifest all the insufficient regard she possessed and acted on. Sometimes the full depth of one’s ill will is not fully manifested in what one does, and our culpability judgments should reflect this.

My Manifestation Account was designed to avoid such problems. To find a criminal action’s culpability, it says, we look not at the agent’s actual degree of error in weighing reasons, but the degree of such error the action manifests. This is assessed in a more objective way based on the circumstances as she believed them to be, i.e. using a principle of lenity to interpret the offender’s behavior.Footnote 33 More precisely, the culpability of a criminal action equals the degree of error in weighing reasons that exists between i) the perfectly law-abiding citizen’s (PC’s) valuation of the reasons the law properly recognizes as bearing on the act, and ii) the otherwise law-abiding citizen’s (OC’s) valuation of these reasons. OC represents the least departure in weighing reasons (under the circumstances as the actual agent believes them to be) that would be needed to get someone to do the crime that the agent actually committed. This amount of error, as explained elsewhere,Footnote 34 is equal to the difference between PC’s valuation of the reasons Contra and the reasons Pro. Why? Because to turn PC into OC, all we need to do is assume an error in overvaluing Pro and/or undervaluing Contra that leads to a valuation of reasons where Pro just slightly outweighs Contra. Recall the theft example. The next tableFootnote 35 shows ways one might adjust the weightings of PC to get OC, who is the smallest departure from PC needed to get one to do the offense. Each version of OC is just as culpable.

Theft–Manifestation Account

Agent

Pro

Contra

Degree of error [Manifestation Account]

Perfect Citizen (PC)

1

10

0

OC1 (Raise Pro)

10.1 (raised from 1)

10

9.1

OC2 (Lower Contra)

1

0.9 (lowered from 10)

9.1

OC3 (Mix)

6 (raised from 1)

5.9 (lowered from 10)

5 + 4.1 = 9.1

One benefit of the Manifestation Account, I’ve argued,Footnote 36 is that it reflects a normatively attractive ideal of the criminal law as making charitable assumptions about us as citizens when interpreting our behavior for criminal law purposes. On this view, the criminal law aims to take us to be the least bad version of ourselves that is compatible with what we did.

2.2 Walen’s Objection

Walen objects that my theory of culpability is actually a theory of degrees of wrongness. The reason, as Walen puts it, is that on my theory “[t]he actual quality of a wrongdoer’s will is, to a large extent, disregarded.”Footnote 37 Instead, the theory is “concerned with only what [amount of ill will] must be implied to explain that particular wrong”Footnote 38 – the amount manifested. This avoids the “mismatch” problem of minor offenses that don’t manifest the full depth of the actor’s ill will; however, the theory manages to correctly assign amounts of criminal blame only by collapsing into a theory of wrongness. Why? Rather than taking culpability to be about the defects in one’s actual practical reasoning (as Simester suggestsFootnote 39), my theory is concerned with the degree of disrespect that actions manifest, which is objectively assessed in terms of the balance of reasons that exist given the circumstances as the actor believes to them to be. This objective aspect of the assessment seems to push the theory in the direction of an account of wrongness. As seen above, the orthodox picture takes wrongness (whether moral wrongness or just bare wrongness) to be more objective in nature.Footnote 40 Thus, the objective assessment of what amount of ill will a given action manifests would seem to more naturally fit the more objective assessment that wrongness involves. Thus, it may seem questionable whether the theory is an account of culpability at all. Wouldn’t it be simpler to just take it to be an account of degrees of wrongness?Footnote 41

This objection matters not just because it reveals confusion about the proper target of the theory I sought to develop, but because it would mean the theory of culpability is not compatible with the orthodox picture sketched above. Culpability, we saw, has a distinct focus on the agent’s practical reasoning – the quality of one’s engagement with the available reasons bearing on what to do.Footnote 42 But if my theory of culpability is not really a function of one’s actual reasoning, then it faces difficulties in capturing what the orthodox view takes culpability to be about. My theory might seem most directly to be a form of act evaluation (as is wrongness), not an assessment of agents in respect of their actions (the lack of respect that went into the act), as the orthodox view assumes is true of culpability.

