Skip to main content
Log in

Proving quadratic reciprocity: explanation, disagreement, transparency and depth

  • Published:
Synthese Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Gauss’s quadratic reciprocity theorem is among the most important results in the history of number theory. It’s also among the most mysterious: since its discovery in the late eighteenth century, mathematicians have regarded reciprocity as a deeply surprising fact in need of explanation. Intriguingly, though, there’s little agreement on how the theorem is best explained. Two quite different kinds of proof are most often praised as explanatory: an elementary argument that gives the theorem an intuitive geometric interpretation, due to Gauss and Eisenstein, and a sophisticated proof using algebraic number theory, due to Hilbert. Philosophers have yet to look carefully at such explanatory disagreements in mathematics. I do so here. According to the view I defend, there are two important explanatory virtues—depth and transparency—which different proofs (and other potential explanations) possess to different degrees. Although not mutually exclusive in principle, the packages of features associated with the two stand in some tension with one another, so that very deep explanations are rarely transparent, and vice versa. After developing the theory of depth and transparency and applying it to the case of quadratic reciprocity, I draw some morals about the nature of mathematical explanation.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Fig. 1
Fig. 2
Fig. 3
Fig. 4

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Lemmermeyer (2000) is a thorough and useful entry point to this literature.

  2. See Gray (2015) (on QR as an example of deep mathematics), Tappenden (2008) (on the naturalness of the Legendre symbol, and on the importance and mysteriousness of QR generally), and Yap (2011) (on the usefulness of Gauss’s congruence notation for proving QR).

  3. A handful of noteworthy examples, in chronological order: Steiner (1978), Resnik and Kushner (1987), Hafner and Mancosu (2005), Tappenden (2005), Mancosu (2008), Lange (2009), Frans and Weber (2014), Lange (2014), Pincock (2015), Inglis and Mejía-Ramos (2019) and D’Alessandro (2020). Some of these and other works on mathematical explanation are discussed below, especially in Sects. 3 to 5.

  4. A recent exception is Colyvan et al. (2018), which discusses a disagreement about how best to explain the free group theorem. Colyvan et al. suggest that there are at least two fundamentally different ways for a proof to be explanatory; they call the relevant properties “abstractness” and “constructiveness”, although neither these qualities nor their connection to explanation are analyzed in much detail.

  5. I mostly follow Cox (2013) for this history. Ireland and Rosen (1990), Frei (1994) and Baumgart (2015) are also useful guides to various aspects of QR, and the compendious Lemmermeyer (2000) contains a great many further references.

  6. Legendre (1830), p. 230.

  7. A referee worries that these questions are predicated on a doubtful assumption about mathematical explanation: namely, that every mathematical fact has a unique correct explanation. As the referee points out, this claim seems false. Some mathematical facts seem not to have any explanation at all. And others seem to have more than one good explanation.

    One could take this worry in two ways. The first interpretation is that I myself appear to be committed to the above assumptions. In fact, I’m not: I reject both the existence claim and the uniqueness claim. In particular, I don’t assume at the outset that we have explained or can explain QR, or that QR must have a single correct explanation if it has any. As far as I can tell, I haven’t said anything that presupposes or appears to endorse either claim.

    The second interpretation is that the doubtful assumptions are made by the mathematicians whose views on QR are at issue. Perhaps the worry is that, if the disagreement about QR is based on mistaken endorsement of a false theory of explanation, then the disagreement ceases to look very interesting: rather than bothering ourselves about the details of these mathematicians’ views, we should just note their incorrect starting point and pay the controversy no further mind. I have two replies. First, it’s unclear that the QR debate would be uninteresting even if it partly depended on false assumptions. Second and more importantly, I see no reason to think that these mathematicians actually do endorse either the existence or uniqueness claim in general. As I show below, some of them do accept one kind of proof as explanatory and reject another kind as unexplanatory. But this isn’t inherently problematic. The claim that one has an explanation for QR doesn’t imply that every mathematical fact has an explanation. The claim that a certain purported explanation is unacceptable doesn’t imply that QR can have only one correct explanation. And even the claim that QR does have only one correct explanation doesn’t imply that this is true of every mathematical fact. So I don’t think the disagreement about QR is based on an obvious mistake of the above sort. Neither version of the worry, then, appears to be a real problem.

