Skip to main content
Log in

Practical concepts and productive reasoning

  • Minds in Skilled Performance
  • Published:
Synthese Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Can we think of a task in a distinctively practical way? Can there be practical concepts? In recent years, epistemologists, philosophers of mind, as well as philosophers of psychology have appealed to practical concepts in characterizing the content of know-how or in explaining certain features of skilled action. However, reasons for positing practical concepts are rarely discussed in a systematic fashion. This paper advances a novel argument for the psychological reality of practical concepts that relies on evidence for a distinctively productive kind of reasoning.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Fig. 1
Fig. 2

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. This essay remains neutral on whether, in addition to observational, semantic, and practical concepts, there are also phenomenal concepts in Chalmers’s (2004) sense.

  2. As raised by Butterfill and Sinigaglia (2014).

  3. From the little they say about practical ways of thinking, it is hard to say whether either Stanley and Williamson (2001) or Stanley (2011) thought of practical ways of thinking as concepts or what else (cf. [Pavese, ming] for discussion).

  4. For a more careful discussion of this Fregean argument for practical concepts, see Pavese (2021).

  5. Butterfill and Sinigaglia (2014, pp. 128–129) do argue that motor representations and intentions differ in formats by arguing that there is a difference in format between cognitive imagininations and phenomenologically action kind imaginations. But their argument assumes that differences in format follow from differences in characteristic performance profile.

  6. I myself believe that there are good reasons for positing this sort of subpersonal representation (cf. Pavese 2017b, 2019, 2020) but I do not want my argument for practical concepts to depend on there being subpersonal motor representations.

  7. Indeed, arguably, far from solving it, appealing to practical concepts makes the interface problem even less tractable, if the problem is, as it seems plausible, one of translation. For what insures that, as intermediaries between conceptual and motor representations, practical concepts will not raise an interface problem of their own? The issue arises because for them to facilitate the translation between the code (or format) of intentions and the code (or format) of motor representation, practical concepts would need to be written in a hybrid code —a little conceptual, a little motoric—but there are reasons to be skeptical that any such a thing as ‘hybrid code’ actually makes sense. If, on the other hand, a hybrid code is simply a code different from both the conceptual and the motoric codes—but somehow resemblant of both—it is not at all clear that the interface problem is overcome. Indeed, a regress of translation threatens to arise.

  8. See Higginbotham (1998) and Ezcurdia (1998).

  9. Cf. Murphy (2004) and Machery (2009)) for an overview of the psychological literature on concept.

  10. I did say that semantic concepts often come with (even explicit) knowledge, but this is not to be understood as definitional; rather it is to be understood as a criterion for semantic concepts’ possession.

  11. I am not endorsing atomism about concepts either (Fodor 1998a; Quilty-Dunn 2021) for here I allow that some concepts might be complex representations. But I am sympathetic to it.

  12. I am grateful to a referee for urging me to clarify these issues.

  13. Cf. Butterfill and Sinigaglia (2014) on evidence for thinking that motor representations do not feature in practical or theoretical reasoning.

  14. Though some spatial reasoning might involve non-conceptual representations (Peacocke 1992), it seems widely assumed that observational concepts would figure in spatial reasoning.

  15. In particular, just like one might have a perceptual belief that has an observational concept as its component (cf. Weiskopf 2015), one might have a practical belief—that is, one might believe a practical proposition—a proposition that has a practical concept as a component, or make a judgment that has a practical concept as a component—a practical judgment. Indeed, I suspect that Anscombe’s (1963) practical knowledge—knowledge of what one is doing while doing it—ought to involve practical concepts of this sort.

  16. The personal-subpersonal level distinction is drawn by different people in different ways. See Drayson (2014) for an overview.

