1 Introduction

In “The Zygote Argument is Invalid: Now What?” (2015b), I argued that Alfred Mele’s original Zygote Argument (Mele 2006, 2008, 2012) is invalid: its two premises tell us merely that the truth of determinism is (perhaps spuriously) correlated with the absence of free human agents, but the argument nonetheless concludes with a specific explanation for that correlation, namely that deterministic laws (of the sort described by determinism) precluderule out, destroy, make impossible, conflict with, rob people of—free will. As such, the original Zygote Argument is deductively invalid (in classical logic), and to infer the Zygote Argument’s explanatory conclusion from its two premises is to commit the cum hoc, ergo propter hoc (with this, therefore because of/on account of this) fallacy.

In a recent essay, Gabriel De Marco (2016) grants that the original Zygote Argument is invalid for the reasons that I identified, and claims that he has developed two new solutions to my objection. In this essay, I argue that both of his proposed solutions fail. The first fails as a “rescue” because it merely repeats (in slightly different jargon) a candidate solution that I proposed in Mickelson 2015b. The second solution fails because it consists in another invalid variant of the original Zygote Argument.

This essay as four main sections. I begin (§2) with a brief overview of the traditional problem of free will and determinism, the problem that the Zygote Argument purports to solve. I then address De Marco’s first reply (§3) and second reply (§4) to my invalidity objection in turn. In closing (§5), I identify the role that covert best-explanation reasoning plays in De Marco’s second solution and offer a few reflections on the current state of the free-will debate.

2 The Problem of Free Will and Determinism

The traditional problem of free will and determinism has two basic components, the correlation problem and the explanation problem (Mickelson 2019a, 2019b, forthcoming). The correlation problem is the familiar challenge of settling the answer to this simple question: Is it metaphysically possible for a normal human to exercise free will when determinism is true? Free-will theorists have been deeply divided by this question for millennia, with many insisting that the answer is “yes” while others insist that the answer is “no.” Since a “no” answer is a commitment to the view that it is impossible for free human agents to exist in a world with deterministic laws (of the sort described by determinism), i.e. to the view that these two phenomena are incompossible, let us refer to the “no” answer as an incompossibility solution to the correlation problem. By contrast, a “yes” answer will be a compossibility solution.

Despite superficial appearances, the (in)compossibility debate is not simply a dispute about the modal distribution of free human agents. Rather, this debate is philosophically interesting because it is a debate about the nature of free will itself: anyone who finds the incompossibility solution intuitive has thereby discovered that, by their intuitive lights, any successful account of free will must include (at least) one necessary condition which is impossible for a human to satisfy when determinism is true. Those who find the compossibility solution satisfying are, thereby, denying that there is any such desideratum on a successful account of free will. As such, the (in)compossibility dispute can be understood both as fundamental dispute about the nature of free will and a dispute about the standards by which a candidate account of free will should be judged.

Although an incompossibility solution to the correlation problem is interesting and dialectically significant in its own right, it also raises a new and challenging explanation problem. This explanation problem consists in two closely related challenges:

The Unmet Condition Challenge (E1): Identify the necessary condition C on free will which humans cannot satisfy when determinism is true.

The Condition-Underminer Challenge (E2): Identify what keeps normal humans from satisfying condition C when determinism is true.

In order to solve (E2), one must identify the precise features/factors of normal humans and/or their environment which make it impossible for a person to satisfy the necessary condition named in the solution to (E1).

Candidate solutions to (E1) are usually divided into three main categories: could-have-done-otherwise conditions (a.k.a. leeway conditions), source conditions, and hybrid conditions (according to which an ability to do otherwise is what allows one to satisfy the source condition on free will). Since it is safe to assume these types of solutions to (E1) are already familiar to the target audience of this essay and they play no role in the present discussion, I will not review them here.Footnote 1

Within the mainstream free-will literature, philosophers do not have any standardized categories for candidate solutions to (E2). However, we can remedy this by importing into our discussion the three basic categories of “luck” introduced by Thomas Nagel in his early work on the paradox of moral luck.Footnote 2 Following Nagel, I will use the phrase “due to luck” as shorthand for “due to factors beyond one’s control.”Footnote 3 The three standard categories of luck (i.e. factors beyond one’s control) are: causal luck, circumstantial luck, and constitutive luck. A person is subject to causal luck, as it is to be understood here, when the factors which account for the diachronic (state-by-state and moment-by-moment) evolution of the physical world—causal relations, causal laws, laws of nature, or the like—are beyond one’s control. Non-causal/actor-extrinsic circumstantial luck obtains when one’s action is due, at least in part, to circumstances (events, states of affairs, etc.) external to the actor that are beyond that actor’s control. Constitutive luck obtains when one’s actions are due, at least in part, to constitutive properties of the actor that are beyond the actor’s control.