Moreover, if my account is supposed to be a theory of wrongfulness instead, then it would be a poor fit with how the orthodox view conceives of criminal wrongs. My theory makes culpability a function solely of the reasons available to the actor to reason from, be motivated by or otherwise take into account. But the orthodox view took it that wrongness is not necessarily a function just of the reasons that are available to the agent to take into account, but also other more objective reasons not available to the agent. Thus, if my theory really is to be seen as an account of what actions the law may deem to be criminal wrongs, it does not amount to a very plausible account. At best, the theory would capture a subjective picture of moral wrongness which is merely one ingredient in the overall legislative determination of which actions to prohibit. This would threaten to render my theory at best quite limited in scope – and at worst outright false.

3 Answering Walen’s Objectivity Objection

Walen objected that my theory is in fact concerned with wrongness because it does not look to the quality of one’s actual reasoning (one’s actual level of ill will) to assess the culpability an agent incurs from doing a given action. While Walen is right that my theory is somewhat more objective in its operation than other views of culpability,Footnote 43 I’ll argue it’s incorrect to say that the theory “disregards”Footnote 44 the actual quality of the agent’s will – i.e. the defects in her actual engagement with the applicable reasons bearing on how to act.

In fact, the culpability attributions licensed by my account do speak in important ways to the actual ill will (or defectiveness in one’s engagement with the reasons one had access to) at the time of one’s misconduct. Even on my Manifestation Account, ill will must still be present for culpability to be attributed for an action. In particular, as I previously explained my view, attributing criminal culpability requires a “repulsion failure” to be present which was causally active in producing one’s misconduct.Footnote 45 Here is what this means. A convenient way to think of the demands of the criminal law is that we have a “repulsion mechanism” whose job is to be motivationally responsive to the factors in virtue of which actions are criminally prohibited and which is supposed to kick in to motivate us not to perform actions that are properly prohibited.Footnote 46 The law is “indifferent to the content of one’s repulsion mechanism,”Footnote 47 as self-interested motivations can be as effective in getting one to avoid criminally wrongful conduct as a concern for others or even respect for law. However, it’s a requirement for a prohibited action to manifest insufficient regard (i.e. be criminally culpable) that the action was caused, at least partially, by a failure of one’s repulsion mechanism.Footnote 48 This, in turn, requires that one’s action was actually called upon to do some motivational work under the circumstances to get one to refrain from a criminally prohibited action, but the repulsion mechanism failed to do its job and one actually went ahead and performed the action nonetheless. Only when one’s action is in this way at least partially caused by a failure of one’s repulsion mechanism would the ill will one possesses be manifested in the action one performed.Footnote 49

Thus, my theory takes it that a prohibited action is culpable only if caused at least in part by ill will. As a result, the theory always imputes at least a portion of the ill will that was actually present and helped produce the conduct. Once we know that some ill will helped cause the prohibited action, the next question is how much ill will a given action manifested. This is where the more objective aspect of the theory comes in. As explained in Sect. 2, the theory applies a principle of lenity under which an action is taken to manifest only the least amount of ill will needed to get an otherwise law-abiding citizen to do the act the defendant did under the circumstances. Because of this lenity-driven approach to determining how culpable an action is (an approach adopted in part to resolve the mismatch problem), my view will sometimes impute less than the full amount of ill will that was present at the time of acting and that was causally active in producing the wrongful action. But the theory never imputes more ill will than one actually possessed.Footnote 50 As a result, there is a meaningful sense in which the theory is still about one’s actual engagement with reasons – i.e. how much lack of respect for others we can discern in how one acted. As such, it is still an instance of what Edwards and Simester call the engagement view, which I take it reflects the orthodox position among criminal law theorists.

