Skip to main content
Log in

Can Social Reflective Equilibrium Delineate Cornell Realist Epistemology?

  • Published:
Philosophia Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Cornell realism (CR), a prominent meta-ethical position that has emerged since the last decades of the twentieth century, proposes a non-reductionist naturalistic account of moral properties and facts. This paper argues that the best version of CR’s chosen methodology for arriving at justified moral beliefs must be seen as a variant of reflective equilibrium. In comparison to the traditional versions, our proposal offers a ‘social’ reinterpretation of reflective equilibrium in delineating CR’s epistemology. We argue that it satisfactorily accounts for objectivity and calls for the inclusion of the social nature of both moral and scientific inquiries. Emphasising the social dimension of their epistemological account also nudges debates in metaethics into incorporating the much-needed social dimension while dealing with questions of moral beliefs and facts that have been of CR’s concern.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. It gets this moniker from the affiliations of its main proponents Richard Boyd, David Brink, Nicholas Sturgeon and Geoffrey-Sayre McCord with the said university.

  2. Cf Tropman (2012), and Oliveira and Perrine (2017).

  3. While the notion of objectivity is contested, Both Brink and Boyd agree that it stands for a sense of the truth and falsity of moral statements being independent of our moral theory. Brink provides a necessary (but not sufficient) condition for objectivity: a domain is objective if there are truths independent of the evidence we possess for claiming them (Brink 1989, 14–17). In this paper, achieving moral objectivity should mean arriving at epistemically reliable representations of moral properties, or facts. At the very least, such a notion assumes that the truth and falsity of such representations can be independent of the evidence we have for it. For more on objectivity, see Tropman (2018).

  4. While there have been a few efforts to provide a social turn to reflective equilibrium like Baderin (2017), our novelty is in attempting to model a social reflective equilibrium framework such that the commitments of Cornell realists towards naturalistic moral realism are reconciled with the social nature of moral inquiry. This contrasts with most traditional works on reflective equilibrium, which either do not require moral enquiries to be social or many contemporary works, which might take reflective equilibrium to be a social enterprise but dispense with any naturalistic metaethical commitments. Pace some accounts where there is only a nudge towards a collective reflective equilibrium, we offer a more substantive account of how the social turn and objectivity can be accommodated at both the level of considered moral judgments and coherence-seeking processes. We thank an anonymous reviewer for highlighting this point.

  5. The appeal of CR also lies in the fact that it provides a way to ascribe cognitivist and realist commitments to ethical discourse without the metaphysical and epistemological ‘baggage’ that accompanies intuitionism (Brink 1999, 197).

  6. For example, it is claimed that moral properties are theory-independent while scientific ones are not, and scientific properties are empirically testable while moral properties are not.

  7. Boyd stresses the unified framework by conceptualising philosophy as a “normative science” with epistemology involved in understanding which belief-forming mechanisms are credible for obtaining truth (1983, 72).

  8. Although Sayre-McCord (1996, 142) and Brink (1989) have made mentions of reflective equilibrium, to the best of our knowledge the scholarship on Cornell realism has not engaged with the role of reflective equilibrium as CR’s epistemology.

  9. Brink too claims that his coherentist theory of moral justification is "essentially John Rawls's method of wide reflective equilibrium" (1989, 104).

  10. The burden of proof then is on critics like Tropman to show either that RE is not a plausible scientific epistemology or that while RE might be applicable in scientific inquiries, it fails in moral inquiries (perhaps because of the discontinuities between the two domains). Such a criticism though, is yet to formulated.

  11. By Constructivists, we are referring to proponents of the Strong program like Bloor, who claimed that the methodology of science used to study reality is deeply theory-dependent and if such a methodology were to be trusted to fetch knowledge, then the reality which the scientists study itself must at least be partly constituted by their theoretical tradition.

  12. Barnes and Bloor call it (the equivalence postulate) the “third feature of relativism”, which requires sociologists, historians, philosophers and the like to treat rationally and irrationally held beliefs to be subjected to similar appeals of applications of mind and influenced by similar patterns of “social organisation”. They argue that irrespective of whether they are considered true or false, beliefs must be subjected to similar scrutiny of their credibility and offered similar kinds of explanations. (1982, 23–28).