We can easily categorize the most familiar types of solutions to (E2) based on which of these factors beyond one’s control is doing the work of keeping people from acting freely. A strict causal luck solution the (E2) proposes that it is impossible for humans to act freely when determinism is true because humans are subject to deterministic causal relations (deterministic causal laws, deterministic laws of nature, or the like). Peter van Inwagen’s Consequence Argument (van Inwagen 1983) is generally considered to be an argument for a causal-luck solution to (E2).Footnote 4 By contrast, a strict constitutive luck solution to (E2) proposes that what keeps people from satisfying the condition named in (E1) is constitutive luck, i.e. the barrier to free agency is that the properties which constitute the agent (at least in key mental respects) are beyond the agent’s control. For example, Galen Strawson uses the Basic Argument to defend a strict constitutive-luck solution to (E2), claiming that that is constitutive luck alone which makes people unfree—from which it follows that the causal-luck solution to (E2) is false (cf. Strawson 1994; Mickelson 2015b, 2019b). A strict circumstantial luck solution to (E2) says that it is impossible to satisfy the condition on free will named in (E1) when determinism is true because people lack control over certain non-causal, agent-extrinsic events which obtained prior to their actions.Footnote 5 Usually, though, philosophers who worry about circumstantial luck do not think that it is a lack of control over past circumstances alone that makes a person unfree, but rather combine circumstantial luck with some other type of luck to create a hybrid solution to (E2). Some philosophers have suggested that a circumstantial/constitutive luck solution could be correct (cf. Latus 2001, Nagel 1986: 113–14). Others have suggested a causal/circumstantial luck solution according to which it is the combination of our lack of control over the laws and circumstances in the remote past which makes us unfree now (cf. Bailey 2012: 361).

Our review of extant solutions to (E2) upsets the common assumption, popular in both the free-will literature and moral-luck literature, that broadly (i.e. strict and hybrid) causal luck solutions to (E2) are the only sort available. When it comes to the supposed incompossibility of free will and deterministic laws, there is an in-house debate among incompossibilists about whether this incompossibility is spurious (as the constitutive luck solution proposes) or not (as a broadly causal luck solution proposes). This means that there is nothing peculiar to the dialectical structure of the problem of free will and determinism which allows one to safely infer a causal luck solution to (E2) from an incompossibility solution to the correlation problem; to infer the former from the latter amounts to fallacious cum hoc, ergo propter hoc reasoning.

The reader will note that the terms ‘incompatibilism,’ ‘compatibilism,’ ‘compatibility,’ and ‘incompatibility’ have not been used in my characterization of the traditional problem of free will and determinism. This is because there is currently no consensus among philosophers about the meaning of these terms, so anyone who uses these terms must either assign a controversial definition to them or define them in such imprecise ways that the meaning of the terms are unclear. When pressed, most free-will specialists agree that the term ‘incompatibilism’ has traditionally picked out a broadly causal luck solution to (E2) of the explanation problem (cf. Pereboom 2001, 2014; Vihvelin 2008, 2013, 2018; McKenna 2010: 432; Levy 2011: 1; McKenna and Pereboom 2016: 151; Sartorio 2016: 147). This is consistent with the etymology of the term ‘incompatibilism’: this bit of jargon was (by all appreances) coined by Keith Lehrer to pick out roughly the thesis that it is owing to determinism that the free-will thesis is false when determinism is true.Footnote 6 By contrast, Mele contends that he is “following standard practice” when he uses this term to name nothing beyond a mere incompossibility solution to the correlation problem. He also proclaims (without argument or evidence) that philosophers who define the term otherwise are guilty of defining the term in a “nonstandard” or “nontraditional” way (Mele 2017: 6, n. 4, and 2019: 3, n.1).Footnote 7 In order to sidestep this dispute about who is “correctly” defining bits of technical jargon, I will not use the term ‘incompatibilism’ or its cognates to make any of the central points in this essay; I will mention them only when doing so contributes to my assessment of De Marco’s proposed solutions to the invalidity objection.

