Skip to main content
Log in

Almog was Right, Kripke’s Causal Theory is Trivial

  • Published:
Philosophia Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Joseph Almog pointed out that Kripkean causal chains not only exist for names, but for all linguistic items (Almog 1984: 482). Based on this, he argues that the role of such chains is the presemantic one of assigning a linguistic meaning to the use of a name (1984: 484). This view is consistent with any number of theories about what such a linguistic meaning could be, and hence with very different views about the semantic reference of names. He concludes that the causal theory is ‘rather trivial’ (1984: 487). In this paper I argue that Almog is correct to hold that the causal theory is trivial, but, contra Almog, argue that the triviality of the existence of causal chains is not a matter of such chains having a presemantic role in assigning linguistic meanings to utterances. Instead, such triviality is due to the fact that the causal theory reflects no more than a truism about the epistemology of convention acquisition.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Almog accepts Millianism and formulates the linguistic meaning of a name like ‘Hillary Putnam’ as ‘to-refer-to-H.-Putnam’ (1984: 482).

  2. While his paper has received significant citation, subsequent authors have not engaged with his charge of triviality specifically. Strangely, such neglect is also true of Almog himself. In a later paper ‘The puzzle that never was – referential mechanics’ (Almog, 2012), and despite the fact that it is explicitly billed as a sequel to ‘Semantical anthropology (Almog, 1984), the issue of causal chains being trivial in virtue of being presemantic does not reappear. The same holds for his subsequent book, Referential Mechanics (2014).

  3. I take it for granted that Kripke’s causal theory is not typically interpreted as trivial. For example, Putnam writes: "Kripke’s work has come to me second hand; even so, I owe him a large debt for suggesting the idea of causal chains as the mechanism of reference" (Putnam, 1975: 198, my italics). Relatedly, Kaplan ends ‘Demonstratives’ with a remark about ‘the power and the mystery of the causal chain theory’ (1989: 563).

  4. I would like to thank an anonymous referee for pressing this issue.

  5. See Carston (2016), Recanati (2017).

  6. Kripke requires, as a condition on the type of causal chain that serves to secure reference, that language users in such a chain must intend to use the name as the speaker that they inherited the name from did (1981: 96).

  7. It is unlikely that this reductive analysis of reference is what people have in mind when they say that Kripke showed that causal chains are the ‘mechanism of reference’. We don’t, in general, express the claim that phenomenon X turns out to reduce to phenomenon Y by claiming that ‘Y is the mechanism of X’. Rather we just say that ‘X turns out to be Y’ or something similar.

  8. See Cohen 2002 for a defense of the idea that names are generic.

  9. Almog, while never pointing out that such chains exist for all conventions, comes close to casting the matter in explicitly epistemic terms in ‘E.T.’s general picture’. Immediately upon presenting this picture, however, he discards epistemic matters and starts to make his argument for the linguistic assignment view (1984: 481).

  10. In stating the convention as a rule I follow Miller’s (Miller, 1992) criticism of the Lewisian view that conventions are regularities (Lewis, 1969).

  11. Stine (1977) defended such a neo-Gricean view of semantic reference.

  12. On the Lewisian view of conventions we generally stick to past behaviour due to ‘salience by precedence’, i.e. precedence renders our past solutions to recurring problems salient to the present (Lewis, 1969: 36). The notion of ‘salience’ here is the technical one from Schelling (1960).

  13. Of course, we can involve the past if we adopt the causal theory of name-individuation, as explained earlier.

  14. I follow Kripke in treating both baptism by ostension and baptism by reference-fixing description as cases of baptism. See, for instance, Kripke (1981: 96).

  15. For a rare dissenting note, see Wettstein (1999: 454).

  16. For a discussion of epistemic transparency, see Boghossian (1994).

  17. One implication of the present work is that we should not take the existence of causal-historical chains as (non-trivial) evidence in favor of reductive causalism. Even if we assume that reductive causalism is false, the epistemology of convention acquisition guarantees that such chains will exist.

  18. For example: ‘Obviously the name is passed on from link to link. But of course not every sort of causal chain reaching from me to a certain man will do for me to make a reference’ (Kripke, 1981: 93).

  19. My own view is that Russell’s adoption of such a view was due to a conceptual confusion concerning different types of linguistic conventions. See Smit (2021).

  20. Note that Kripke introduces the causal theory rights after soliciting intuitions about cases (‘Feynman’, ‘Einstein’, ‘Gödel’) that trade on the weakness of viewing the semantic reference of names as idiolectical.

References

  • Almog, J. (1984). Semantical anthropology. Midwest Studies in Philosophy, 9, 479–489

  • Almog, J. (2012). The puzzle that never was – referential mechanics. Schantz, R. (ed). Prospects For meaning. De Gruyter

  • Almog, J. (2014). Referential mechanics. Direct reference and the foundations of semantics. Oxford University Press

  • Boghossian, P. (1994). The transparency of mental content. Philosophical Perspectives, 8, 33–50

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Carston, R. (2016). Contextual adjustment of meaning. Riemer (Ed.). Handbook of semantics. Routledge

  • Cohen, L. J. (2002). The individuation of proper names. Knowledge and Language. Boston Studies in the Philosophy of Science, 227, 119–140. Springer

  • Evans, G. (1982). (Ed: Macdowell, J). The Varieties of Reference. New York: Oxford University Press

  • Frege, G. (1948). Sense and reference. The Philosophical Review, 57(3), 209–230.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Frege, G. (1956). The thought: a logical enquiry. Mind, 65, 289–311

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kaplan, D. (1989). Demonstratives. Almog, J, et al. (eds.) Themes from Kaplan. Oxford University Press

  • Kripke, S. (1977). Speaker’s reference and semantic reference. Midwest Studies in Philosophy, 2, 255–276

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kripke, S. (1981). Naming and necessity. Oxford: Blackwell Publishing

    Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, D. (1969). Convention: a philosophical study. Cambridge: Harvard University Press

    Google Scholar 

  • Miller, S. (1992). On conventions. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 70, 435–444

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Putnam, H. (1975). Explanation and reference. Mind, language and reality: philosophical Papers, volume 2. Cambridge University Press

  • Recanati, F. (2017). Contextualism and polysemy. Dialectica, 71, 379–397

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Russell, B. (1910). Knowledge by acquaintance and knowledge by description. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 11, 108–128

  • Schelling, T. (1960). The strategy of conflict. Cambridge: Harvard University Press

    Google Scholar 

  • Searle, J. (1983). Intentionality: an essay in the philosophy of mind. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Smit, J. P. (2021). Russell’s eccentricity. Erkenntnis, 86, 275–293

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Soames, S. (2002). Beyond rigidity. New York: Oxford University Press

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Stine, G. (1977). Meaning other than what we say. Philosophical Studies, 33, 319–337

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wettstein, H. (1999). A father of the revolution. Noûs, 33, 443–457

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to JP Smit.

Ethics declarations

Conflict of Interest

The authors declare that they have no conflict of interest.

Additional information

Publisher’s Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Springer Nature or its licensor (e.g. a society or other partner) holds exclusive rights to this article under a publishing agreement with the author(s) or other rightsholder(s); author self-archiving of the accepted manuscript version of this article is solely governed by the terms of such publishing agreement and applicable law.

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Smit, J. Almog was Right, Kripke’s Causal Theory is Trivial. Philosophia 51, 1627–1641 (2023). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11406-023-00625-0

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Revised:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11406-023-00625-0

Keywords

Navigation