Skip to main content
Log in

Art, imagination, and experiential knowledge

  • Original Research
  • Published:
Synthese Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

In this paper, I argue that art can help us imagine what it would be like to have experiences we have never had before. I begin by surveying a few of the things we are after when we ask what an experience is like. I maintain that it is easy for art to provide some of them. For example, it can relay facts about what the experience involves or what responses the experience might engender. The tricky case is the phenomenal quality of the experience or what it feels like from the inside. Thus, in the main part of the paper, I discuss how art can provide us with this as well. I conclude by situating my view in the context of the broader debate over transformative experiences. I maintain that art can solve some but not all of the problems that arise when deciding whether to undergo a transformation.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Many philosophers are skeptical about aesthetic testimony. We cannot know, they claim, whether an item is beautiful based on someone else's say-so (for discussion, see Hills, 2020; Hopkins, 2011; Meskin, 2004; Nguyen, 2017; Robson, 2012). But it is usually conceded that we can learn from others whether we are likely to enjoy the item (see Meskin, 2004, p. 72). This is especially true if the testifiers have been reliable indicators of our preferences in the past.

  2. Artists sometimes give expression to their own experiences. In such cases, external confirmation is not required. We are warranted in taking what the artwork reveals at face value.

  3. My account might suggest that works of art direct us much like Lego instructions do. They identify each individual part of the whole and tell us exactly how it combines with the others. While some works of art may proceed in this fashion, most do not. Art typically directs our imagination in less didactic ways. For example, the musical score of a movie sets a mood, and this mood helps to structure our sense of what is happening in the plot. It prompts us to imagine the scenario in a particular way or from a particular perspective without telling us exactly what it is we are to imagine. Metaphors have a similar power. Romeo need not discursively describe the place of Juliet in his world. He can just say, “Juliet is the sun,” and this figure of speech frames our understanding of his experience of young love. One benefit of these non-didactic forms of guidance is that they are open-ended. The meaning of a live metaphor is inexhaustible; the structuring implications of the mood set by a musical score does not have hard and fast limits. This open-endedness helps address the gap problem discussed later in the paper.

  4. When I say that conveying experiential knowledge is art’s domain, I mean that it is something art is capable of doing. I do not mean that it is an artistic function—something a work does by virtue of being art as opposed to something else. I admit that conveying experiential knowledge is not something all or only art can do. I also concede that it may not be part of what makes something good art. Thus, enjoying a work’s ability to reveal what an experience is like may not amount to appreciating it qua art. On all such issues, I wish to remain agnostic.

  5. I would like to thank the anonymous reviewers of this article, as well as Sarah Reynolds, Saul Fisher, Ram Neta, and L. A. Paul, for their invaluable feedback and support. I am also grateful to the participants of the Yale University workshop on transformative experiences, the 2022 Eastern Division Meeting of the American Philosophical Association, and the 2022 Annual Meeting of the Rocky Mountain Division of the American Society for Aesthetics for their insightful comments and discussions.

References

  • Anzaldúa, G. (1987). Borderlands/la frontera: The new mestiza. Aunt Lute Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Arpaly, N. (2020). What is it like to have a crappy imagination? In E. Lambert & J. Schwenkler (Eds.), Becoming someone new: Essays on transformative experience, choice, and change (pp. 122–132). Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Aumann, A. (2021). Form and content in Emily Dickinson’s poetry. In E. Camp (Ed.), The poetry of Emily Dickinson: Philosophical perspectives (pp. 108–144). Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Aumann, A. (2022). Art and transformation. Journal of the American Philosophical Association, 8(4), 567–585. https://doi.org/10.1017/apa.2021.40

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cappelen, H., & Dever, J. (2017). Empathy and transformative experience without the first person point of view (a reply to L.A. Paul). Inquiry, 60(3), 315–336. https://doi.org/10.1080/0020174X.2017.1262018

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Carroll, N. (1990). The philosophy of horror: Or paradoxes of the heart. Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Carroll, N. (2001). Beyond aesthetics: Philosophical essays. Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Cath, Y. (2019). Knowing what it is like and testimony. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 97(1), 105–120. https://doi.org/10.1080/00048402.2018.1433697

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Coninx, S. (2020). Pain, amnesia, and qualitative memory: Conceptual and empirical challenges. Journal of Consciousness Studies, 27(11–12), 126–133.