3 De Marco’s Terms and “Initial Solution”

Mele has presented several statements of the Zygote Argument since it was first introduced, and it will be useful to adopt an intuitive way of tracking them. With that aim in mind, I will hereafter refer to statements of the Zygote Argument by the year they first appeared in print, starting with “ZA-2006” to label the very first statement of the Zygote Argument (Mele 2006).Footnote 8 My invalidity objection targets a later statement of the Zygote Argument that Mele put forward in response to criticisms of ZA-2006, hereafter “ZA-2012”Footnote 9:

ZA-2012

P1. Ernie is not [free or] morally responsible for anything he does.

P2. Concerning moral responsibility of the beings into whom the zygotes develop, there is no significant difference between the way Ernie’s zygote comes to exist and the way any normal human zygote comes to exist in a deterministic universe.

C. So determinism precludes [free will and] moral responsibility – at least for human beings who develop from normal human zygotes. (Mele 2012: 15)Footnote 10

ZA-2012 is invalid: its premises entail merely that it is metaphysically impossible for a normal human born from a human zygote to act freely and morally responsibly when determinism is true, but its conclusion says that it is owing to determinism that people lack free will and moral responsibility when determinism is true.Footnote 11

So understood, we can say that ZA-2012 is invalid because its premises support only (an idiosyncratically restricted variant of) the incompossibility solution to the correlation problem, but its conclusion forwards a controversial causal luck solution to (E2) of the explanation problem.

Having shown that ZA-2012 is fallacious, I outlined two ways to improve the original Zygote Argument, saying:

[T]here are two ways that one might repair the argument. The simplest repair strategy is to weaken the original conclusion so that the Zygote Argument concludes to mere incompossibilism [i.e. the thesis that deterministic laws and free action are incompossible]. However, if the original, explanatory conclusion of Mele’s argument is to be defended, the Zygote Argument must be amended to include a premise that identifies deterministic laws as a freedom-undermining feature of the manipulation story. (Mickelson 2015b: 2912; my emphasis)

Here, I propose two distinct strategies for responding to the invalidity objection. First, one may hold the two premises of ZA-2012 fixed and change its solution to the incompossibility thesis entailed by those premises. For clarity, let us call any argument which results from implementing this “simplest repair” strategy a premise-preserving solution to the invalidity objection. Second, one may keep the premises of ZA-2012 fixed and update its premises so that they support this explanatory conclusion in order to create a variant of the Zygote Argument which is invulnerable to my invalidity objection. Let us call any argument which results from this strategy a conclusion-preserving solution to the invalidity objection. Notably, I argue that the only dialectically felicitous way to develop a conclusion-preserving solution to my invalidity objection is to supplement ZA-2012’s original premises with a best-explanation argument (Mickelson 2015b: 2912).

From the outset, I worried that philosophers might be tempted to brush off my complaints about the invalidity of ZA-2012 given how easy it is to develop a new, valid variant of ZA-2012 using the premise-preserving strategy (Mickelson 2015b: 2917). My proposed premise-preserving variant of the Zygote Argument, hereafter “Simple Repair,” may be summarized as follows:

  • Simple Repair

  • P1. Ernie does not freely A and is not morally responsible for A-ing.

  • P2. Concerning free action and moral responsibility, there is no significant difference between Ernie’s A-ing and any candidate for a free and morally responsible action in a deterministic universe.

  • C. So, no normal human candidate for a free and morally responsible action in a deterministic universe is a free action nor an action for which the actor is morally responsible. (Mickelson 2015b: 2917-2919)

In response to the invalidity objection and my overview of the two response strategies,Footnote 12 Mele adopted the following premise-preserving variant of ZA-2012, hereafter “ZA-2013”:

  • ZA-2013

  • P1. Ernie is [not a free agent and is] not morally responsible for anything.