  17. About (i): the idea is that working memory is not a discrete subpersonal system and is instead the locus of central cognition (e.g., Baddeley 1992, 1996; D’Esposito and Postle 2015) as well as the locus for highly cognitive capacities such as reasoning, learning and comprehension, as well as propositional attitudes (Prinz 2004). If productive reasoning depends on representations in working memory, that is at least some reason to think that productive reasoning is available to central cognition and so personal-level. About (ii): if the productive reasoning is affected by some general (but not necessarily declarative) knowledge of the subject, that would be evidence that it is not encapsulated, and so, in my sense, not subpersonal. So, in the following I will assume that (i) and (ii) are together sufficient for reasoning to be personal-level in the relevant sense.

  18. Some have talked of practical concepts to refer to conceptual representations of affordances. Here, I don’t take this feature to enter into the notion of practical concepts, as I am thinking of it.

  19. Paresis occurs when the subject is damaged in their corticospinal system—that is, the cortical motor areas and the corticospinal tract that connects the cerebral cortex to the spinal cord. It reflects a problem in transferring motor commands from the cortex to the spinal cord (Sathian et al. 2011). The term ‘ataxia’ is instead used in a specific sense to refer to impaired spatial and temporal coordination of movements or sometimes more generally as a catch-all term for poor coordination, inaccurate and variable movements, dysmetria, and intention tremor. It results from damage to the cerebellum, its input and output pathways in the brainstem, the spinocerebellar tracts or posterior columns in the spinal cord, or large fibers in peripheral sensory nerves.

  20. In fact, some describe apractic agents as performing movement errors with their non-paretic hands. Cf. Goldenberg (1996).

  21. This hypothesis is formulated differently from different researchers. Some talk of motor programs, action schemas, while others talk of control policies.

  22. Indeed, on the basis of the evidence marshaled so far, one of the first philosophers to discuss ideo-motor apraxia—(Merleau-Ponty 1962, pp. 523–525, fn 99)—observes “We will not render apraxia comprehensible \(\dots \), unless the movement to be accomplished can be anticipated but without being so through a representation.” Indeed, Merleau-Ponty (1962, p. 142) argues that apractic subjects lack a body schema, which he does not seem to conceive of representationally.

  23. For yet other experiments on the Novel Tool Test, see Osiurak et al. (2013) and Jarry et al. (2013).

  24. A referee objects that it is not obvious that imaginistic representations of actions should be considered practical concepts since they are not obviously necessary for intentional responses to typical environmental cues and the referee thinks that practical concepts should be involved in such responses. As we have seen, I don’t think it is obvious that practical concepts are involved for performing familiar tasks in environmentally triggered conditions (perception of affordances, semantic or observational concepts might explain those performances). Nor is it part of the functional characterization given in Sect. 3 that practical concepts are involved in environmentally triggered responses. Indeed, those responses don’t seem to involve productive reasoning.

  25. A referee asks whether it could be that apractic patients have more general memory problems, that prevents them from learning any new concepts. However, as discussed in Sect. 4, there is no evidence that it is common to all apractic patients that they have more general memory problems (though some have Alzheimer’s, not all do cf Wheaton and Hallett (2007), p. 1). A referee further asks whether apractic subjects may be missing the ability to perform tasks on demand, because they cannot or call up the action schemas on the basis of novel activators. Note that this explanation assumes— like the popular explanation—they have already action schemas for tasks they have not encountered before, and we have seen from the Novel Tool Test that that is not true.

  26. I am grateful to an anonymous reviewer for raising this objection in this form.

References

  • Anscombe, G. E. M. (1963). Intention. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Baddeley, A. (1992). Working memory. Science, 255(5044), 556–559.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Baddeley, A. (1996). The concept of working memory. Models of Short-Term Memory, 1–27.

  • Barsalou, L. W. (1999). Perceptual symbol systems. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 22(4), 577–660.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bartolo, A., Cubelli, R., Della Sala, S., Drei, S., & Marchetti, C. (2001). Double dissociation between meaningful and meaningless gesture reproduction in apraxia. Cortex, 37(5), 696–699.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Boghossian, P. (2003). Blind reasoning. Aristotelian Society Supplementary, 77(1).