One might question this and ask if there really are cases where my view imputes more ill will, and thus culpability, for an action than the amount the agent possessed when acting. Most importantly, consider a very hesitant and anguished offender who does a criminal action – suppose it’s a theft – with high degree of reluctance and regret. Call her Jane. She strongly feels the pull of the reasons against the action – suppose she gives exactly the correct weight to the reasons Contra – and just barely manages to do the criminal action. Thus, one might think she possesses only a small amount of ill will. To be more precise, suppose Jane’s actual valuation of reasons takes it that Pro = 10.1 and Contra = 10 (assuming units of reason come in increments of 0.1). However, suppose that the correct valuation (as in the Theft example above) is Pro = 1 and Contra = 10. Isn’t this a case in which my theory might impute more culpability than the real amount of ill will that the agent actually possessed at the time? The actual amount of ill will Jane possessed was 9.1. After all, this is the degree to which Jane overvalued the reasons Pro, and she gave the right weight to Contra.

Nonetheless, my account does not impute more culpability than the amount of ill will Jane actually possesses. The amount of ill will the theory imputes in its culpability assessment of this action is also 9.1. After all, this is the least amount of ill will that must be present to get an actor to do the wrongful action under the circumstances. Thus, in this case, the Manifestation Account attributes the same amount of culpability for the action as the amount of ill will that actually was present. The theory sometimes attributes less culpability than the full amount of ill will possessed at the time of acting, and sometimes the same amount – but never more.Footnote 51

For this reason, the culpability judgments generated by the Manifestation Account does always reflect on the agent’s actual engagement with reasons at the time of acting – her actual valuation of the weight of the applicable reasons. It does not always reflect the full depth of depravity the offender may possess in their heart (which we might even know, through admissions or other communications, was causally active in producing the conduct in question). But the theory always attributes an amount of culpability that bears some relation to how much ill will was actually present. Sometimes it attributes less, but it doesn’t attribute more. In this way, the theory – despite its greater objectivity than other views – still concerns the quality of one’s actual engagement with reasons and does not entirely disregard it. It looks to the degree of ill will that is manifested by one’s action – i.e. an amount one’s action showed one to possess at least as much as. For this reason, the theory does not disregard one’s actual practical reasoning and so I resist Walen’s suggestion that the theory really concerns wrongness rather than culpability as the orthodox view conceives of it.Footnote 52Footnote 53

4 Extending the Manifestation Account to Excuses

To strengthen this response to Walen, I now want to answer a further concern. Another way the Manifestation Account might be thought to be overly objective is that it fails to account for the sort of case where the agent-centered notion of culpability, as distinct from the more agent-neutral notion of wrongness, is most clearly on display – namely, cases of excused wrongdoing. As I presented it in earlier work, my theory has little to say about culpability in excuse cases. Thus, it not only is incomplete as a theory of culpability, but it seems incompatible with the orthodox view presented in Sect. 1. Here I set aside cases of exemptions, where one’s cognitive faculties are so impaired that one falls below the minimum threshold for being an agent who is aptly subject to judgments of blame.Footnote 54 Instead, the worry for my account concerns “rationale-based excuses” like duress and provocation, where the agent remains a full actor who performed a genuine action but has reduced culpability for their wrong due to their excuse.Footnote 55 (What to say about incapacity defenses like insanity, and whether they sometimes function as genuine excuses not exemptions or denials of an offense element, is a complex issue, which I mostly set aside in what follows.Footnote 56)

The challenge for the Manifestation Account is this. The orthodox view understands culpability as improper engagement with the reasons available to the agent, while taking it that excuses accept the wrongness of one’s action but deny one’s culpability for it (at least partly). However, as presented, the Manifestation Account offers no distinctive way of calculating the culpability of excused actions. It would simply apply the culpability calculus presented in Sect. 2 to such actions. But this incorrectly entails that excused wrongs remain fully culpable. This is what follows from the perfectly law-abiding person’s weighting of the relevant reasons, given that excused actions (supposing there are any) are assumed to remain all-things-considered wrongs that at least a perfectly law-abiding person would manage not to do.Footnote 57 Accordingly, the Manifestation Account as presented fails to capture what the orthodox view assumes about genuine excuses (as opposed to exemptions or justifications): namely, that they fully accept wrongness but still eliminate or reduce culpability. Footnote 58

Thus, to make the Manifestation Account compatible with the orthodox view and allow it to explain why genuinely excused wrongs (if any) are properly viewed as having reduced culpability, I show how the account can be amended to apply also to excused wrongdoing. This would allow the theory to account for the cases in which the distinctive contribution of culpability is most easily discernable, namely those where a prohibited action is admittedly wrongful (at least in the sense of bare wrongs from Sect. 1) but which nonetheless have reduced culpability. This reinforces the conclusion that the theory properly concerns culpability rather than a theory of wrongness as Walen suggested. It also offers additional theoretical benefits, summarized in the conclusion.

