Skip to main content
Log in

Can the Russellian Monist Escape the Epiphenomenalist’s Paradox?

  • Published:
Topoi Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Russellian monism—an influential doctrine proposed by Russell (The analysis of matter, Routledge, London, 1927/1992)—is roughly the view that physics can only ever tell us about the causal, dispositional, and structural properties of physical entities and not their categorical (or intrinsic) properties, whereas our qualia are constituted by those categorical properties. In this paper, I will discuss the relation between Russellian monism and a seminal paradox facing epiphenomenalism, the paradox of phenomenal judgment: if epiphenomenalism is true—qualia are causally inefficacious—then any judgment concerning qualia, including epiphenomenalism itself, cannot be caused by qualia. For many writers, including Hawthorne (Philos Perspect 15:361–378, 2001), Smart (J Conscious Stud 11(2):41–50, 2004), and Braddon-Mitchell and Jackson (The philosophy of mind and cognition, Blackwell, Malden, 2007), Russellian monism faces the same paradox as epiphenomenalism does. I will assess Chalmers’s (The conscious mind: in search of a fundamental theory. Oxford University Press, New York, 1996) and Seager’s (in: Beckermann A, McLaughlin BP (eds) The Oxford handbook of philosophy of mind. Oxford University Press, New York, 2009) defences of Russellian monism against the paradox, and will put forward a novel argument against those defences.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Some philosophers call these properties ‘intrinsic properties’ instead. That does not affect the structure of RM and the arguments I will discuss.

  2. Robinson (2018) provides another interesting comparison between RM and epiphenomenalism. While my discussion is compatible with and potentially relevant to his, his concern is not PPJ.

  3. See Chalmers (1996) for a detailed overview.

  4. A rival view is that the connections between categorical and dispositional properties are contingent: it is possible for the same categorical property to play different dispositional roles under different laws of nature (see, for example, Langton 1998; Lewis 2009).

  5. Another possible interpretation is that the two kinds of properties are identical. See Sect. 4.1 for a discussion of this view.

  6. I assume that most readers are familiar with Chalmers’s zombie argument and thus will not introduce it here.

  7. Our actual categorical bases are assumed not to be zombie bases for the sake of the argument, because we are assuming that RM is true. However, without the assumption that RM is true, it is possible that our actual categorical bases are zombie bases.

  8. I am heavily indebted to Frank Jackson for a discussion with respect to this point.

  9. While Nozick’s account is seminal, it has some more developed variants in the literature which take probability, distance between possible worlds, and so on into account. For the sake of simplicity, however, I shall not discuss them.

  10. Heil’s identity theory does not allow for multiple realisability and is thus much stronger than the identity theory used by Smart (2007) to explain the mind/body relation.

  11. It is noteworthy that, in a seminal paper on metaphysics (2005), Heil provides some independent reasons for rejecting the idea of multiple realisability. With this in mind, he might reasonably reject the implication. Nonetheless, the rejection of multiple realisability is, doubtlessly, a very radical view which very few would accept.

  12. Of course, we may not know exactly how to bridge the gap, but a view widely accepted among scientists and physicalist philosophers is: contemporary brain sciences lead us to expect that advances in those disciplines will eventually reveal the answer to the question, and to thereby believe that physicalism is true (see, for example, Churchland 1996; Hohwy and Frith 2004; Chan and Latham forthcoming).

  13. This view is in fact very similar to an assumption of RM: the scientific categorical ignorance thesis (see Sect. 1).

  14. I am indebted to Daniel Stoljar for raising this objection.

References

  • Armstrong D (1961) Perception and the physical world. Routledge, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Blackburn S (1990) Filling in space. Analysis 50(2):62–65

    Google Scholar 

  • Braddon-Mitchell D, Jackson F (2007) The philosophy of mind and cognition, 2nd edn. Blackwell, Malden

    Google Scholar 

  • Campbell K (1984) Body and mind, 2nd edn. University of Notre Dame Press, Notre Dame

    Google Scholar 

  • Chalmers D (1996) The conscious mind: in search of a fundamental theory. Oxford University Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Chalmers D (2002) Does conceivability entail possibility? In: Gendler TS, Hawthorne J (eds) Conceivability and possibility. Oxford University Press, Oxford, pp 145–200