  • Brass, M., & Heyes, C. (2005). Imitation: is cognitive neuroscience solving the correspondence problem? Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 9(10), 489–495.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bratman, M., et al. (1987). Intention, plans, and practical reason (Vol. 10). Harvard University Press.

  • Broome, J. (2002). Practical reasoning. Reason and nature: Essays in the theory of rationality, 85–111.

  • Butterfill, S. A., & Sinigaglia, C. (2014). Intention and motor representation in purposive action. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 88(1), 119–145.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Buxbaum, L. J., Schwartz, M. F., & Carew, T. G. (1997). The role of semantic memory in object use. Cognitive Neuropsychology, 14(2), 219–254.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Buxbaum, L. J., Sirigu, A., Schwartz, M. F., & Klatzky, R. (2003). Cognitive representations of hand posture in ideomotor apraxia. Neuropsychologia, 41(8), 1091–1113.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Camp, E. (2009). Putting thoughts to work: Concepts, systematicity, and stimulus-independence. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 78(2), 275–311.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Campbell, J. (1996). Shape properties, experience of shape and shape concepts. Philosophical Issues, 7, 351–363.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Carey, S. (2009). Oxford series in cognitive development (Vol. 3). In The origin of concepts. Oxford university press.

  • Chalmers, D. J. (2004). 13 phenomenal concepts and the knowledge argument (269 pp). In There’s Something About Mary: Essays on phenomenal consciousness and Frank Jackson’s knowledge argument.

  • Christensen, W. (2020). The skill of translating thought into action: Framing the problem. Review of Philosophy and Psychology, 1–27.

  • De Renzi, E. (1989). Apraxia. In F., B. and J., G., editors, Handbook of clinical neuropsychology. Elsevier.

  • De Renzi, E. (1999). Apraxia. In Handbook of clinical neuropsychology (Vol. 2, pp. 421–440). Psychology Press.

  • De Renzi, E. (2012). Action. In K. F. W. Ramsey (Ed.), The Cambridge handbook of cognitive science (pp. 92–111). Cambridge Universitu Press.

  • De Renzi, E., Motti, F., & Nichelli, P. (1980). Imitating gestures: A quantitative approach to ideomotor apraxia. Archives of Neurology, 37(1), 6–10.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • De Vignemont, F., Majid, A., Jola, C., & Haggard, P. (2009). Segmenting the body into parts: Evidence from biases in tactile perception. Quarterly Journal of Experimental Psychology, 62(3), 500–512.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • De Vignemont, F., Tsakiris, M., & Haggard, P. (2006). Body mereology. Human Body Perception from the Inside Out 147–170.

  • D’Esposito, M., & Postle, B. R. (2015). The cognitive neuroscience of working memory. Annual Review of Psychology, 66.

  • Drayson, Z. (2014). The personal/subpersonal distinction. Philosophy Compass, 9(5), 338–346.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dummett, M. (1993). The seas of language. Oxford University Press.

  • Ezcurdia, M. (1998). The concept-conception distinction. Philosophical Issues, 9, 187–192.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ferrari, P. F., Rozzi, S., & Fogassi, L. (2005). Mirror neurons responding to observation of actions made with tools in monkey ventral premotor cortex. Journal of Cognitive Neuroscience, 17(2), 212–226.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fodor, J. (1998a). Concepts: Where cognitive science went wrong. Clarendon Press.

  • Fridland, E. (2019). Intention at the interface. Review of Philosophy and Psychology 1–25.

  • Gallese, V., & Lakoff, G. (2005). The brain’s concepts: The role of the sensory-motor system in conceptual knowledge. Cognitive Neuropsychology, 22(3–4), 455–479.

  • Geschwind, N., & Damasio, A. R. (1985). Apraxia. Handbook of Clinical Neurology, 1(49), 423–432.