4.1 What We Want to Capture: A Closer Look at Duress

To show what we want a theory of culpability to capture, consider a case of the excuse of duress:

Duress: The Spider Crew wants to sell some enriched uranium on the black market. They go to Dr Alina Johnson who works in the lab in the city and tell her to steal it for them after closing tonight or else they will kidnap her daughter and “hurt her in ways you can’t imagine.” She knows they have committed acts of violence in the past and has no doubt they wouldn’t hesitate to carry out the threat if she didn’t comply (or went to the police). So she gives in to the threat, steals the uranium and hands it over to the Spider Crew.

Alina plausibly has a duress excuse to the crime of theft. On the English law test, the duress defense is available only if a “sober person of reasonable firmness” with the legally cognizable characteristics of the defendant (like age, gender, illness, pregnancy) would have behaved the same way.Footnote 59 For this to be a case of excuse not justification, it would have to be the case that the action remains all things considered, or in an impersonal sense, wrongful (which a perfectly law-abiding person would manage to abstain from even if many of us would not) while Alina’s culpability for it is reduced, resulting in acquittal. How might this be the case?Footnote 60 Assume the probability-adjusted harm of allowing enriched uranium to get onto the black market is much greater than of one individual experiencing grievous bodily harm and possible death. This would preclude a necessity (or lesser evils) justification, which typically requires the harm one’s conduct can reasonably be expected to prevent is greater than the harm it can reasonably be expected to cause (such that it’s really the lesser evil).Footnote 61 Alina therefore has done something all-things-considered wrong and unlawfulFootnote 62 – something, let’s suppose, that the weight of reasons on the facts as she believes them to be decisively disfavors. Despite being wrongful (at least a bare wrong in the sense outlined aboveFootnote 63), however, the duress she faces reduces her culpability sufficiently to prevent conviction. She engaged with the available reasons in such a way that, although wrongful (not supported by the balance of reasons), we nonetheless have sufficient sympathy for her that we do not see her as properly meriting legal condemnation. Her act didn’t manifest enough insufficient regard to merit the condemnation built into a conviction.

There are two ways to understand why Alina, despite having acted in a way the law takes to be wrongful, still merits exculpation. The dominant model sees excuses as cases where the actor’s rationality (or will) was overcome by emotion in ways we find understandable, even if the circumstances do not sufficiently justify the conduct to render it non-wrongful.Footnote 64 While the balance of applicable reasons disfavors Alina’s conduct, we would find an emotion-driven reaction along the lines of what Alina did to be understandable and sympathetic enough to merit exculpation even though her conduct was wrongful.

One concern, however, is that some cases that seem to merit a duress defense don’t involve an emotional reaction that overwhelmed the actor’s rational assessment of the reasons.Footnote 65 Sometimes actors who seemingly merit an excuse are cool and collected and yet still do the crime – not from an emotional disturbance but from calmly assessing the circumstances. If some such actors should be exculpated too, as plausibly would be the case for Alina even if she calmly assessed the situation and chose to behave as she did in the above case, this would require an alternative theoretical basis than emotion overwhelming reason. One plausible account distinguishes the objectively applicable (third-personal) reasons bearing on the action and the agent-relative (first-personal) reasons that reflect the individual prerogatives or privileges citizens have to pursue personal priorities. It’s not implausible to think there is an agent-relative prerogative to inflict some degree of impersonally unjustified harm to defend oneself and loved ones from grave threats. This might be recognized on an excusatory basis out of sympathy for the defendant’s plight and as a “concession to human frailty,” rather than the objective balance of reasons which justifications focus on.Footnote 66