  • P2. Concerning [the free action and] moral responsibility of the beings into whom the zygotes develop, there is no significant difference between the way Ernie’s zygote comes to exist and the way any normal human zygote comes to exist in a deterministic universe.

  • C. So in no possible deterministic world in which a human being develops from a normal human zygote is that human being [free or] morally responsible for anything he or she does (Mele 2013: 176).

Mele has recently reaffirmed his commitment to the premise-preserving strategy in his restatement of ZA-2013 as a modus ponens argument that I will call “ZA-2019”:

  • ZA-2019

  • P1. Ernie is not [a free agent or] morally responsible for anything he does.

  • P2. If Ernie is not [a free agent or] morally responsible for anything he does, no human being who develops from a normal human zygote in a deterministic world is morally responsible for anything he or she does.

  • C. So in no possible deterministic world in which a human being develops from a normal human zygote is that human being [a free agent or] morally responsible for anything he or she does. (Mele 2019: 120-121)

ZA-2019 is, uncontroversially, a valid argument.

Mele presents ZA-2019 in response to the worry that ZA-2013 is invalid.Footnote 13 Mele’s attention to this invalidity objection is somewhat puzzling. Mele offers no evidence that any professional philosopher has had this sort of worry about the validity of ZA-2013, nor does he mention that multiple free-will specialists (e.g. Mickelson 2015b: 2917, n.6; Sartorio 2016: 163–164) had already addressed this “worry” by pointing out that arguments such as ZA-2013 may be represented as modus ponens arguments. Moreover, Mele’s attention to this relatively trivial invalidity objection to ZA-2013 might confuse the average reader, for he does not distinguish it from my invalidity objection to ZA-2012—which is noteworthy because restating ZA-2013 as ZA-2019 does not address my invalidity objection.Footnote 14

To stave off needless confusion, let us draw a clear line between my invalidity objection to ZA-2012 and Mele’s trivial invalidity worries about ZA-2013. Hereafter, let the latter type of invalidity objection be known as the logic-text objection, since it amounts to little more than the (arguably misguidedFootnote 15) complaint that Mele should have stated ZA-2013 as a logic-text proof in classical deductive logic from the outset (rather than leaving this simple task as an exercise for his readers). By contrast, when an argument is invalid because it fails in its aim to close the “explanatory gap” between an incompossibility solution to the correlation problem and a specific solution to (E2) of the explanation problem, I will call it an explanatory gap objection.Footnote 16

While I grant that ZA-2013 and ZA-2019 are valid arguments, I do not think that Mele has, by adopting these new variants of ZA-2012/ZA-2006, adequately responded to the explanatory gap objection. Even if sound, ZA-2013 and ZA-2019 do nothing to adjudicate between the rival candidate explanations for the incompossibility of deterministic laws and free human agents. I have motivated this point by demonstrating that ZA-2013 may be used as a foundation for a more sweeping generalization argument which concludes that free will is impossible due entirely to constitutive luck, from which it follows that a strict constitutive luck solution to (E2) is true, that the causal luck solution to (E2) promoted by ZA-2012 is false, and that the conclusion of ZA-2013 expresses a true but metaphysically arbitrary claim (Mickelson 2015b; see also Mickelson 2017, 2019a, and 2019b). To be clear, I have never proposed that ZA-2013 is invalid, unimportant, or otherwise uninteresting; I have simply pointed out the generally overlooked fact that the premises of ZA-2012 fall short of delivering a broadly causal luck solution, or any solution whatever, to (E2).Footnote 17 This observation does not suggest that the Zygote Argument is unworthy of attention, but it does suggest that the underlying logical structure and upshot of manipulation arguments are poorly understood and, so, are worthy of considerably more attention than they have been given.

