Skip to main content
Log in

Naïve Realism and the Relationality of Phenomenal Character

  • Published:
Topoi Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Naïve realism (also called ‘relationalism’ or ‘object view’) is becoming increasingly popular, but the specific outline of its commitments remains often underspecified by proponents and misunderstood by critics. Naïve realism is associated with two claims, both concerning genuine, veridical perceptual experience (where this excludes hallucinations). Constitutive Claim (CC): The phenomenal character of perception is (partly) constituted by the mind-independent objects in one’s surrounding and their properties. Relational Claim (RC): Perception is a relation to mind-independent objects in the environment and their properties. Some philosophers use the two claims interchangeably while talking about naïve realism, while others use only one or the other, although they do not explicitly discuss if the other claim is also a core commitment of naïve realism, or if naïve realism can be held without the other claim. This raises the question of how RC and CC relate to one another, together with the most pressing question of what each claim ultimately commits one to. After discussing the shortcomings of alternative interpretations, I argue that naïve realism should be understood as committed to, first and foremost, RC. This should be understood as a claim about the phenomenal character of perception, rather than about its nature, structure or essence (whatever that means). CC, on the other hand, should be understood as a corollary of RC. This doesn’t only offer a better characterisation of how naïve realists understand phenomenal character: it also helps us understand how we can simultaneously claim that the object of perception is a constitutive element of perception, while also allowing for it to play a causal role in determining perception.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Notice that Kind and Soteriou characterise weak transparency in different ways. Here I follow Soteriou. For an overview of the debate on transparency and a discussion of further distinctions in the way the claim has been made, see Bordini (2023).

  2. Strong intentionalism claims that the phenomenal character of perceptual experiences is fully determined by its representational content, while weak intentionalism claims that qualia account for the phenomenal character of perceptual experiences. Notice that sometimes these positions sometimes go by different names. Here I follow the terminology adopted by Crane (2001, Ch: 3, §25), to which I also refer for a detailed discussion of the debate.

  3. Alternatively, one could read CC as a causal claim, saying that the phenomenal character of a perception causally depend on the object perceived and their features in such a way that it would not be what it is, were the object absent or different. However, this can’t be what naïve realists intend, since almost anybody (irrespective of their account of perception) would accept that the phenomenal character is causally sensitive to the objects perceived, to the point that the claim verges on the trivial.

  4. This explains how naïve realism is most often understood as entailing disjunctivism: if the object is part of the essence or real definition of the phenomenal character of perception, then a hallucination, where the object is lacking, can’t have the same phenomenal character. The fact that some have argued that naïve realism can be upheld without committing to disjunctivism reflects the fact that not everyone agrees on what naïve realism entails, due to the ambiguity affecting the formulation of both CC and RC. Other strategies to defend a non-disjunctive versions of naïve realism rely on arguing that objects (although non-standard) are also constituents of the phenomenal character of hallucination (Raleigh 2014, Ali 2018).

  5. Similarly, Boyd Millar (who, unlike Nudds, is not a sympathiser of naïve realism) claims: “Naïve realism is the view that when you perceive a particular object, the phenomenology of your perceptual experience is constituted by your standing in the acquaintance relation to that object and certain of its properties.” (Millar 2015: 607).

  6. ‘Consciousness’ and ‘phenomenal character’ are not always used as synonymous, but I take it that, in the debate I am considering, ‘phenomenal character’ is taken to refer to the conscious aspect of perception (sometimes called ‘conscious character’), to what it is like for the subject to undergo the experience. Thus, for the current purposes, what makes perception conscious is at least coextensive with its phenomenal character.

  7. For a defence of the claim that relational facts can’t change their relation-constituents, see, for instance, Fine (2000: 5).

  8. Interestingly, here Strawson uses this idea to object to Snowdon (1998). In this paper, Snowdon suggests that a naïve realist view, according to which “the visible facts are constituents of the experience” (Snowdon 1998: 302) can secure a non-accidental link between the object and perception better than the causal link posited by causal theories of perception. Against Snowdon, Strawson argues that the idea that “natural items themselves could be logically linked is nonsense, a category howler” (Strawson 1998: 314): only things capable of truth and falsity can be logically connected. Thus, only a description of perception can be said to entail the existence of the object, not perception itself. Here Strawson fails to see that the relation between perception (or its phenomenal character) is not merely logical, but metaphysical, in the sense I elucidated in §1.3 and 3.

  9. Naïve realism is not incompatible with claiming that perception has a representational content. It is incompatible with claiming that the phenomenal character is determined by the representational content. Therefore, even a naïve realist might allow for perception to have a representational content (see Locatelli and Wilson 2017).

  10. The idea that the intermediate cause (the brain state) should not be confused with a psychological event goes back to Hinton (1973; 75–87).

  11. One might object that this leaves open a further question. If one accepts that the perception is directly caused by the brain state, and the brain state itself could occur in the absence of the object, it is tempting to think that the effect produced by the brain state should itself be independent of the object. But this would be a different strand of objection from the one I am concerned with here, and one that has been already largely dealt with by naïve realists and I don’t have space to rehearse here (see in particular Fish 2009 and Martin 2004; 2006). There is no good reason to think that the same brain state could not give rise to an event which is most appropriately characterised disjunctively, as either a perception (the obtaining of a relation with the object) or a hallucination (which only seems a perception). This is motivated idea through an appeal to either a local supervenience principle, or the ‘same proximate cause same effect’ principle. However, locally supervenience is highly disputable (see Fish 2009 for a discussion) and the same proximate cause same immediate effect principle, if at all acceptable, should allow for background conditions and non-causal constitutive elements affecting the nature of the outcome of the proximate cause (see Martin 2004, 2006 for a discussion).