  13. McPherson (2015, 655) has offered a similar analysis.

  14. Rawls does not adequately clarify what achieving coherence entails. It is often suggested that it involves maximising relations of support and minimizing conflicts between the members of the belief set (Cath 2016). Consistency, systematicity, generality and simplicity have all been considered as desirable features of the resulting belief set Kappel (2006).

  15. Background theories would include aligned non-moral judgments, such as the epistemic or pragmatic importance of various moral theories.

  16. To be fair, in one of his earlier writings, Rawls uses the first person plural ‘we’ while referring to how we can arrive at considered moral judgments and claims that the legitimacy of considered moral judgments is to be granted when competent judges arrive at a consensus (1951, 180). However, he quickly abandons that in his later works as seen in the quote.

  17. CR’s moral semantics built on Boyd’s causal regulation account has come under challenge from what has been referred to as the Moral Twin earth problem (Horgans & Timmons 1992). As mentioned earlier, the focus of our paper is on their epistemology, and hence we have chosen not to engage with it. However, several interlocutors including Brink have responded to the issue (Copp 2000; Brink 2001). Väyrynen (2018) and Geirsson (2005) have also provided useful accounts of possible responses from the naturalists.

  18. See Timmons (1991) for a supporting claim that Brink and Boyd can be employed to show how we can have epistemic access to moral facts, although Timmons finds Boyd’s naturalistic semantics to be problematic.

  19. Especially when coherence is sought under “impartial and imaginative consideration of the interests of the relevant parties” (Brink 1989, 132).

  20. In a later work Brink (1999) talks of a dialectical equilibrium that could be closely seen in connection with our proposal. Brink however, doesn’t offer any defense of his position and restricts himself to the concept and its virtues.

  21. Our response to Street is limited to her possible objections to CR’s naturalism and not a refutation of the Darwinian dilemma in general.

  22. Street uses the term ‘evaluative’ to capture a broader range of judgments that are under the influence of evolutionary forces. We have replaced it with the narrower term ‘moral’ to maintain continuity.

  23. Such criticisms are often called as input objections (Timmons 1991).

  24. While there might be some tension in suggesting that it is reasonable to hold on to intuitions and in the same vein arguing for their removal from the set of considered moral judgments, it is to be noted that steadfastness seems to be applicable to those cases where a sheer inability to provide moral reasons for one’s judgment is called as dumbfounding, while conciliation is applicable in responding to recalcitrant intuitions.

  25. While Baderin’s criticism is against Wolff and Avner de-Shalit (2013) conception of public reflective equilibrium and not specifically against CR’s reinterpretation of RE, the crux of her allegation can still apply to CR. We have not engaged with Baderin and Wolf & de-Shalit’s conceptions of public reflective equilibrium because their framing of the question is vastly different from ours, with their concern being how to accommodate “public opinion” to the practice of moral philosophy.

  26. Rawls himself held a view compatible with CR’s stance in his (1951) article mentioned earlier. He held his method in ethics (RE) to be analogous to the study of inductive logic which is interested in formulating criteria to decide which empirical claims must be considered true.

  27. This is in clear contrast to some contemporary works, which might take reflective equilibrium to be a social enterprise but dispense with any naturalistic metaethical commitments. For instance, while Brandstedt & Brannmark (2020) do offer a practical ‘ bottom-up’ interpretation of reflective equilibrium, their account is vastly different from ours. They explicitly give up the notion of moral truth, and the process of reflective equilibrium is employed “not in the search of moral truth, but rather to highlight what stands in the way of solutions to problems agents face in different domains of social life” (2020, 355). Our account attempts to reconcile the notion of moral truths to the social process of moral inquiry. We thank an anonymous reviewer for highlighting this point.

  28. Anderson clarifies that by democratic, she intends equal and dignified participation of all stakeholders in a moral dispute (Anderson 2016, 94).

