Skip to main content
Log in

Carroll’s Infinite Regress and the Act of Diagramming

  • Published:
Topoi Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

The infinite regress of Carroll’s ‘What the Tortoise said to Achilles’ is interpreted as a problem in the epistemology of mathematical proof. An approach to the problem that is both diagrammatic and non-logical is presented with respect to a specific inference of elementary geometry.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. See (Avigad 2003).

  2. Prawitz analyzes the meaning of these logical notions in the terms of the notion of a proposition’s ground. The result is an account where the basic logical inferences—i.e. those logical inferences where the necessity of the conclusion is immediately seen—correspond directly to the the introduction and elimination rules of natural deduction. For the details, see (Prawitz 2012).

  3. One may wonder if an analogous claim holds also of A in Carroll’s ABZ inference. (One may wonder this even even if identity is understood to be a logical notion. The notion of equality in the inference is not the notion of identity. Rather, it concerns whether two possibly distinct lengths have the same magnitude.) I believe a case can be made that an inference from B to Z is valid and non-logical, but this would require an in-depth analysis of Euclid’s notion of equal magnitude, which is beyond the scope of this paper.

    On the other hand, if we go by the treatment of the equality of magnitude in the Elements, the inference from B to Z is not on its own justified. In contrast to order relations like ‘x is before y’, the equality of magnitude is explicitly declared to be transitive in an axiom given in the common notions of book I (the axiom is in fact premise A in Carroll’s syllogism). This fits with Manders’ analysis of Euclid’s proof method in Manders (2008). ‘x is before y’ is a co-exact relation and thus the method permits one to use diagrams to reason about it. On the other hand, equality of magnitude is an exact relation, and the method demands that all reasoning involving it be made explicit in propositions. I will discuss Manders’ analysis in more detail in the conclusion.

  4. Prawitz in fact identifies an inference akin to \(\alpha\) as valid and non-logical in Prawitz (2013). It is: Adam is longer than Beatrice, Beatrice is longer than Carlo. Therefore, Adam is longer than Carlo.

  5. A similar point concerning C′s relation to \(\alpha '\) can be made. As observed above, it is natural to interpret C as a model-theoretic statement—i.e. if A and B are true in a model \(\mathcal {M}\), then Z is true in model \(\mathcal {M}\). It thus provides some information about inference \(\alpha '\). This information, however, is not necessary to justify the inference.

    The idea here is formulated from a more general perspective in Michael Detlefsen’s interpretation of Poincaré’s philosophical writings on mathematics in Detlefsen (1992). According to Detlefsen, non-logical mathematical inferences such as \(\alpha\) are central to Poincaré’s epistemology of mathematics. “In the case of Poincaréan proof, the key feature is the grasping or intuiting the mathematical architecture between p [the premise of a mathematical inference] and c [the conclusion of a mathematical inference] (p. 368).” In making a non-logical mathematical inference logical by adding a premise that expresses a universal feature of the given mathematical subject—as is done in the move from \(\alpha\) to \(\alpha '\)—one “abstracts away from this grasp of architecture itself and instead focuses on its net classical effect...[a logical proof] separates or detaches the net classical effect of a warrant or justification from that warrant or justification itself. It then replaces the actual grasp or comprehension of the underlying justification with reflection on the semantic or epistemic status thus abstracted from it (p. 369).”

  6. I assume in what follows that a similar difficulty does not arise with respect to the visual verification of statements of fact.

  7. For ease of exposition, I describe only the case where the diagram is constructed from the premises in the first stage. The same point applies mutatis mutandis to the case where the diagram is verified to satisfy the premise.

  8. A similar procedure, termed integration of premises, is posited as fundamental in the psychological theory of reasoning presented in Knauff’s (2013). Knauff’s theory, in fact, is built around an account of inferences that exploit the transitivity of a linear order like \(\alpha\).

  9. For these rules in Eu and E, see Section 5.2 of ‘The technical notions of Eu’ at www.john.mumma.org/Writings.html and Section 3.4 of Avigad et al. (2009), respectively.

References

  • Avigad J (2003) Number theory and elementary arithmetic. Philosophia Mathematica 11:257–284

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Avigad J, Dean E, Mumma J (2009) A formal system for Euclid’s elements. Rev Symb Log 2:700–768

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Carroll L (1895) What the tortoise said to achilles. Mind 104:691–693

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Detlefsen M (1992) Poincaré against the logicians. Synthese 90:349–378

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hilbert D (1971) Foundations of geometry. Open Court Publishing Company, La Salle

    Google Scholar 

  • Knauff M (2013) Space to reason: a spatial theory of human thought. MIT Press, Cambridge

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Manders K (2008) The Euclidean diagram. In: Mancosu (ed) Philosophy of mathematical practice. Clarendon Press, Oxford, pp 112–183

    Google Scholar 

  • Mumma J (2010) Proofs, pictures, and Euclid. Synthese 175:255–287

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pasch M (1882) Vorlesungen über neure geometrie. B.G. Teubner, Leipzig

    Google Scholar 

  • Prawitz D (2005) Logical consequence from a constructivist point of view. In: Shapiro S (ed) Oxford handbook of philosophy of math and logic. Oxford University Press, Oxford, pp 671–695

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Prawitz D (2009) Inference and knowedge. In: Pělis M (ed) Logica yearbook 2008. College Publications, London, pp 175–192

    Google Scholar 

  • Prawitz D (2012) The epistemic significance of valid inference. Synthese 187:887–898

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Prawitz D (2013) Validity of inference. In: Frauchiger M (ed) Reference, rationality, and phenomenlogy: themes from F\(\upphi\)llesdol. Ontos Verlag, Heusenstamm, pp 179–204

    Google Scholar 

  • Stroud B (1979) Inference, belief, and understanding. Mind 88:179–196

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to John Mumma.

Ethics declarations

Conflict of interest

There were no sources of funding for this paper, and so no conflicts of interest exist.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Mumma, J. Carroll’s Infinite Regress and the Act of Diagramming. Topoi 38, 619–626 (2019). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11245-017-9530-4

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11245-017-9530-4

Keywords

Navigation