Skip to main content
Log in

The questioning-attitude account of agnosticism

  • Original Research
  • Published:
Synthese Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

I defend a proposition-directed, sui generis account of agnosticism, according to which being agnostic about some proposition, P, involves a sceptical or questioning mental stance towards both the truth and falsity of P. Call this the questioning-attitude account. The questioning-attitude account contrasts with the question-directed attitude account of Jane Friedman, which holds that the object of agnosticism is a question rather than a proposition. I argue that the questioning-attitude account not only avoids a major weakness of Friedman’s question-directed attitude account, but it also displays the following three attractive features: (1) it offers an explanation of why ascriptions of agnosticism often take an interrogative compliment, (2) it offers a univocal account of the content of all three doxastic attitudes, and (3) it fleshes out the claim that agnosticism is sui generis by describing what makes agnosticism distinct from both belief and disbelief.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Friedman (2013c, 2017) prefers to use the term “suspend judgement” to refer to the neutral doxastic attitude. However, following Matthew McGrath (McGrath, 2021), I will use the term “agnosticism” to refer to the attitude and “suspend judgement” to refer to the mental act of putting off judgement. While there are important differences between my conception of the neutral doxastic attitude and Friedman’s, nothing of substance will depend on this difference of terminology.

  2. Shah and Velleman (2005, p. 503). See and cf. Cassam (2010, p. 81).

  3. See and cf. Lord (2020, p. 128).

  4. The normative account of what it means to be committed to the truth of offered here includes a narrow scope requirement having to do with the appropriate doxastic response to one's evidence and a wide scope requirement stipulating that one is rationally criticisable if one adopts a commitment to not-P while also maintaining one’s commitment to P.   Lord (2018) argues, I believe convincingly, that wide scope consistency requirements are reducible to narrow scope evidential norms. However, I wish to remain non-committal regarding such reducibility for the purposes of the present discussion.

  5. Examples of the narrow usage of the term “doxastic attitude” include: Feldman and Conee (2018), Steup (1988), Chisholm (1989), Sosa (1991), Feldman (2003), Steup (2008), and McGrath (McGrath, 2021). For an argument that the attitudes of believing, disbelieving, and agnosticism (or what she calls “suspending judgement”) are not reducible to degrees of belief, see Friedman (2013c).

  6. Friedman (2013a, p. 145).

  7. Special thanks to an anonymous referee for this journal for raising the present objection.

  8. For an in-depth discussion of the relationship between agnosticism and inquiry, see Archer (2018, 2019).

  9. Lilly (2019, pp. 217–218).

  10. See and cf. Friedman (2013b: 178) and Raleigh (2021).

  11. Raleigh (2021, p. 2462).

References

  • Archer, A. (2018). Wondering about what you know. Analysis, 78(4), 596–604.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Archer, A. (2019). Agnosticism, inquiry, and unanswerable questions. Disputatio, 53(11), 63–88.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cassam, Q. (2010). Judging, believing and thinking. Philosophical Issues, 20, 80–95.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chisholm, R. (1989). Theory of knowledge. 3rd Edition. Englewood Cliffs, N.J.: Prentice Hall.

  • Feldman, R. (2003). Epistemology. Upper Saddle River, New Jersey: Prentice-Hall.

  • Feldman, R., & Conee, E. (2018). Between belief and disbelief. In K. McCain (Ed.), Believing in accordance with the evidence (Vol. 398, pp. 71–89). Synthese Library.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Friedman, J. (2013a). Question-directed attitudes. Philosophical Perspectives, 27, 145–174.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Friedman, J. (2013b). Rational agnosticism and degrees of belief. In D. Gendler & J. Hawthorne (Eds.), Oxford studies in epistemology. (Vol. 4). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Friedman, J. (2013c). Suspended judgement. Philosophical Studies, 162(2), 165–181.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Friedman, J. (2017). Why suspend judging? Nous, 51(2), 302–326.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hieronymi, P. (2006). Controlling attitudes. Pacific Philosophical Quarterly, 87(1), 45–74.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kapitan, T. (1986). Deliberation and the presumption of open alternatives. The Philosophical Quarterly, 36(143), 230–251.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kaplan, M. (1981). A Bayesian theory of rational acceptance. The Journal of Philosophy, 78(6), 305–330.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lilly, W. (2019). Constitutive reasons and the suspension of judgement. Dialogue, 58(2), 215–224.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lord, E. (2018). The importance of being rational. Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Lord, E. (2020). Suspension of judgment, rationality’s competition, and the reach of the epistemic. In S. Schmidt & G. Ernst (Eds.), The ethics of belief and beyond (pp. 126–145). Routledge.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • McGrath, M. (2021). Being neutral: Agnosticism, inquiry and the suspension of judgement. Noûs, 55(2), 463–484.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Raleigh, T. (2021). Suspending is believing. Synthese, 198, 2449–2474.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shah, N., & Velleman, D. (2005). Doxastic deliberation. The Philosophical Review, 114(4), 497–534.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sosa, E. (1991). Knowledge in perspective: Selected essays in epistemology. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

  • Steup, M. (1988). The deontic conception of epistemic justification. Philosophical Studies, 53(1), 65–84.

  • Steup, M. (2008). Doxastic freedom. Synthese, 161(3), 375–392.

  • Weintraub, R. (1990). Decision-theoretic epistemology. Synthese, 83(1), 159–177.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Williams, S. G. (1989). Belief, desire and the praxis of reasoning. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 90, 119–142.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Avery Archer.

Ethics declarations

Conflict of interest

There are no financial or non-financial interests that are directly or indirectly related to the work submitted for publication.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Springer Nature or its licensor (e.g. a society or other partner) holds exclusive rights to this article under a publishing agreement with the author(s) or other rightsholder(s); author self-archiving of the accepted manuscript version of this article is solely governed by the terms of such publishing agreement and applicable law.

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Archer, A. The questioning-attitude account of agnosticism. Synthese 200, 498 (2022). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-022-03971-w

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-022-03971-w

Keywords

Navigation