Skip to main content
Log in

Do Conventions Need to Be Common Knowledge?

  • Published:
Topoi Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Do conventions need to be common knowledge in order to work? David Lewis builds this requirement into his definition of a convention. This paper explores the extent to which his approach finds support in the game theory literature. The knowledge formalism developed by Robert Aumann and others militates against Lewis’s approach, because it shows that it is almost impossible for something to become common knowledge in a large society. On the other hand, Ariel Rubinstein’s Email Game suggests that coordinated action is no less hard for rational players without a common knowledge requirement. But an unnecessary simplifying assumption in the Email Game turns out to be doing all the work, and the current paper concludes that common knowledge is better excluded from a definition of the conventions that we use to regulate our daily lives.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Fig. 1
Fig. 2
Fig. 3

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. All equilibria in two-person, zero-sum games are interchangeable and payoff-equivalent.

  2. John Maynard Smith (1982) defines an evolutionarily stable strategy as a best reply to itself that is a better reply to any alternative best reply than the alternative best reply is to itself, but biologists don’t seem to worry much about the small print involving alternative best replies.

  3. When outcomes other than just winning or losing can arise, it is necessary to interpret the payoffs as Von Neumann and Morgenstern (1944) utilities.

  4. Lewis says that a pure strategy is strictly dominated if it is never a best reply to any strategy combination available to the other players. With this weak definition, it is false that a strictly dominated strategy is never used with positive probability in equilibrium.

  5. When (K4) is assumed, (K0) and (K3) are redundant.

  6. If the true state x lies in a truism T that implies KE, we first show that Alice knows that E has occurred. But if x is in T, then x is in KE, whether or not T is a truism. We next show that if Alice knows that E has occurred, then a truism T has occurred that implies E. Take T = KE. The event T is a truism, because (K3) says that T implies KT. The truism T must have occurred, because to say that Alice knows that E has occurred means that the true state x lies in KE = T.

  7. Wherever something is asserted to be known in the standard theory, say instead that it is believed with probability at least p.

  8. We identify a player’s informational state with the numbers of messages the player thinks it possible may have been sent. Thus {0,1} is the state in which Alice thinks either 0 or 1 messages have been sent. If Alice plays the default action DOVE in this state, it is optimal for Bob to play DOVE at {1,2}. On finding himself in this informational state, Bob believes it more likely that the number of messages is 1 rather than 2, because the second message can only go astray if the first message is received. Can it then be optimal for him to play HAWK? The most favorable case is when each of the two alternatives is equally likely, and Alice is planning to play DOVE in the informational state {2,3}. Bob might as well then be playing against someone playing each strategy in the ordinary Stag Hunt Game with equal probability, so his optimal reply is hawk, which he knows corresponds to DOVE at {1,2}. Similarly, Bob’s play of DOVE in the informational state {1,2} implies that Alice plays DOVE at {2,3}. And so on.

  9. Mathematicians say that there is a discontinuity at infinity. That is to say, when we take the limit as N approaches infinity, we don’t get the same result as when we set N equal to infinity. (Monderer and Samet (1989) argue that we should be taking the limit as p approaches one of the common p-belief operator.)

  10. One can restrict the number of Nash equilibria by imposing costs of sending and receiving messages, but this doesn’t affect the basic result.

  11. The exact Nash equilibria don’t all approximate the Nash bargaining solution N because our computer implementation didn’t allow the players to vary their demands continuously.

References

  • Aumann R (1976) Agreeing to disagree. Ann Stat 4:1236–1239

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Binmore K (1987) Modeling rational players I. Econ Phil 3:9–55

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Binmore K (1994) Playing fair: game theory and the social contract I. MIT Press, Cambridge, MA

    Google Scholar 

  • Binmore K (2005) Natural justice. Oxford University Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Binmore K (2007) Does game theory work? The bargaining challenge. MIT Press, Cambridge MA

    Google Scholar 

  • Binmore K (2007) Playing for real. Oxford University Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Binmore K, Samuelson L (2001) Coordinated action in the electronic mail game. Games Econ Behav 35:6–30

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Binmore K, Swierzbinski J, Hsu S, Proulx C (1993) Focal points and bargaining. Int J Game Theory 22:381–409

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cubitt R, Sugden R (2005) Common reasoning in game theory: a resolution of the paradoxes of ‘common knowledge of rationality’. Centre for Decision Research and Experimental Economics 17, School of Economics, University of Nottingham

  • Halpern JY (1987) Using reasoning about knowledge to analyse distributed systems. Annu Rev Comp Sci 2:37–68

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Harsanyi J (1977) Rational behavior and bargaining equilibrium in games and social situations. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Hume, D (1978) A treatise of human nature, 2nd edn. Clarendon Press, Oxford (edited by Selby-Bigge LA, revised by Nidditch P, first published 1739)

  • Kalai E, Smorodinsky M (1975) Other solutions to Nash’s bargaining problem. Econometrica 45:1623–1630

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lewis D (1969) Convention: a philosophical study. Harvard University Press, Cambridge, MA

    Google Scholar 

  • Maynard Smith J (1982) Evolution and the theory of games. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Monderer D, Samet D (1989) Approximating common knowledge with common beliefs. Games Econ Behav 1:170–190

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Myerson R (1991) Game theory: analysis of conflict. Harvard University Press, Cambridge, MA

    Google Scholar 

  • Nash J (1950) The bargaining problem. Econometrica 18:155–162

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nash J (1951) Non-cooperative games. Ann Math 54:286–295

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rawls J (1972) A theory of justice. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Rousseau J-J (1913) The inequality of man. In: Cole G (ed) Rousseau’s social contract and discourses. Dent, London

  • Rubinstein A (1989) The electronic mail game: strategic behavior under almost common knowledge. Am Econ Rev 70:385–391

    Google Scholar 

  • Schelling T (1960) The strategy of conflict. Harvard University Press, Cambridge MA

    Google Scholar 

  • Skyrms B (1996) Evolution of the social contract. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Skyrms B (2003) The stag hunt and the evolution of the social structure. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Turnbull C (1972) The mountain people. Touchstone, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Von Neumann J, Morgenstern O (1944) The theory of games and economic behavior. Princeton University Press, Princeton

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Ken Binmore.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Binmore, K. Do Conventions Need to Be Common Knowledge?. Topoi 27, 17–27 (2008). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11245-008-9033-4

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11245-008-9033-4

Keywords

Navigation