  • Gibbs, R. W. (2005). The psychological status of image schemas. From Perception to Meaning: Image Schemas in Cognitive Linguistics, 29, 113–136.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gibbs, R. W, Jr. (2003). Embodied experience and linguistic meaning. Brain and language, 84(1), 1–15.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Glick, E. (2011). Abilities and know how attributions. In J. Brown & M. Gerken (Eds.), Knowledge ascriptions (pp. 120–139) Oxford University Press.

  • Goldenberg, G. (1995). Imitating gestures and manipulating a mannikin-the representation of the human body in ideomotor apraxia. Neuropsychologia, 33(1), 63–72.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Goldenberg, G. (1996). Defective imitation of gestures in patients with damage in the left or right hemispheres. Journal of Neurology, Neurosurgery & Psychiatry, 61(2), 176–180.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Goldenberg, G. (1999). Matching and imitation of hand and finger posturesin patients with damage in the left or right hemispheres. Neuropsychologia, 37(5), 559–566.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Goldenberg, G. (2001). Imitation and matching of hand and finger postures. Neuroimage, 14(1), S132–S136.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Goldenberg, G. (2008). Apraxia. Handbook of clinical neurology, 88, 323–338.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Goldenberg, G. (2013). Apraxia: The cognitive side of motor control. Oxford.

  • Goldenberg, G., & Hagmann, S. (1997). The meaning of meaningless gestures: A study of visuo-imitative apraxia. Neuropsychologia, 35(3), 333–341.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Goldenberg, G., & Hagmann, S. (1998). Tool use and mechanical problem solving in apraxia. Neuropsychologia, 36(7), 581–589.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Goldenberg, G., Hartmann-Schmid, K., Sürer, F., Daumüller, M., & Hermsdölrfer, J. (2007). The impact of dysexecutive syndrome on use of tools and technical devices. Cortex, 43(3), 424–435.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Goldenberg, G., & Spatt, J. (2009). The neural basis of tool use. Brain, 132(6), 1645–1655.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Goldenberg, G., & Strauss, S. (2002). Hemisphere asymmetries for imitation of novel gestures. Neurology, 59(6), 893–897.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Goldenberg, G., Wimmer, E., Auff, G., & Schnaberth, G. (1986). Impairment of motor planning in patients with Parkinson’s disease: Evidence from ideomotor apraxia. Journal of Neurology, Neurosurgery, and Psychiatry, 49, 1266–1272.

  • Hampe, B., & Grady, J. E. (2005). From perception to meaning: Image schemas in cognitive linguistics, (Vol. 29). Walter de Gruyter.

  • Harman, G. (1976). Practical reasoning. The Review of Metaphysics, 431–463.

  • Harman, G. (2008). Change in view: Principles of reasoning. Cambridge University Press.

  • Hartmann, K., Goldenberg, G., Daumüller, M., & Hermsdörfer, J. (2005). It takes the whole brain to make a cup of coffee: the neuropsychology of naturalistic actions involving technical devices. Neuropsychologia, 43(4), 625–637.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hayakawa, Y., Fujii, T., Yamadori, A., Meguro, K., & Suzuki, K. (2015). A case with apraxia of tool use: selective inability to form a hand posture for a tool. Brain and Nerve Shinkei kenkyu no shinpo, 67(3), 311–316.

  • Hegarty, M. (2004). Mechanical reasoning by mental simulation. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 8(6), 280–285.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Heilman, K. M., & Rothi, L. J. G. (1993). Apraxia. In K. M. Heilman & E. Valenstein (Eds.), Clinical neuropsychology (pp. 141–164). New York Oxford: Oxford University Press.

  • Heilman, K. M., Maher, L. M., Greenwald, M. L., & Rothi, L. J. (1997). Conceptual apraxia from lateralized lesions. Neurology, 49(2), 457–464.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Higginbotham, J. (1998). Conceptual competence. Philosophical Issues, 9, 149–162.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hodges, J. R., Bozeat, S., Ralph, M. A. L., Patterson, K., & Spatt, J. (2000). The role of conceptual knowledge in object use evidence from semantic dementia. Brain, 123(9), 1913–1925.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hodges, J. R., Spatt, J., & Patterson, K. (1999). “what” and “how”: Evidence for the dissociation of object knowledge and mechanical problem-solving skills in the human brain. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences, 96(16), 9444–9448.