Regardless of one’s account of excuses, duress exculpates those who commit offenses in response to a threat that a “sober person of reasonable firmness” would not be able to withstand. This helps show how culpability comes apart from wrongness in criminal law theory. Suppose that, following the orthodox view, we understand the notion of wrongness relevant to the criminal law as the conduct that is decisively disfavored by the applicable reasons, where these reasons do not all have to be available to the agent at the time of acting and can include a range of agent-neutral or impersonal considerations that the legislature may legitimately look to in deciding which conduct to prohibit (such as harm, deterrence, expressive benefits, and providing reassurance to victims). If we make this assumption, then culpability stands as a distinct notion focusing on what an action says about whether one has engaged with reasons in at least a minimally tolerable way. Considering excuses shows us that what is “minimally tolerable” here is not marked out just by the line between unlawfulness (wrongfulness) and lawfulness, but rather suggests that we also can tolerate some unlawful (wrongful) conduct in certain especially sympathetic circumstances.

This shows a distinct contribution made by the notion of culpability. Suppose one wanted to understand all of criminal law simply in terms of wrongness and wrongness were the only relevant normative concept in one’s legal moralist view – perhaps for reasons of conceptual parsimony.Footnote 67 This would produce an impoverished view of excuse cases. To secure the result that Alina should be exculpated, a theory of the criminal law that could only appeal to wrongness would have to say that Alina’s conduct simply is not wrong – i.e. not properly prohibited. But this is an impoverished account of Alina’s case. It provides no acknowledgment of the reasons in virtue of which the legislature may have legitimately chosen to mark out the conduct at issue as an offense, including the reasonable concern to deter theft and facilitation of terrorist activities and to express our condemnation thereof through criminalization. Surely these reasons stand even in cases like Alina’s where we can also have sympathy for giving in to such extreme threats. Therefore, it would be more accurate and illuminating to accept that the conduct is wrongful, thus fully acknowledging the legislature’s reasons for marking it out as a wrong even in cases like Alina’s. Instead, the exculpation is better seen as stemming from viewing the conduct as non-culpable. Why? Because abstaining from the offense under Alina’s circumstances is not something it seems fair and humane to expect citizens to do, as even a person of “reasonable firmness” would behave similarly in her place. Alina’s conduct, even if wrongful and legitimately deemed unlawful, does not cross beneath the threshold of action that displays the minimum level of regard for others that we expect everyone in society not to dip below.

4.2 Extending the Manifestation Account to Excuse Cases

As presented above, the Manifestation Account of culpability still faces difficulty in such cases. I have offered no worked-out account of how to understand wrongful but excused actions. The Manifestation Account as presented earlier said an action manifests an amount of insufficient regard equal to the degree of error in weighing reasons that exists as between: i) the perfectly law-abiding citizen’s (PC’s) valuation of the applicable reasons and ii) the otherwise law-abiding citizen’s (OC’s) valuation of these reasons. OC represents the least departure in weighing reasons (given the circumstances as the agent believes them to be) that is needed to get someone to do the offense that the agent actually committed. Schematically, Alina’s conduct can be represented as follows:

Unjustified Nuclear Theft/Facilitation of Terrorism

Agent

Pro

Contra

Degree of error

[Unamended Manifestation Account]

PC

20

50

0

OC

50.1

50

30.1

Thus, the theory as stated entails that even crimes done with excuses are culpable. The theory needs to be amended to explain why offenses done with excuses are not culpable.