    Google Scholar 

  • Coplan, A. (2004). Empathic engagement with narrative fictions. The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism, 62(2), 141–152.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Currie, G. (1995). The moral psychology of fiction. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 73(2), 250–259.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • De Brigard, F. (2020). Do we need another kind of memory? Journal of Consciousness Studies, 27(11–12), 134–144.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dennett, D. C. (2020). A history of Qualia. Topoi, 39(1), 5–12. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11245-017-9508-2

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dickinson, E. (1998). The poems of Emily Dickinson. Belknap Press of Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Donnelly, M. (2019). The cognitive value of literary perspectives: Donnelly. The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism, 77(1), 11–22. https://doi.org/10.1111/jaac.12621

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dretske, F. (1981). The pragmatic dimension of knowledge. Philosophical Studies, 40(3), 363–378.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dunn, E. W., Forrin, N. D., & Ashton-James, C. E. (2009). On the excessive rationality of the emotional imagination: A two-systems account of affective forecasts and experiences. In K. D. Markman, W. M. P. Klein, & J. A. Suhr (Eds.), Handbook of imagination and mental simulation (pp. 331–346). Psychology Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ekman, P. (1992). An argument for basic emotions. Cognition & Emotion, 6(3–4), 169–200.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Feagin, S. L. (1996). Reading with feeling: The aesthetics of appreciation. Cornell University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Gerrig, R. J. (1993). Experiencing narrative worlds: On the psychological activities of Reading. Yale University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Gittel, B., Deutschländer, R., & Hecht, M. (2016). Conveying moods and knowledge-what-it-is-like through lyric poetry: An empirical study of authors’ intentions and readers’ responses. Scientific Study of Literature, 6(1), 131–163. https://doi.org/10.1075/ssol.6.1.07git

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Goldman, A. I. (2006). Imagination and simulation in audience responses to fiction. In S. Nichols (Ed.), The architecture of the imagination: new essays on pretence, possibility, and fiction (pp. 41–56). Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Harman, E. (2015). Transformative experiences and reliance on moral testimony. Research Philosophica, 92(2), 323–339. https://doi.org/10.11612/resphil.2015.92.2.8

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hills, A. (2020). Aesthetic Testimony, Understanding and Virtue. Noûs.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hopkins, R. (2011). How to be a pessimist about aesthetic testimony. The Journal of Philosophy, 108(3), 138–157.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ismael, J. (2019). Experience, transformation, and imagination. Rivista Internazionale Di Filosofia e Psicologia, 10(3), 330–338.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kajtár, L. (2016). What mary didn’t read: On literary narratives and knowledge. Ratio, 29(3), 327–343. https://doi.org/10.1111/rati.12098

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kierkegaard, S. (1987). Either/Or, Part II (H. V. Hong & E. H. Hong, Trans.). Princeton University Press.

  • Kind, A. (2020). What imagination teaches. In E. Lambert & J. Schwenkler (Eds.), Becoming someone new: Essays on transformative experience, choice, and change (pp. 133–146). Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Kind, A. (2021). Bridging the divide: Imagining across experiential perspectives. In C. Badura & A. Kind (Eds.), Epistemic uses of imagination (pp. 237–259). Routledge.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Kind, A. (2022). Learning to imagine. The British Journal of Aesthetics, 62(1), 33–48. https://doi.org/10.1093/aesthj/ayab037

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Krishnamurthy, M. (2015). We can make rational decisions to have a child: On the grounds for rejecting L.A. Paul’s arguments. In S. Hannan, S. Brennan, & R. Vernon (Eds.), Permissible progeny? The morality of procreation and parenting (pp. 170–183). Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Le Blon, J. C. (1725). Coloritto: Or the harmony of clouring in painting. Samuel Palmer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Leonard, N. (2021). Epistemological Problems of Testimony. In E. N. Zalta (Ed.), The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/testimony-episprob/

  • Lewis, D. (1999). What experience teaches. In Papers in Metaphysics and Epistemology (pp. 262–290). Cambridge Scholars Press.

  • Lynch, K. (2020). Knowing what an experience is like and the reductive theory of knowledge-Wh. Analytic Philosophy, 61(3), 252–275. https://doi.org/10.1111/phib.12171

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mäcklin, H. (2022, January 11). When art transports us, where do we actually go? Psyche. https://psyche.co/ideas/when-art-transports-us-where-do-we-actually-go

  • Magidor, O. (2015). The myth of the de se. Philosophical Perspectives, 29, 249–283.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Maibom, H. L. (2016). Knowing me, knowing you: Failure to forecast and the empathic imagination. In A. Kind & P. Kung (Eds.), Knowledge through imagination (pp. 185–206). Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • McCoy, J., Paul, L. A., & Ullman, T. (2019). Modal prospection. In A. I. Goldman & B. P. McLaughlin (Eds.), Metaphysics and cognitive science (pp. 235–267). Oxford University Press. https://doi.org/10.1093/oso/9780190639679.003.0010

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Meskin, A. (2004). Aesthetic testimony: What can we learn from others about beauty and art? Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 69(1), 65–91.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Montero, B. G. (2020). What experience doesn’t teach: Pain amnesia and a new paradigm for memory research. Journal of Consciousness Studies, 27(11–12), 102–125.