  • Hutto, D. D. (2005). Knowing what? radical versus conservative enactivism. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 4(4), 389–405.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hutto, D. D., & Myin, E. (2012). Radicalizing enactivism: Basic minds without content. MIT Press.

  • Israel, D., Perry, J., & Tutiya, S. (1993). Executions, motivations, and accomplishments. The Philosophical Review, 102(4), 515–540.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jarry, C., Osiurak, F., Delafuys, D., Chauviré, V., Etcharry-Bouyx, F., & Le Gall, D. (2013). Apraxia of tool use: More evidence for the technical reasoning hypothesis. Cortex, 49(9), 2322–2333.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jeannerod, M. (2006). Motor cognition: What actions tell the self. 42. Oxford University Press.

  • Johnson, M. (2012). Action, embodied meaning, and thought. In Action, perception and the brain (pp. 92–116). Springer.

  • Kenny, A. (2010). Concepts, brains, and behaviour. Grazer Philosophische Studien, 81(1), 105–113.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kertesz, A., & Hooper, P. (1982). Praxis and language: The extent and variety of apraxia in aphasia. Neuropsychologia, 20(3), 275–286.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Krakauer, J. W. (2019). The intelligent reflex. Philosophical Psychology, 32(5), 822–830.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Krakauer, J. W. (2020). Automatizing knowledge: Confusion over what cognitive neuroscience tells us about intellectualism. In The Routledge handbook of philosophy of skill and expertise, (pp. 219–225). Routledge.

  • Krakauer, J. W., & Shadmehr, R. (2007). Towards a computational neuropsychology of action. Progress in Brain Research, 165, 383–394.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lande, K. J. (2018). The perspectival character of perception. The Journal of Philosophy, 115(4), 187–214.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lande, K. J. (2020). Mental structures. Noûs.

  • Laurence, S., & Margolis, E. (1999). Concepts: Where cognitive science went wrong. jerr a fodor. The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 50(3), 487–491.

  • Lauro-Grotto, R., Piccini, C., & Shallice, T. (1997). Modality-specific operations in semantic dementia. Cortex, 33(4), 593–622.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lehmkuhl, G., Poeck, K., & Willmes, K. (1983). Ideomotor apraxia and aphasia: An examination of types and manifestations of apraxic symptoms. Neuropsychologia, 21(3), 199–212.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Leiguarda, R., Lees, A., Merello, M., Starkstein, S., & Marsden, C. (1994). The nature of apraxia in corticobasal degeneration. Journal of Neurology, Neurosurgery & Psychiatry, 57(4), 455–459.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Liepmann, H. (1900). Das krankheitsbild der apraxie (motorische asymbolie): Auf grund eines falles von einseitiger apraxie. Monatschrift für Psychiatrie und Neurologie, 8, 15–44.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Liepmann, H. (1906). Der weitere krankheitsverlauf bei dem einseitig apraktischen und der gehirnbefund auf grund von serienschnitten. European Neurology, 19(3), 217–243.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Macauley, B. L., & Handley, C. L. (2005). Gestures produced by patients with aphasia and ideomotor apraxia. Contemporary Issues in Communication Science and Disorders, 32(Spring), 30–37.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Machery, E. (2009). Doing without concepts. Oxford University Press.

  • Merleau-Ponty, M. (1962). Phenomenology of perception. Routledge.

  • Mosdell, M. (2019). Modeling practical thinking. Mind & Language, 34(4), 445–464.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Murphy, G. (2004). The big book of concepts. MIT press.

  • Mylopoulos, M., & Pacherie, E. (2017). Intentions and motor representations: The interface challenge. Review of Philosophy and Psychology, 8(2), 317–336.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Negri, G. A., Lunardelli, A., Reverberi, C., Gigli, G. L., & Rumiati, R. I. (2007). Degraded semantic knowledge and accurate object use. Cortex, 43(3), 376–388.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Noë, A. (2005). Anti-intellectualism. Analysis, 65(288), 278–90.