Nonetheless, I contend, the theory can be extended to account for such cases.Footnote 68 Here is my proposal for how to do it. When an offense is done without sufficient justification but excusing conditions are present (whether sufficient or not), the Amended Manifestation Account would say the culpability of the action is calculated differently than when no excuse is present. Rather than finding the difference between the weights attached by PC and OC, as can normally be done, we should instead look to the weights attached to the reasons Pro and Contra that would be attachedFootnote 69 (on the facts the actor is aware of) by a person of reasonable firmness (RF) who has the same legally cognizable characteristics and faces the same pressure (threats, coercion, provocation, etc.) as the actual actor. RF thus is supposed to reflect our shared judgments about which actions done in response to pressurized circumstances meet the minimum standard of acceptability that we insist on as a society – i.e. which we would have sufficient understanding and sympathy for to tolerate in our community even if wrongful.Footnote 70 Note that in saying that even a person of reasonable firmness would perform a given wrongful action, I don’t mean to suggest that this makes the conduct itself reasonable or non-wrongful. It’s only the firmness in question that is reasonable, although it admittedly might be clearer to use “minimally acceptable” to modify “firmness.” If the action is genuinely excused (not justified), it must remain all-things-considered wrongful such that it would not be performed by a perfectly law-abiding citizen (who may have especially high levels of fortitude). And for excuse cases, this will be so even if the wrongful action also has reduced culpability because a person of reasonable (or minimally acceptable) firmness would not manage to abstain from it in light of their vulnerabilities or limitations that we can have sympathy for. I continue to present the view in terms of what a person of reasonable firmness (RF) would do to fit better with the legal test (though would be equally happy with other terminology, such as speaking of the person of “minimally tolerable” firmness).

Given all this, the Amended Manifestation Account would hold that when there is credible evidence (enough to meet the burden of production) that D was in excusing conditions when she committed offense A, and the issue is whether these conditions are enough to exculpate this otherwise unjustified wrongful conduct, then the culpability of A equals the degree of error as between i) OC’s valuation of the applicable reasons and ii) RF’s valuation thereof (not PC’s). However, when it’s clear that no excusing conditions apply, then the unamended account would still give the right results. Thus, on the amended account, when an action is fully excused – i.e. when RF would also do the action – no insufficient regard is manifested.Footnote 71 Even if PC would (perhaps heroically) abstain from this conduct, such that doing this excused action involves a departure from the standard of legal perfection, this is not manifested by the action – i.e. we do not find the regard given to the interests of others to be insufficient or below the minimum standard of due regard expected in our community. Normally, RF’s valuation of reasons will coincide with PC’s; they come apart only in excuse cases. While the Amended Manifestation Account takes RF to be the operative measuring stick for culpability in general, this yields different culpability results from the unamended theory, which assesses culpability by reference to PC, only where excuses are in play.

More precisely, the Amended Manifestation Account gives distinctive results (compared to the original theory) in two cases where D finds herself in excusing conditions: 1) those where RF would still commit the offense even though it’s unjustified and 2) those where RF would be expected to resist the emotional pressure that is present and refrain from the action. Consider each in turn. First, recall Alina who is exculpated because a person of reasonable firmness would not be expected to refrain from behaving as she did. The culpability of her action is given as follows:

Excused and Unjustified Nuclear Theft

Agent

Pro

Contra

Degree of error

[Amended Manifestation Account]

PC

20

50

0

RF

55

50

0

OC

50.1

50

x

Alina’s action manifests no insufficient regard because although PC (perhaps heroically) would not do the wrongful action, culpability on the Amended Manifestation Account is measured against the yardstick of RF (as compared to OC, not PC). And RF would do the action. So OC’s valuation of reasons would contain no error relative to RF’s.

Now take a case where D is in excusing conditions but RF would be able to abstain from the offense in the agent’s shoes. Thus, consider Mark. Suppose the criminal gang threatens to smash the windows of Mark’s convertible unless he steals the nuclear material for them. Perhaps the car has sentimental value for him, so he is overwhelmed by an emotional response that induces him to commit the theft. Even if RF’s weighing of reasons were somewhat distorted by an understandable and sympathetic emotional response to the pressure applied to Mark, RF nonetheless would not give in to the threat. Here, to find the culpability of the action, we compare OC’s valuation of reasons to RF’s. We ask what the smallest departure from RF’s valuation of reasons would be that is needed to get someone with D’s legally cognizable characteristics to do the crime under the circumstances, and that is the insufficient regard it manifests.

Partially Excused Unjustified Nuclear Theft

Agent

Pro

Contra

Degree of error

PC

10

50

0

RF

15

50

0

OC

50.1

50

35.1 [= 50.1 – 15 + 50 – 50]

The action here manifests insufficient regard because both PC and RF will refrain from the theft despite the pressure that is present. The amount manifested is determined by comparing how OC weighs reasons to how RF does. (This amount, 35.1, which is obtained by comparing OC to RF, is less than if we’d compared OC to PC, which would have yielded culpability 40.1.)