De Marco (2016) enters the debate at this point, claiming that he has devised two ways to “rescue” the Zygote Argument from my explanatory gap objection:

According to Mickelson, the only way to make such arguments valid is to supplement them with an argument that is an inference to the best explanation. In this paper, I argue that there are two other ways in which the proponent of such manipulation arguments can modify their argument, neither of which requires an inference to the best explanation. (De Marco 2016, abstract; my emphasis)

Pace De Marco, this summary of my position is flawed. It is not true that I say that the only way to change the invalid ZA-2012 into a valid argument is to “supplement them with an argument that is an inference to the best explanation.” As already discussed, I clearly outlined two ways to repair ZA-2012 in the face of the explanatory gap objection in Mickelson 2015b, namely the premise-preserving strategy and the conclusion-preserving strategy. I did claim that the only way to a conclusion-preserving solution to the explanatory gap objection to ZA-2012 is to add a best-explanation argument, but I also explicitly describe a premise-preserving solution that does not involve best-explanation reasoning of any kind (namely, “Simple Repair” above).

De Marco’s mischaracterization of my position is important when we look at his “two other ways” to repair manipulation arguments which are vulnerable to the explanatory gap objection.Footnote 18 De Marco summarizes his “initial solution” to the explanatory gap objection as follows:

For those manipulation arguments that are invalid for the reasons that Mickelson gives [i.e., those that are subject to an explanatory gap objection], as well as for the Zygote Argument, an easy fix would be to change their conclusion to the claim that compatibilism is false. (De Marco 2016:1624, my emphasis)

Since De Marco stipulates his own definition for the term ‘compatibilism’ in the course of his 2016 essay, it is important to note that he uses the phrase “compatibilism is false” to pick out the following incompossibility thesis:

there is no possible universe in which deterministic laws obtain and someone who is subject to the laws performs a free action (De Marco 2016: 1624).Footnote 19

So, piecing things together, De Marco’s “initial solution” to the explanatory gap objection consists in the following premise-preserving variant of ZA-2012, call it “Easy Fix”:

  • Easy Fix

  • P1. Ernie does not act freely or responsibly.

  • P2. With regard to free action and moral responsibility, there is no significant difference between Ernie and a standard agent (i.e. someone who is, like Ernie, subject to the laws of nature) in a deterministic universe.

  • C. So, there is no possible universe in which deterministic laws obtain and a standard agent performs a free action.Footnote 20

Easy Fix is a valid argument, so it may appear that De Marco’s initial solution to the explanatory gap objection is a success.

Stepping back, however, grave problems with De Marco’s first solution become apparent. The reader will note that the terms ‘compatibility,’ ‘incompatibility,’ ‘incompossibility, ‘compatibilism,’ ‘incompatibilism,’ and ‘incompossibilism’ do not appear in any of the statements of the Zygote Argument we have considered so far, i.e. ZA-2006, ZA-2012, ZA-2013, ZA-2019, Simple Repair, and Easy Fix. As such, how one defines these terms is completely irrelevant to the validity of these arguments. By extension, how one defines the aforementioned terms is also irrelevant when assessing which of these manipulation arguments is vulnerable to an explanatory gap objection. It is irrelevant, then, that De Marco refers to the incompossibility thesis stated in the conclusion of Easy Fix by using the phrase “compatibilism is false” while I prefer the phrase “incompossibilism is true” (for reasons that I provide in Mickelson 2015a, 2017, 2019a, 2019b, and forthcoming). This means that we can safely set aside De Marco’s disapproval of my preferred labelling systemFootnote 21 and refocus on De Marco’s claim that Easy Fix constitutes a new solution to my explanatory gap objection to ZA-2012.

Once we focus on the content of De Marco’s Easy Fix, the differences between it and my Simple Repair disappear: the two arguments are constituted by the same three propositions presented in the same logical form. Simply put, Easy Fix and Simple Repair are the same argument.Footnote 22 It follows that De Marco’s first solution to the explanatory gap objection is a nonstarter.Footnote 23

4 De Marco’s Second Solution

In De Marco’s second response to the explanatory gap objection, he takes up a conclusion-preserving strategy. De Marco agrees that the original Zygote Argument’s explanatory conclusion may be defended by adding a best-explanation argument to the premises of the original Zygote Argument (De Marco 2016: 1627), but he rejects my proposal that best-explanation reasoning is required to support its explanatory conclusion (i.e. that such reasoning is required to felicitously fill the explanatory gap between an incompossibility solution to the correlation problem and a specific solution to (E2) of the explanation problem) (De Marco 2016: 1625). Rather than identifying a flaw in the argument I make in support of this proposal (Mickelson 2015b: 2912), De Marco proposes a counterexample in the form of a new variant of the Zygote Argument.