  29. For instance, with the parity thesis in mind, CR could grant that testimony plays an important role in the case of scientific beliefs also. CR’s reinterpretation not only works as a feasible method in the moral domain, it is also a better characterization of how scientific inquiries proceed.

References

  • Anderson, Elizabeth. (2016). “The Social Epistemology of Morality.” In Michael Brady and Miranda Fricker (Eds.). The Epistemic Life of Groups. Oxford University Press.

  • April, C. W., & April, M. D. (2016). Understanding Moral Distress Through the Lens of Social Reflective Equilibrium. The American Journal of Bioethics, 16(12), 25–27.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Arras, John. (2009). “The Way We Reason Now: Reflective Equilibrium in Bioethics.” In Bonnie Steinbock (Ed.). The Oxford Handbook of Bioethics, (46–71). Oxford University Press.

  • Baderin, A. (2017). Reflective Equilibrium: Individual or Public? Social Theory and Practice, 43(1), 1–28. https://doi.org/10.5840/soctheorpract20174311

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Barnes, B., and D. Bloor. (1982) `Relativism, Rationalism and the Sociology of Knowledge’. In M. Hollis and S. Lukes (eds.). Rationality and Relativism (pp. 21–47). Blackwell.

  • Beauchamp, T. L., & Childress, J. F. (1994). Principles of Biomedical Ethics. Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Boyd, Richard. (Forthcoming). “On Being’ Oh So Scientific’: Evolutionary Theory as Methodological Anesthesia in Moral Philosophy and Moral Psychology.” In Bastian Reichardt (Ed). Problems of Goodness: New Essays in Metaethics. https://rnb1114.wixsite.com/richardboyd/papers.

  • Boyd, R. (1983). On the Current Status of the Issue of Scientific Realism. Erkenntnis, 19, 45–90.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Boyd, R. (1988). “How to Be a Moral Realist”. In G. Sayre-McCord (Ed). Essays on Moral Realism (181–228). Cornell University Press.

  • Boyd, R. (2010). Realism, natural kinds, and philosophical methods. In H. Beebee & S. Leary (Eds.), The Semantics and Metaphysics of Natural Kinds (pp. 11–34). New York, NY: Routledge.

  • Brandstedt, E., & Brännmark, J. (2020). Rawlsian constructivism: A practical guide to reflective equilibrium. Journal of Ethics, 24(4), 355–373.

  • Brink, D. (1989). Moral Realism and the Foundations of Ethics. Cambridge Studies in Philosophy. Cambridge University Press.

  • Brink, D. (1999). Objectivity and Dialectical Methods in Ethics. Inquiry, 42(2), 195–212.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brink, D. (2001). Realism, Naturalism, and Moral Semantics. Social Philosophy and Policy, 18(2), 154–176.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brink, D. (2014). Principles and Intuitions in Ethics: Historical and Contemporary Perspectives. Ethics, 124(4), 665–694. https://doi.org/10.1086/675878

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Buchanan, Allen. (2007). Social Moral Epistemology and the Role of Bioethicists. In Lisa A. Eckenwiler and Felicia Cohn (Eds.). The Ethics of Bioethics: Mapping the Moral Landscape. Johns Hopkins University Press.

  • Buchanan, A. (2002). Social Moral Epistemology. Social Philosophy and Policy, 19(2), 126–152.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cath, Yuri. (2016). Reflective Equilibrium. In H. Cappelen, T. Gendler, and J. Hawthorne (Eds.). The Oxford Handbook of Philosophical Methodology (213–230). Oxford University Press.

  • Copp, D. (2000). Milk, honey, and the good life on moral twin earth. Synthese, 124(1), 113–137.

  • Daniels, N. (1979). Wide Reflective Equilibrium and Theory Acceptance in Ethics. The Journal of Philosophy, 76(5), 256–282.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Daniels, N. (1980). Reflective Equilibrium and Archimedean Points. Canadian Journal of Philosophy, 10(1), 83–103.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • DePaul, Michael R. (2011). Methodological Issues: Reflective Equilibrium. In Christian B Miller (Ed.) The Continuum Companion to Ethics (75–106). Continuum.