Thus, the Amended Manifestation Account can account also for excusing conditions whose influence on the agent’s practical reasoning we find sympathetic and are willing to tolerate as a society. When such excuses are present, it becomes clear that the operative yardstick for measuring culpability comes not from comparing OC with PC but rather with RF. Outside these two sorts of cases where excusing conditions are present, RF’s weighting of reasons will be the same as PC’s and so the Amended Manifestation Account lines up with the results of the original version of the account in cases involving no excuses.Footnote 72

The Amended Manifestation Account thus can capture the distinct contribution made by the notion of culpability as opposed to wrongness, which is most visible in excuse cases. Usually, unjustified (bare) wrongs will be criminally culpable as well (provided no excuse applies). This is what the original Manifestation Account entailed. However, by extending the account to explain why acts like Alina’s remain wrong but aren’t culpable, the Amended Manifestation Account is on stronger footing as a theory of culpability. The Amended Manifestation Account plausibly accounts for cases like Alina’s: it fully recognizes the legislative considerations that make it legitimate to deem Alina’s conduct to be a (bare) wrong while still giving full recognition to the aspects of the case that lead us to sympathize with and ultimately condone her practical reasoning, thus negating her culpability.

Furthermore, by focusing on culpability as distinct from wrongness in excuse cases, we can see that the threshold of minimally tolerable engagement with reasons does not perfectly track the line between (bare) wrongful and lawful conduct. Rather, certain tokens of act types that are properly deemed legal wrongs might nonetheless not involve engagement with reasons that dips below the level of due regard that we expect from everyone in society. That is, actions like Alina’s, even if properly deemed legal wrongs, do not manifest insufficient regard. The line between actions that make a conviction deserved and those that don’t should track this line between acts that manifest insufficient regard and those that don’t, not the line between unjustified wrongs and lawful action.

4.3 An Objection: Indifference and the motivations of excused actors

An anonymous reviewer helpfully points out that one might still worry that the Amended Account has trouble with deviant cases involving especially indifferent actors. Suppose Alina* is actually motivated to do the theft not because of the threat or a concern for her children’s well-being, but because she is insufficiently repulsed by the wrong-making features of the theft. Here the theft might still seem quite culpable. Can the Amended Manifestation Account capture this?

One response suggested by some of my earlier work on manifestation in the context of justifications might be to bite the bullet and say that even if Alina* possesses significant ill will in this case, it is not manifested in this action because of the threat that she is aware of.Footnote 73 However, this seems not to be the most plausible route to take for excuse cases. After all, the basis for excuses offered above is a sense of sympathy or compassion toward the defendant in light of the especially challenging circumstances they faced.Footnote 74 But given the indifferent way Alina* was motivated, it is not very plausible that our sympathy would be engaged. It is for similar reasons that excuses are typically conditioned on one’s conduct being caused in the particular way the excuse specifies, rather than that one caused the conditions of one’s own excuse or was motivated by the prospect of avoiding liability due to having an excuse.Footnote 75 If one is motivated in either of these dubious ways, our sympathy likewise would not be engaged. So there is little normative basis for an excuse.

How to capture this on the Amended Manifestation Account? The simplest way is to make use of another bit of machinery from my original account of culpability. I take it that in assessing culpability, what matters is how large a defect in practical reasoning it would take to get someone in the defendant’s circumstances to do what defendant did under whatever the privileged description of this act is. In legal contexts, the relevant description is naturally supplied by the applicable legal doctrine (or for normative culpability judgments, what this legal description should be). Thus, when an excuse is in play, the relevant description of the actor’s conduct, for purposes of assessing culpability, should specify the manner in which the putatively excused conduct was motivated.Footnote 76 This is needed to ensure that the action is one where our sympathy is genuinely engaged. The relevant description of Alina*’s conduct, thus, should be something like: committing the nuclear theft from indifference to the harms and risks involved, rather than due to the threat or concern for her children. It will require a large amount of insufficient regard for legally protected interests to get one to do the action described in this fine-grained way.

