Skip to main content
Log in

Disagreement in philosophy

  • Original Research
  • Published:
Synthese Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Recent philosophical discussions construe disagreement as epistemically unsettling. On learning that a peer disagrees, it is said, you should suspend judgment, lower your credence, or dismiss your peer’s conviction as somehow flawed, even if you can neither identify the flaw nor explain why you think she is the party in error. Philosophers do none of these things. A distinctive feature of philosophy as currently practiced is that, although we marshal the strongest arguments we can devise, we do not expect others to agree. Nor are we dismayed then they do not. Through a survey of familiar professional practices, I argue that philosophy rightly revels in responsible disagreement. This discloses important and perhaps surprising facets of the epistemology of philosophy.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. See Samuel Elgin (2015) and James Lenman (2000) for arguments that show that consequentialists are never in a position to know or reasonably believe that a given action is good. They know that it is good if and only if it maximizes utility. Because causal chains are endless, we cannot know which action satisfies that requirement.

  2. This example was suggested to me by Samuel Elgin.

References

  • Aristotle. (1941). The basic works of Aristotle, R. McKeon (Eds). Random House.

  • Barnett, Z. (2019). Philosophy without belief. Mind, 128, 109–138.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Christensen, D. (2007). Epistemology of disagreement: The good news. Philosophical Review, 116, 187–217.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cohen, L. J. (1992). An essay on belief and acceptance. Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dellsén, F. (2019). Rational understanding: Toward a probabilistic epistemology of acceptability. Synthese, 198, 2475–1494.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Elgin, C. (1996). Considered judgment. Princeton University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Elgin, S. (2015). The unreliability of foreseeable consequences: A return to the epistemic objection. Ethical Theory and Moral Practice, 18, 459–466.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Elgin, C. (2017). True enough. MIT Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Elgin, C. (2018). Reasonable disagreement’. In C. R. Johnson (Ed.), Voicing dissent (pp. 10–21). Routledge.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Fumerton, R. (2010). You can’t trust a philosopher’. In R. Feldman & T. A. Warfield (Eds.), Disagreement (pp. 90–110). Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Goldberg, S. (2013a). Disagreement, defeat, and assertion’. In D. Christensen & J. Lackey (Eds.), The epistemology of disagreement: New essays (pp. 167–189). Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Goldberg, S. (2013b). Defending philosophy in the face of systematic disagreement. In D. Machuca (Ed.), Disagreement and skepticism (pp. 277–294). Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Heydrich, W. (1993). A reconception of meaning. Synthese, 95, 77–94.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hills, A. (2016). Understanding Why. Noûs, 50, 661–688.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kitcher, P. (1990). The division of cognitive labor. Journal of Philosophy, 87, 5–22.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lenman, J. (2000). Consequentialism and cluelessness. Philosophy and Public Affairs, 29, 342–370.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, D. (2000). Academic appointments: Why ignore the advantage of being right? David Lewis: Papers in ethics and social philosophy (pp. 187–200). Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mill, J. S. (1978). On liberty. Hackett Publishing Co.

    Google Scholar 

  • Russell, B. (1971). ‘Letter to FREGE’ From Frege to Gödel. In J. Van Heijenoort. Harvard University Press, (pp. 124–125).

  • van Fraassen, B. (2008). Scientific representation. Clarendon Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Vogel, J. (1990). Are there counterexamples to the closure principle? In M. D. Roth & G. Ross (Eds.), Doubting (pp. 13–27). Kluwer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgement

I am grateful to Greta Turnbull and participants at the 2018 Ryerson University Philosophy Conference for comments on an earlier draft of this paper, and to two anonymous reviewers for comments. In particular I am grateful for the recommendation that I recognize the ways that Mill's views align with mine.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Catherine Z. Elgin.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Elgin, C.Z. Disagreement in philosophy. Synthese 200, 20 (2022). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-022-03535-y

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-022-03535-y

Keywords

Navigation