  • Geirsson, H. (2005). Moral twin-earth and semantic moral realism. Erkenntnis, 62(3), 353–378.

  • Haidt, J., Bjorklund, F., & Murphy, S. (2000). Moral dumbfounding: When intuition finds no reason. Unpublished manuscript, University of Virginia

  • Horgan, T., & Timmons, M. (1992). Troubles for new wave moral semantics: The ‘open question argument’ revived. Philosophia, 21(3), 153–175. https://doi.org/10.1007/BF02382554

  • Jones, Karen. (2007). “Moral Epistemology”. In Frank Jackson and Michael Smith (Eds.). The Oxford Handbook of Contemporary Philosophy.

  • Kappel, K. (2006). The Meta-justification of Reflective Equilibrium. Pdf. Ethical Theory and Moral Practice, 9, 131–147.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kurth, C. (2013). What Do Our Critical Practices Say about the Nature of Morality? Philosophical Studies, 166(1), 45–64.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Levy, N. (2006). The Wisdom of the Pack. Philosophical Explorations, 9(1), 99–103.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lutz, Matthew and James Lenman. (2021). “Moral Naturalism”. In Edward N. Zalta (Ed.). The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Spring 2021 Edition), URL = <https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2021/entries/naturalism-moral/>.

  • McGrath, S. (2019). Moral Knowledge. Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • McPherson, Tristram. (2015). “The Methodological Irrelevance of Reflective Equilibrium.” In Chris Daly (Ed). The Palgrave Handbook of Philosophical Methods. Palgrave Macmillan.

  • Mercier, H., & Sperber, D. (2011). Why Do Humans Reason? Arguments for an Argumentative Theory. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 34(2), 57–74.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Oliveira, L. R. G., & Perrine, T. (2017). Cornell Realism, Explanation, and Natural Properties. European Journal of Philosophy, 25(4), 1021–1038.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rawls, J. (1999). A Theory of Justice (Rev). Belknap Press of Harvard University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Rawls, J. (1974). The Independence of Moral Theory. Proceedings and Addresses of the American Philosophical Association, 48, 5–22.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rawls, J. (1951). Outline of a Decision Procedure for Ethics. The Philosophical Review, 60(2), 177.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sayre-McCord, G. (1996). Coherentist Epistemology and Moral Theory. In Walter Sinnott-Armstrong and Mark Timmons (Eds.) Moral Knowledge? New Readings in Moral Epistemology (137–89). Oxford University Press.

  • Scanlon, T M. (2014). Being Realistic About Reasons. Oxford [Eng.]. University Press.

  • Street, S. (2006). A Darwinian Dilemma for Realist Theories of Value. Philosophical Studies, 127(1), 109–166.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sturgeon, N. (2007). Ethical naturalism. In D. Copp (Ed.), The Oxford Handbook of Ethical Theory (pp. 91–121). Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press.

  • Timmons, M. (1991). On The Epistemic Status of Considered Moral Judgments. The Southern Journal of Philosophy, 29(S1), 97–129.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tropman, E. (2018). Formulating Moral Objectivity. Philosophia, 46(4), 1023–1040.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tropman, E. (2012). Can Cornell Moral Realism Adequately Account for Moral Knowledge? Theoria, 78(1), 26–46.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Väyrynen, P. (2018). A simple escape from moral twin earth. Thought: A Journal of Philosophy, 7(2), 109–118.

  • Wolff, Jonathan, and Avner de-Shalit. (2013). Disadvantage. Oxford Political Theory. Oxford University Press.

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Sushruth Ravish.

Ethics declarations

Conflict of Interest

The authors declare that they have no conflict of interest.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Springer Nature or its licensor (e.g. a society or other partner) holds exclusive rights to this article under a publishing agreement with the author(s) or other rightsholder(s); author self-archiving of the accepted manuscript version of this article is solely governed by the terms of such publishing agreement and applicable law.

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Ravish, S., Sirola, V.S. Can Social Reflective Equilibrium Delineate Cornell Realist Epistemology?. Philosophia 51, 2015–2033 (2023). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11406-023-00654-9

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Revised:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11406-023-00654-9

Keywords

Navigation