De Marco claims that a conclusion-preserving variant of the original Zygote Argument can be created without using best-explanation reasoning by adding a third premise which asserts that free-will possibilism is true, i.e. that it is metaphysically possible for someone to act freely (De Marco 2016: 1625–1626). De Marco does not provide a simple statement of this new manipulation argument, but the argument he describes, call it “ZAP-2016,” may be summarized as follows:

  • ZAP-2016

  • P1. Ernie does not freely A and is not morally responsible for A-ing.

  • P2. Concerning free action and moral responsibility, there is no significant difference between Ernie’s A-ing and a standard agent (i.e. a normal human who is, among other things, subject to the laws of nature) in a deterministic universe.

  • P3. Possibilism: Possibly, a standard agent performs a free action for which he is morally responsible.

  • C. So, determinism precludes—rules out, makes impossible, destroys, prevents the exercise of—free will and moral responsibility of standard agents in worlds at which determinism is true, i.e. it is impossible for a standard agent to exercise free will and moral responsibility (at least in part) because they are subject to deterministic laws of nature.

ZAP-2016 is invalid. Like ZA-2012, there is an explanatory gap between the proposition that is entailed by the premises and the proposition that is expressed by the conclusion.

Since ZAP-2016’s invalidity is not immediately obvious to everyone, some commentary on its invalidity is called for. The reader will note that ZAP-2016’s premises entail that possibly, someone exercises free will in a universe without deterministic laws, but they do not tell us why no one acts freely in universes with deterministic laws. For all that is said in the premises of this argument, it may simply be a brute fact that no humans act freely when determinism is true. This means that although ZAP-2016 was specifically introduced to solve the explanatory gap objection ZA-2012, it nonetheless succumbs to it: the relevance-relation-affirming “because” clause in ZAP-2016’s conclusion does not follow from the argument’s three premises. ZAP-2016 is deductively invalid, and to infer its conclusion from its premises is to commit the cum hoc, ergo propter hoc fallacy.

Clearly there are norms and narratives in place which make it easy for free-will theorists to overlook—or at least think it is wise to ignore—the fallacious reasoning found in arguments such as ZA-2012 and ZAP-2016, so it will be useful to more fully expose the invalidity in ZAP-2016’s underlying logical form. In giving ZA-2016, De Marco is de re proposing that the conjunction of possibilism and the incompossibility solution to the correlation problem guarantees that a broadly causal luck solution to (E2) is correct—and, by extension, that all rival solutions to (E2) are incorrect. As such, we may summarize De Marco’s commitments by restating ZAP-2016 as follows, hereafter “ZAP-2020”:

  • ZAP-2020

  • P1. The incompossibility solution to the correlation problem is true (assuming that both premises of the original Zygote Argument are true).

  • P2. Possibilism, the view that free will is metaphysically possible, is true.

  • C. A broadly causal luck solution to (E2) of the explanation problem is correct; non-causal solutions, such as the strict constitutive luck solution, are incorrect.

De Marco implies that there is no value in calling the substantively difference propositions expressed in P1 and C of ZAP-2020 by different names (De Marco 2016: 1623–1624). This is surprising, since he grants that it is fallacious to infer C from P1 alone (he grants this when he grants that ZA-2012 is invalid). By contrast, I advise that the propositions expressed in C and P1 should be given distinct names on the grounds that free-will theorists otherwise tend to conflate these substantively different claims and overlook the fact that it is fallacious to infer C from P1. I also think that the term ‘incompossibilism’ is an apt name to pick out the incompossibility thesis stated in P1, and introducting a new term for P1 allows us to continue using ‘incompatibilism’ (as it traditionally has been) to name roughly the explanatory thesis stated in C.