  • Ochipa, C., Rapcsak, S. Z., Maher, L. M., Rothi, L. J. G., Bowers, D., & Heilman, K. M. (1997). Selective deficit of praxis imagery in ideomotor apraxia. Neurology, 49(2), 474–480.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Osiurak, F., Aubin, G., Allain, P., Jarry, C., Richard, I., & Le Gall, D. (2008). Object usage and object utilization. A single-case study. Neurocase, 14(2), 169–183.

  • Osiurak, F., & Badets, A. (2016). Tool use and affordance: Manipulation-based versus reasoning-based approaches. Psychological review, 123(5), 534.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Osiurak, F., Jarry, C., Lesourd, M., Baumard, J., & Le Gall, D. (2013). Mechanical problem-solving strategies in left-brain damaged patients and apraxia of tool use. Neuropsychologia, 51(10), 1964–1972.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Osiurak, F., Rossetti, Y., & Badets, A. (2017). What is an affordance? 40 years later. Neuroscience & Biobehavioral Reviews, 77, 403–417.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Osiurak, F. A. A. (2011). Re-examining the gesture engram hypothesis. New perspectives on apraxia of tool use. Neuropsychologia, 49(3), 299–312.

  • Osiurak, F. E. A. (2009). Unusual use of objects after unilateral brain damage. the technical reasoning model. Cortex, 45(6), 769–783.

  • Pacherie, E. (2000). The content of intentions. Mind & Language, 15(4), 400–432.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pacherie, E. (2011). Nonconceptual representations for action and the limits of intentional control. Social Psychology, 42(1), 67.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pavese, C. (2013). The unity and scope of knowledge. PhD thesis, Rutgers University.

  • Pavese, C. (2015a). Knowing a rule. Philosophical Issues, 25(1), 165–188.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pavese, C. (2015b). Practical senses. Philosopher’s Imprint, 15(29).

  • Pavese, C. (2017a). Know-how and gradability. The Philosophical Review, 126(3), 345–383.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pavese, C. (2017b). A theory of practical meaning. Philosophical Topics, 45(2), 65–96.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pavese, C. (2019). The psychological reality of practical representation. Philosophical Psychology, 32(5), 784–821.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pavese, C. (2020). Practical representation. In Routledge handbook of philosophy of skills and expertise (pp. 226–244). Routledge.

  • Pavese, C. (2021). Might there actually be practical concepts? Manuscript.

  • Pavese, C. (forthcoming). Knowledge-how. Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.

  • Peacocke, C. (1988). Thoughts: An essay on content. In Aristotelian society series (Vol. 4). Blackwell.

  • Peacocke, C. (1992). A study of concepts. The MIT Press.

  • Peigneux, P., Van der Linden, M., Andres-Benito, P., Sadzot, B., Franck, G., & Salmon, E. (2000). Exploration neuropsychologique et par imagerie fonctionnelle cérébrale d’une apraxie visuo-imitative. Revue Neurologique, 156(5), 459–474.

  • Pinker, S. (2007). The stuff of thought: Language as a window into human nature. Penguin.

  • Poeck, K. (1986). The clinical examination for motor apraxia. Neuropsychologia, 24(1), 129–134.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Prinz, J. J. (2004). Furnishing the mind: Concepts and their perceptual basis. MIT press.

  • Quilty-Dunn, J. (2021). Polysemy and thought: Toward a generative theory of concepts. Mind & Language.

  • Quilty-Dunn, J., & Mandelbaum, E. (2018). Inferential transitions. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 96(3), 532–547.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Quine, W. (1960). Word and object. MIT Press

  • Rapcsak, S. Z., Ochipa, C., Anderson, K. C., & Poizner, H. (1995). Progressive ideomotor apraxia-evidence for a selective impairment of the action production system. Brain and cognition, 27(2), 213–236.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rizzolatti, G., Fogassi, L., & Gallese, V. (2002). Motor and cognitive functions of the ventral premotor cortex. Current Opinion in Neurobiology, 12(2), 149–154.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rizzolatti, G., & Sinigaglia, C. (2008). Mirrors in the brain: How our minds share actions and emotions. Oxford University Press.