    Google Scholar 

  • Murphy, M. (2022, July 1). “Elvis”: Anatomy of a Scene. The New York Times. https://www.nytimes.com/video/movies/100000008425728/elvis-scene.html?smid=url-share

  • Nanay, B. (2016). The role of imagination in decision-making. Mind & Language, 31(1), 127–143.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nguyen, C. T. (2017). The uses of aesthetic testimony. The British Journal of Aesthetics, 57(1), 19–36.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nussbaum, M. C. (1990). “Finely aware and richly responsible”: Literature and the moral imagination. In Love’s knowledge (pp. 148–167). Oxford University Press.

  • Oatley, K. (2016). Fiction: Simulation of social worlds. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 20(8), 618–628.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Parent, T. (2014). Knowing-Wh and embedded questions. Philosophy Compass, 9(2), 81–95. https://doi.org/10.1111/phc3.12104

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Paul, L. A. (2014). Transformative experience. Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Paul, L. A. (2015). Transformative choice: Discussion and replies. Research Philosophica, 92(2), 473–545.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Paul, L. A. (2017). De se preferences and empathy for future selves. Philosophical Perspectives, 31(1), 7–39.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Paul, L. A. (2019). Reply to Symposiasts. Rivista Internazionale Di Filosofia e Psicologia, 10(3), 3.

    Google Scholar 

  • Paul, L. A. (2020). Who will i become? In E. Lambert & J. Schwenkler (Eds.), Becoming someone new: Essays on transformative experience, choice, and change (pp. 16–36). Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Pavese, C. (2017). Know-how and gradability. The Philosophical Review, 126(3), 345–383. https://doi.org/10.1215/00318108-3878493

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Peacocke, A. (2020). How literature expands your imagination. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 1, 1–22.

    Google Scholar 

  • Peterson, M. (2009). An introduction to decision theory. Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Pettigrew, R. (2015). Transformative experience and decision theory. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 91(3), 766–774. https://doi.org/10.1111/phpr.12240

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pettigrew, R. (2019). Choosing for changing selves. Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Puolakka, K. (2022). Learning from literary experience. Journal of Aesthetic Education, 56(1), 56–73. https://doi.org/10.5406/15437809.56.1.04

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Robson, J. (2012). Aesthetic testimony. Philosophy Compass, 7(1), 1–10.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rowe, M. W. (2009). Literature, knowledge, and the aesthetic attitude. Ratio, 22(4), 375–397.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ryle, G. (1948). The concept of mind. University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sharadin, N. (2015). How You can reasonably form expectations when you’re expecting. Res Philosophica, 92(2), 441–452. https://doi.org/10.11612/resphil.2015.92.2.2

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shone, T. (2004). Blockbuster: How hollywood learned to stop worrying and love the summer. Simon and Schuster.

    Google Scholar 

  • Smith, M. (1995). Engaging characters: Fiction, emotion, and the cinema. Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stoljar, D. (2016). The semantics of ‘what it’s like’ and the nature of consciousness. Mind, 125(500), 1161–1198. https://doi.org/10.1093/mind/fzv179

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stroud, S. R. (2008). Simulation, Subjective knowledge, and the cognitive value of literary narrative. The Journal of Aesthetic Education, 42(3), 19–41. https://doi.org/10.1353/jae.0.0016

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tye, M. (2011). Knowing what it is like. In J. Bengson & M. A. Moffett (Eds.), Knowing how: Essays on knowledge, mind, and action (pp. 300–313). Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wallace, A. (1998, August 6). ‘Ryan’ Ends Vets’ Years of Silence. Los Angeles Times. https://www.latimes.com/archives/la-xpm-1998-aug-06-mn-10608-story.html

  • Walsh, D. (1969). Literature and knowledge. Wesleyan University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wilson, T. D., & Gilbert, D. T. (2005). Affective forecasting: Knowing what to want. Current Directions in Psychological Science, 14(3), 131–134.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Zeman, A., Dewar, M., & Della Sala, S. (2015). Lives without imagery: Congenital aphantasia. Cortex A Journal Devoted to the Study of the Nervous System and Behavior, 73, 378–380. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.cortex.2015.05.019

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Funding

No funding was received to assist with the preparation of this manuscript.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Antony Aumann.

Ethics declarations

Conflict of interest

The author has no competing interests to declare that are relevant to the content of this article.

Ethical approval

No human or animal participants were involved in this work.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Springer Nature or its licensor (e.g. a society or other partner) holds exclusive rights to this article under a publishing agreement with the author(s) or other rightsholder(s); author self-archiving of the accepted manuscript version of this article is solely governed by the terms of such publishing agreement and applicable law.

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Aumann, A. Art, imagination, and experiential knowledge. Synthese 201, 100 (2023). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-023-04109-2

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-023-04109-2

Keywords

Navigation