Using my preferred terminology and taxonomy of free-will views, we can give an even more incisive summary the underlying structure of ZAP-2016 and ZA-2020, an argument I will call the “Core Argument”Footnote 24:

The premises of the Core Argument entail that possibly, someone exercises free will in a universe without deterministic laws,Footnote 29 but they do not tell us why someone cannot act freely in universes with deterministic laws. The premises of the Core Argument do not tell us that deterministic causation or deterministic laws, qua being deterministic, pose a direct threat to free will. Nor do the premises of the Core Argument tell us that there is something special about the subset of metaphysically possible beings who are subject to the laws which make them unfree.Footnote 30 That is, the premises of the Core Argument do not indicate that the “subject to the laws” constraint on incompossibilism (the view De Marco picks out with the phrase “compatibilism is false”) tracks a freedom-relevant feature of agents.Footnote 31 In other words, the premises of the Core Argument do not tell us whether it is relevant to one’s ability to act freely that one is (or is not) subject to the laws, yet the conclusion clearly asserts that it is partly because people are subject to deterministic laws that they lack free will when determinism is true. In other words, there is still a sizable explanatory gap between the explanatory claim expressed in the Core Argument’s conclusion and the more modest non-explanatory conclusion entailed by the Core Argument’s premises. The Core Argument is subject to the explanatory gap objection—and, by extension, so is ZAP-2016 and ZAP-2020.

Having seen that ZAP-2016 is patently subject to the same type of explanatory gap objection as the original Zygote Argument, De Marco’s second attempt to rescue Mele’s argument from the explanatory-gap objection does not merely fall short of its aims; it falls short of qualifying as a viable attempt to address the problem. Moreover, since ZAP-2016 is invalid, this argument does not, pace De Marco, give us “reason to reject Mickelson’s thesis that such arguments need to be supplemented with an inference to the best explanation in order to be valid” (De Marco 2016: 1625).Footnote 32 Indeed, De Marco provides the reader with no reason to question my argument for the claim that closing the explanatory gap between an incompossiblity solution to the correlation problem and a specific candidate solution to (E2) of the explanation problem—at least in the context of manipulation arguments—requires a best-explanation argument.

5 Minimizing Vs. Closing the Explanatory Gap

Although De Marco’s conclusion-preserving solution technically fails, the reader might think that it still adequately addresses the explanatory gap objection: adding the assumption of possibilism to incompossibilism does not close the explanatory gap between an incompossibility solution to the correlation problem and a causal-luck solution to (E2) of the explanation problem, but perhaps it minimizes the gap to the point that it is no longer worrisome. After all, if possibilism is true and so is incompossibilism, what other than deterministic laws could account for the lack of free human agents in deterministic universes? What better explanation could there be?

This question is worth raising because it exposes the problem with De Marco’s claim that he does not partake in best-explanation reasoning by adding the assumption of possibilism to the premises of ZA-2012:

Notice that nothing of what I have said above [in constructing ZAP-2016] amounts to an inference to the best explanation. Adding C [the assumption of possibilism] to the Zygote Argument [ZA-2012], or to manipulation arguments for incompatibilism [i.e. arguments for a broadly causal-luck solution to (E2) of the explanation problem], would not thereby make it a best explanation argument, nor would it need to be supplemented by one. (De Marco 2016: 1626)

Contrary to what De Marco’s commentary implies, there is more to a best-explanation argument than asserting a speculative explanatory claim. Among other things, one must build up a case for one’s preferred explanation by carefully considering viable alternative explanations and showing that one’s preferred explanation is better than its rivals.

Instead of taking up this difficult work (cf. Mickelson 2019a, 2019b), De Marco takes a dialectical shortcut: adding possibilism to the premises of ZA-2012 allows him to reject out of hand a swath of explanatory claims which imply that free will is impossible for reasons which have nothing whatever to do with the laws of nature. For instance, I have demonstrated that ZA-2013 may be used as the foundation for a manipulation which supports G. Strawson’s constitutive luck solution to (E2) of the explanation problem, from which it follows that all broadly causal luck solutions are false (Mickelson 2015b: 2923; see also my “master manipulation argumen” in Mickelson 2019b). To assume that possibilism is true, however, is to assume that G. Strawson’s preferred explanation for the impossibility free will—and, a fortiori, its spurious incompossibility with every possible phenomena (from fluffy kittens to atom bombs and deterministic laws)—is false.