References

  • Ali R (2018) Does hallucinating involve perceiving? Philos Stud 175(3):601–627. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-017-0884-7

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Beck O (2017) Rethinking Naive Realism. Philos Stud 1–27

  • Bordini D (2023) Seeing through transparency. https://philarchive.org/rec/BORSTT-4.

  • Brewer B (2008) ‘How to account for illusion. In: Haddock A, Macpherson F (eds) Disjunctivism: perception, action, knowledge. Oxford University Press, pp 168–180

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Brewer (2011) Perception and its objects. Oxford University Press, USA

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Burge T (2010) Origins of objectivity. Oxford University Press, Oxford

  • Child W (1992) Vision and experience: the causal theory and the disjunctive conception. Philos Q 42(168):297–316

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Crane T (2001) Elements of mind: an introduction to the philosophy of mind. Oxford University Press, Oxford

  • Davidson D (1967) Causal relations. J Phil 64(21):691–703

  • Eilan N (2017) Perceptual objectivity and consciousness: a relational response to Burge’s challenge. Topoi 36(2):287–298. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11245-015-9325-4

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fine K (1995) Ontological dependence. Proc Aristot Soc 95(1):269–290

  • Fine K (2000) Neutral relations. Phil Rev 109(1):1–33

  • Fish WC (2009) Perception, hallucination, and illusion. Oxford University Press, USA

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Genone J (2016) Recent work on naive realism. Am Philos Q 53(1):1–25

    Google Scholar 

  • Hinton JM (1973) Experiences: an inquiry into some ambiguities. Clarendon Press, Oxford

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Kind A (2003) What’s so transparent about transparency? Philos Stud 115(3):225–244

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Koslicki K (2012) Varieties of ontological dependence. In: Schnieder B, Correia F (eds) Metaphysical grounding: understanding the structure of reality. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, pp 186–213

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Locatelli R, Wilson KA (2017) Perception without representation. Topoi 36(2):197–212

    Article  PubMed  PubMed Central  Google Scholar 

  • Martin MGF (1997) The reality of appearances. In: Sainsbury M (ed) Thought and ontology. Franco Angeli

    Google Scholar 

  • Martin (2004) The limits of self-awareness. Philos Stud 120(1–3):37–89

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Martin (2006) On being alienated. In: Gendler TS, Hawthorne J (eds) Perceptual experience. Oxford University Press, Oxford

  • Millar B (2015) Naïve realism and illusion. Ergo 2:607–625

  • Nanay B (2014) The representationalism versus relationalism debate: explanatory contextualism about perception. Eur J Philos 23(1):321–336

    Google Scholar 

  • Nudds M (2009) Recent work in perception: naïve realism and its opponents. Analysis 69(2):334–346

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Raleigh T (2014) A new approach to “perfect” hallucinations. J Conscious Stud 21(11–12):81–110

    Google Scholar 

  • Russell B (1992) Theory of knowledge: the 1913 manuscript. Routledge

    Google Scholar 

  • Snowdon PF (1998) Strawson on the concept of perception. The philosophy of P.F. Strawson. Open Court, Chicago

    Google Scholar 

  • Soteriou M (2011) The perception of absence, space, and time. In: Roessler J, Lerman H, Eilan N (eds) Perception, causation, and objectivity. Oxford University Press, Oxford

  • Soteriou (2013) The mind’s construction: the ontology of mind and mental action. Oxford University Press, Oxford

  • Soteriou (2014) The disjunctive theory of perception. In: Zalta EN (ed) The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2010/entries/perception-disjunctive/.

  • Strawson PF (1988) Perception and its objects. In Dancy J (ed) Perceptual knowledge. Oxford University Press. reprinted in: Bernecker S, Dretske FI (eds) (2000) Knowledge: readings in contemporary epistemology. Oxford University Press, New York, pp 452–467

  • Steenhagen M (2019) Must naive realists be relationalists? Eur J Philos 27(4):1002–1015

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Strawson PF (1998) Reply to Paul Snowdon. The philosophy of P.F. Strawson. Open Court, Chicago

  • Tye M (1995) What “What It Is Like” Is Like. Analysis 55:125

    Google Scholar 

  • Wiggins D (1968) On being in the same place at the same time. Phil Rev 77 (1):90–95

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Roberta Locatelli.

Ethics declarations

Conflict of interest

The author has no conflict of interest to disclose.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Springer Nature or its licensor (e.g. a society or other partner) holds exclusive rights to this article under a publishing agreement with the author(s) or other rightsholder(s); author self-archiving of the accepted manuscript version of this article is solely governed by the terms of such publishing agreement and applicable law.

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Locatelli, R. Naïve Realism and the Relationality of Phenomenal Character. Topoi 43, 221–231 (2024). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11245-023-09953-y

Download citation

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11245-023-09953-y

Keywords

Navigation