  8. To be clear, the meaning I’m giving to ‘transparent’ should be understood as somewhat stipulative. Although it’s compatible with (and inspired by) the way many mathematicians use the term, I’m not claiming that my definition exactly captures what they all have in mind. Indeed, there’s probably some variation in different authors’ understanding of transparency.

  9. An infamous example is Don Zagier’s “one-sentence proof” that every prime congruent to 1 modulo 4 is a sum of two squares (Zagier 1990).

  10. See for instance Grimm (2010), Inglis and Mejía-Ramos (2019), Khalifa (2013), Wilkenfeld (2014), Turri (2015) and Waskan et al. (2015).

  11. In a similar vein, I’ve argued in D’Alessandro (2020) that some explanations aren’t grounded in objective dependence relations, and that some type of epistemic or cognitive account of explanation may be the best alternative.

  12. Thanks in part to a 2015 special issue of Philosophia Mathematica on mathematical depth (Vol. 23, No. 2).

  13. See D’Alessandro (2018) for a sustained argument that the reduction of arithmetic to set theory isn’t explanatory.

  14. “The choice of this lake—the largest and deepest freshwater reservoir in the world—was determined by the high transparency of its water, its depth, and the ice cover that allows the installation of deep-water equipment during two months in winter” (Domogatsky 2015, p. 23).

  15. The argument was Gauss’s third published proof, but the fifth proof he discovered. The conventional numbering of Gauss’s proofs is based on the order of publication.

  16. Gauss’s lemma is the following statement, which is used in quite a few proofs of quadratic reciprocity. Let p be an odd prime and let a be an integer coprime to p. Consider the residues a (mod p), 2a (mod p), 3a (mod p), \(\ldots \) , \(\left( \frac{p-1}{2}\right) a\) (mod p). (These are all distinct.) Suppose that n of these residues are greater than p/2. Then, writing \(\left( \frac{a}{p}\right) \) for the Legendre symbol, we have \(\left( \frac{a}{p}\right) =\left( -1\right) ^{n}\).

  17. I.e., so that the sum of an even and an odd parity is odd, and the sum of two odd or even parities is even.

  18. Artin reciprocity says that two algebraic objects—the abelianization of a certain kind of Galois group, and a certain kind of idele class group—are isomorphic. Defining these groups in a precise way would take quite a few layers of definitions.

  19. For the record, Steiner’s theory claims that a proof is explanatory when it’s “deformable” in a certain respect, while Kitcher’s account is a mathematical application of his well-known unificationist theory of scientific explanation. Some philosophers remain sympathetic to modified or restricted versions of these views. For instance, Weber and Verhoeven (2002) develop an amended Steinerian account that’s only intended to handle certain kinds of explanatory proof. And Tappenden (2005) is a sympathetic exploration of the idea that unification promotes explanation in mathematics. See D’Alessandro (2019) for more on Steiner’s and Kitcher’s views and their respective receptions.

References

  • Aigner, M., & Zeigler, G. M. (2010). Proofs from the book (4th ed.). Berlin: Springer.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Arana, A. (2015). On the depth of Szemerédi’s theorem. Philosophia Mathematica, 23, 163–176.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Baumgart, O. (2015). The quadratic reciprocity law: A collection of classical proofs (F. Lemmermeyer, Ed. and Trans.). Heidelberg: Birkhäuser.

  • Booß-Bavnbek, B., & Wojciechowski, K. P. (1993). Elliptic boundary problems for dirac operators. New York: Springer.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Cassels, J. W. S. (1950). The rational solutions of the diophantine equation. Acta Mathematica, 82, 243–273.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Colyvan, M. (2012). An introduction to the philosophy of mathematics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Colyvan, M., Cusbert, J., & McQueen, K. J. (2018). Two flavours of mathematical explanation. In A. Reutlinger & J. Saatsi (Eds.), Explanation beyond causation: Philosophical perspectives on non-causal explanations (pp. 231–249). New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cox, D. A. (2013). Primes of the form\(x^{2}+ny^{2}\): Fermat, class field theory, and complex multiplication (2nd ed.). New York: Wiley.