Accordingly, for duress to genuinely reduce one’s culpability, it plausibly must be the case that one performed the wrongful action from duressi.e. in response to and out of concern for the interests of those threatened. Only then would our sympathy be likely to be sufficiently engaged to see the actor as having reduced culpability. Thus, in assessing the culpability of a putatively excused action, to rule out cases of indifferent motivation like Alina*, it’s plausible we should apply the Amended Manifestation Account to the actor’s conduct described so as to include the particular motivations that were causally operative. This accords well with legal doctrine as well.Footnote 77 (Depending on one’s views about the relevance of motives to justifications, this may mark a difference from the way the culpability of putatively justified actions are to be assessed, where motives may not matter since justifications do not similarly involve a sympathy-based relaxation to our expectations.Footnote 78)

5 Concluding Remarks: Toward A Unified Framework for Criminal Wrongs and Criminal Culpability

In this paper, I have defended the Manifestation Account from Walen’s objection and shown that it is best seen as a theory of culpability as distinct from wrongness, as these notions are understood on an orthodox view. Moreover, I showed how the Manifestation Account can be extended to cover the cases that most clearly show the separate role of culpability as distinct from wrongness, namely cases of excused wrongdoing.

One payoff for extending the Manifestation Account to cover culpability not only for legally wrongful (and unjustified) actions but also for excused actions is that it provides a convenient way to give a unified reasons-based account of all the main categories of criminal misconduct as conceived on the orthodox view. That is, it suggests a simple picture, which proceeds in terms of reasons, of a) when acts are wrongful and how wrongful they are, as well as b) how culpable wrongful unexcused actions are, plus c) how culpable wrongful excused actions are.

First, to account for the degree of bare (or legal) wrongness of an action, we can simply apply the conception of wrongness baked into the orthodox view. To assess the bare wrongness of an action, we would consider the degree to which all the reasons that bear on what to do in a given choice situation decisively disfavor the action under consideration, where these reasons do not need to be all epistemically available to the actor to reason from, but which may properly be taken into account by the legislature for purposes of deciding what conduct to deem unlawful.

Second, the culpability of unjustified wrongful actions in a non-excuse case is to be understood along the lines of the Manifestation Account (whether the original or the amended version, as they are indistinguishable in such cases). This involves narrowing our assessment from considering all the reasons bearing on how to act – regardless of their availability to the agent to reason from at the time – to instead considering just those reasons the agent could reasonably be expected to reason from on the occasion in question. Thus, on the Manifestation Account, to assess the culpability of a wrongful action which may or may not be justified, but in which no excuse is implicated, we can compare: i) the weights attached by PC (the perfectly law-abiding citizen) to the reasons bearing on how to act that were available to the actual agent to reason from at the time with ii) the weights attached to these reasons by OC (the otherwise law-abiding citizen). The culpability of the action equals the degree of error in OC’s weighting of the epistemically available reasons relative to PC’s weighting thereof.Footnote 79

Finally, to account for culpability in cases of wrongful action where a putative rationale-based excuse (as opposed to a justification or exemption) is also in play, we can look to the Amended Manifestation Account. This would tell us that, to assess culpability, we should compare (i) the weights we can in sympathy expect to be attached by RF (the person of reasonable, or we might say minimally tolerable, firmness) to the reasons that are epistemically available for the actual agent to reason from at the time with (ii) the weights attached to these same reasons by OC. The culpability of the action (if any) equals the degree of error in OC’s valuation of these epistemically available reasons relative to RF’s valuation thereof, in the way the Amended Manifestation Account advises.Footnote 80

In this way, a reasons-based framework can be used to account for (a) the wrongness of actions, (b) their culpability when justifications might be in play but not excuses and (c) their culpability when an excuse is in play. This reasons-based account helps crystallize the distinct roles of wrongness and culpability, as well as show how the culpability of an action differs in cases of unjustified wrongs where no excuse is relevant and cases of wrongs that are unjustified but have an excuse.