  • Sathian, K., Buxbaum, L. J., Cohen, L. G., Krakauer, J. W., Lang, C. E., Corbetta, M., & Fitzpatrick, S. M. (2011). Neurological principles and rehabilitation of action disorders: Common clinical deficits. Neurorehabilitation and Neural Repair, 25(5-suppl), 21S-32S.

  • Schiffer, S. (2002). Amazing Knowledge. Journal of Philosophy, 99(4), 200–202.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Searle, J. R., Willis, S., et al. (1983). Intentionality: An essay in the philosophy of mind. Cambridge University Press.

  • Sekinea, K., & Rosec, M. L. (2013). The relationship of aphasia type and gesture production in people with aphasia. American Journal of Speech-Language Pathology, 662, 672.

    Google Scholar 

  • Silveri, M. C., & Ciccarelli, N. (2009). Semantic memory in object use. Neuropsychologia, 47(12), 2634–2641.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sims, V. K., & Hegarty, M. (1997). Mental animation in the visuospatial sketchpad: Evidence from dual-task studies. Memory & Cognition, 25(3), 321–332.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sirigu, A., Cohen, L., Duhamel, J.-R., Pillon, B., Dubois, B., & Agid, Y. (1995). A selective impairment of hand posture for object utilization in apraxia. Cortex, 31(1), 41–55.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sirigu, A., Duhamel, J.-R., & Poncet, M. (1991). The role of sensorimotor experience in object recognition: A case of multimodal agnosia. Brain, 114(6), 2555–2573.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Spatt, J., Bak, T., Bozeat, S., Patterson, K., & Hodges, J. R. (2002). Apraxia, mechanical problem solving and semantic knowledge. Journal of Neurology, 249(5), 601–608.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stanley, J. (2011). Know how. Oxford University Press.

  • Stanley, J., & Williamson, T. (2001). Knowing how. Journal of Philosophy, 98(8), 411–444.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Strawson, G. (2010). Mental reality (representation and mind). MIT Press.

  • Weiskopf, D. (2015). Observational concepts. In: The Conceptual Mind: New Directions in the Study of Concepts (pp. 223–247).

  • Weiskopf, D. A. (2020). Anthropic concepts. Noûs, 54(2), 451–468.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wermter, S., Palm, G., & Elshaw, M. (2005). Biomimetic neural learning for intelligent robots: Intelligent systems, cognitive robotics, and neuroscience, (Vol. 3575). Springer.

  • Wheaton, L. A., & Hallett, M. (2007). Ideomotor apraxia: A review. Journal of the neurological sciences, 260(1–2), 1–10.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wilson, M. (2001). The case for sensorimotor coding in working memory. Psychonomic bulletin & review, 8(1), 44–57.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Zalta, E. (2001). Fregean senses, modes of presentation, and concepts. Philosophical Perspectives, 15, 335–359.

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Carlotta Pavese.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

I’d like to thank John Krakauer for many discussions over the years on ideo-motor apraxia and its relevance for my project. I am very grateful to Ian Robertson, Daniel Hutto, Wayne Christensen, Shaun Gallagher, Katsunori Miyahara, as well as the other participants of the Mind in Skilled Performance conference at the University of Wollongong in February 2020 for helpful feedback on the talk on which this paper is based. I am grateful to Sara Aronowitz for discussion and helpful comments on an earlier draft. The comments of two anonymous reviewers were also very helpful. Finally, I am grateful to the Center of Human Abilities for a fellowship that partly supported this research.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Pavese, C. Practical concepts and productive reasoning. Synthese 199, 7659–7688 (2021). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-021-03132-5

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-021-03132-5

Keywords

Navigation