In the light of the discussion above, the dialectical role played by ZAP-2016’s possibilism-affirming premise is now clear: this premise rules out all extant candidate solutions to (E2) which conflict with traditional causal luck solutions to (E2).Footnote 33 By adding possibilism to the premises of ZA-2012, De Marco clears away rivals to the broadly causal-luck explanation for the incompossibility without having to engage with them. He thereby clears the way for a best-explanation inference to the conclusion that deterministic laws undermine human free will. Pace De Marco, then, adding possibilism to the premises of the original Zygote Argument to create an argument incompatibilism (i.e. a broadly causal luck solution to (E2) of the explanation problem) is to engage in a type of best-explanation reasoning after all.Footnote 34

Moreover, as the careful reader may have already noticed, adding possibilism to the premises of ZA-2012 (i.e. to the assumption that the incompossibility solution to the correlation problem is correct) is, in effect, to assume that some libertarian-friendly account of free will is correct.Footnote 35 By “libertarian-friendly,” I simply mean those accounts of free will which include at least one necessary condition which cannot be satisfied by a normal human when determinism is true, but can be satisfied (along with all the other necessary conditions on free will) when determinism is false. De Marco gives us no reason to think that it is dialectically felicitous to assume that a libertarianism-friendly account of free will is correct in a manipulation argument for incompatibilism. That is, De Marco gives us no reason to suppose that it is dialectically felicitous to assume that some libertarian-friendly solution to (E1) of the explanation problem is correct in an argument which purports to show that an incompossibility solution to the correlation problem is true, i.e. that all compossibility-friendly accounts of free will are false.

At precisely what point in the unfolding of a manipulation argument—if any—is it dialectically felicitous for a philosopher to appeal to their preferred libertarian-friendly account of free will to make their case for the causal luck solution to (E2) and against, for instance, a strict constitutive luck solution? Is a broadly causal luck explanation for the incompossibility of free will and deterministic laws available only to those who are already committed to the truth of a specific libertarian-friendly view of free will?Footnote 36 Can defenders of any type of libertarian-friendly account of free will (e.g. both event-causal and agent-causal views) accept the premises and conclusion of the Core Argument, or only a subset? That is, can those who embrace a libertarian-friendly account of free will argue for a broadly causal luck solution to (E2) of the explanation problem without begging the question against both those philosophers who accept a compossibility solution to the correlation problem as well as those impossibilists who (like G. Strawson) reject libertarian-friendly accounts of free will? Does this discussion of the Zygote Argument have connections to the similar on-going disputes about the Consequence Argument, e.g. that it is question-beginning (cf. Fischer and Pendergraft 2013) and that it may not (contrary to popular billing) support any specific solution to (E2) of the explanation problem (cf. Campbell 2007: 111)? These fruitful new questions are raised by the explanatory gap objection, and their answers are by no means obvious. Since De Marco aims to trivialize the explanatory gap objection when he claims that it easily answered and rests upon distinctions that are not worth “fussing” over, he overlooks the interesting questions and fruitful new lines of inquiry that this objection have opened up.

6 Conclusion

In this essay, I have argued that both of De Marco’s proposed solutions to my explanatory gap objection are nonstarters. De Marco’s “initial solution” describes a successful premise-preserving solution to the objection but it cannot be credited to him: he merely repeats—using his own preferred and arguably problematic jargonFootnote 37—a type of premise-preserving solution that I had already identified and Mele had already adopted. De Marco’s second solution consists in an invalid variant of the Zygote Argument which, like Mele’s original argument, is subject to the explanatory gap objection. Finally, De Marco failed to see that best-explanation reasoning plays a covert role in making his new Zygote Argument (ZAP-2016) appear valid. This means that De Marco fails to challenge my claim that there is no (non-question-begging way) to close the gap between an incompossibility solution to the correlation problem and a specific solution (e.g. a broadly causal luck solution) to (E2) of the explanation problem without using best-explanation reasoning.

If closing the explanatory gap between mere incompossibility views and views about what explains/accounts for that incompossibility were as trivial and philosophically uninteresting as many free-will specialists appear to think, then why is fully closing the gap between an incompossibility solution to the correlation problem and a broadly causal luck solution to (E2) of the explanation problem proving to be so difficult? This question remains—along with many other interesting questions raised by the explanatory gap objection—unanswered. In my assessment, such questions help us to see the project of closing the explanatory gap for what it is: a surprisingly difficult and potentially illuminating philosophical challenge.