    Google Scholar 

  • Chalmers D (2003) Consciousness and its place in nature. In: Stich DS, Warfield F (eds) The Blackwell guide to philosophy of mind. Blackwell, Malden, pp 102–142

    Google Scholar 

  • Chan LC, Latham AJ (Forthcoming) Four meta-methods for the study of qualia. Erkenntnis

  • Churchland PS (1996) The hornswoggle problem. J Conscious Stud 3(5–6):402–408

    Google Scholar 

  • Dennett D (1991) Consciousness explained. Back Bay Books, Boston

    Google Scholar 

  • Harman G (1986) Moral explanations of natural facts—can moral claims be tested against moral reality? South J Philos 24:57–68

    Google Scholar 

  • Hawthorne J (2001) Causal structuralism. Philos Perspect 15:361–378

    Google Scholar 

  • Heil J (2003) From an ontological point of view. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Heil J (2004) Philosophy of mind, 2nd edn. Routledge, New York

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Heil J 2005, Dispositions. Synthese 144(3):343–356

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hohwy J, Frith C (2004) Can neuroscience explain consciousness?. J Conscious Stud 11(7/8):180–198

    Google Scholar 

  • Jackson F (1982) Epiphenomenal qualia. Philos Q 32:127–136

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jackson F (1998) From metaphysics to ethics: a defence of conceptual analysis. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Joyce R (2016) ‘Evolution, truth-tracking, and moral skepticism’. In: Essays in moral skepticism. Oxford University Press, Oxford, pp 142–158

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Kim J (2005) Physicalism, or something near enough. Princeton University Press, Princeton

    Google Scholar 

  • Langton R (1998) Kantian humility: our ignorance of things in themselves. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Levine J (1983) Materialism and qualia: the explanatory gap. Pac Philos Q 64:354–361

    Google Scholar 

  • Lewis D (2009) Ramseyan humility. In: Braddon-Mitchell D, Nola R (eds) Conceptual analysis and philosophical naturalism. MIT Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Locke D (2009) A partial defense of Ramseyan humility. In: Braddon-Mitchell D, Nola R (eds) Conceptual analysis and philosophical naturalism. MIT Press, Cambridge, pp 223–242

    Google Scholar 

  • Nozick R (1981) Philosophical explanations. Harvard University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Oderberg D (2009) The non-identity of the categorical and the dispositional. Analysis 69(4):677–684

    Google Scholar 

  • Robinson W (2012) Phenomenal realist physicalism implies coherency of epiphenomenalist meaning. J Conscious Stud 19(3–4):145–163

    Google Scholar 

  • Robinson W (2018) Russellian monism and epiphenomenalism. Pac Philos Q 99(1):100–117

    Google Scholar 

  • Russell B (1927/1992) The analysis of matter. Routledge, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Seager W (2009) Panpsychism. In: Beckermann A, McLaughlin BP (eds) The Oxford handbook of philosophy of mind. Oxford University Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Smart JJC (1959) Sensations and brain processes. Philos Rev 68(2):141–156

    Google Scholar 

  • Smart JJC (2004) Consciousness and awareness. J Conscious Stud 11(2):41–50

    Google Scholar 

  • Smart JJC (2007) The Mind/brain identity theory. In: Zalta E (ed.), Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy. http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/mind-identity/. Retrieved 25 Oct 2017

  • Stoljar D (2001) The conceivability argument and two conceptions of the physical. Philos Perspect 15(s15):393–413

    Google Scholar 

  • Stoljar D (2014) Four kinds of Russellian monism. In: Kriegel U (ed) Current controversies in philosophy of mind. Routledge, New York, pp 17–39

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

The author would like to acknowledge David Braddon-Mitchell, Belinda Calderone, Michael Duncan, Frank Jackson, Justine Kingsbury, Andrew James Latham, James Norton, Luke Roelofs, Daniel Stoljar, Lei Zhong, the philosophy of mind group at the Australian National University, and participants in my presentations of this paper at the University of Sydney and the National Taiwan University for their useful discussions or comments. Special thanks are due to Belinda Rickard.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Lok-Chi Chan.

Ethics declarations

Ethical Approval

This article does not contain any studies with human participants or animals performed by any of the authors.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Chan, LC. Can the Russellian Monist Escape the Epiphenomenalist’s Paradox?. Topoi 39, 1093–1102 (2020). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11245-018-9579-8

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11245-018-9579-8

Keywords

Navigation