  • D’Alessandro, W. (2018). Arithmetic, set theory, reduction and explanation. Synthese, 195, 5059–5089.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • D’Alessandro, W. (2019). Explanation in mathematics: Proofs and practice. Philosophy Compass,. https://doi.org/10.1111/phc3.12629.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • D’Alessandro, W. (2020). Viewing-as explanations and ontic dependence. Philosophical Studies, 177, 769–792.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Di Bucchianico, A., & Loeb, D. E. (1998). Natural exponential families and umbral calculus. In B. E. Sagan & R. P. Stanley (Eds.), Mathematical essays in honor of Gian-Carlo Rota (pp. 195–212). Boston: Birkhäuser.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Domogatsky, G. (2015). A new neutrino telescope for Lake Baikal. CERN Courier, 55, 23–24.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dudley, U. (2009). A guide to elementary number theory. Washington, D.C: Mathematical Association of America.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Edwards, H. M. (1977). Fermat’s last theorem: A genetic introduction to algebraic number theory. New York: Springer.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Frans, J., & Weber, E. (2014). Mechanistic explanation and explanatory proofs in mathematics. Philosophia Mathematica, 22, 231–248.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Frei, G. (1994). The reciprocity law from Euler to Eisenstein. In S. Chikara, S. Mitsuo, & J. W. Dauben (Eds.), The intersection of history and mathematics (pp. 67–90). Basel: Birkhäuser Verlag.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Garrett, P. (2005). Cryptographic primitives. In P. Garrett & D. Lieman (Eds.), Public-key cryptography (pp. 1–62). Providence, RI: American Mathematical Society.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Gauss, C. F. (1863). Werke (Vol. II). Göttingen: Königlichen Gesellschaft der Wissenschaften.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gauss, C. F. (1966). Disquisitiones arithmeticae (English edition, A. A. Clarke, Trans). New York: Springer.

  • Givental, A. (2006). The Pythagorean theorem: What is it about? American Mathematical Monthly, 113, 261–265.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gouvêa, F. Q. (2015). Review of The quadratic reciprocity law: A collection of classical proofs, by Oswald Baumgart (F. Lemmermeyer, Ed. and Trans.). MAA Reviews, June 30, 2015, online at https://www.maa.org/press/maa-reviews/the-quadratic-reciprocity-law-a-collection-of-classical-proofs.

  • Gowers, T. (2000). The two cultures of mathematics. In V. Arnold, M. Atiyah, P. Lax, & B. Mazur (Eds.), Mathematics: Frontiers and perspectives (pp. 65–78). Providence, RI: American Mathematical Society.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gowers, T. (2008). Mathematics, memory and mental arithmetic. In M. Leng, A. Paseau, & M. Potter (Eds.), Mathematical knowledge (pp. 33–58). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gray, J. (2015). Depth—A Gaussian tradition in mathematics. Philosophia Mathematica, 23, 177–195.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gray, J. (2018). A history of abstract algebra: From algebraic equations to modern algebra. Cham: Springer.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Grimm, S. R. (2010). The goal of explanation. Studies in the History and Philosophy of Science, 41, 337–344.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hafner, J., & Paolo, M. (2005). The varieties of mathematical explanation. In P. Mancosu, K. Frovin Jørgensen, & S. A. Pedersen (Eds.), Visualization, explanation and reasoning styles in mathematics (pp. 215–250). Berlin: Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Hanna, G. (2018). Reflections on proof as explanation. In A. G. Stylianides & G. Harel (Eds.), Advances in mathematics education research on proof and proving: An international perspective (pp. 3–18). Cham: Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Hardy, G. H. (2012). A mathematician’s apology. New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Harriss, E. O. (2006). Review of “The Pythagorean theorem: What is it about?”, by Alexander Givental. Mathematical Reviews, MathSciNet, MR2204490.

  • Hecke, E. (1981). Lectures on the theory of algebraic numbers (G. U. Brauer & J. R. Goldman, Trans.). New York: Springer.

  • Hilbert, D. (1998). The theory of algebraic number fields (I. T. Adamson, Trans.). Berlin: Springer.

  • Inglis, M., & Mejía-Ramos, J. P. (2019). Functional explanation in mathematics. Synthese,. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-019-02234-5.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ioffe, A. D. (2000). Review of A. A. Milyutin and N. P. Osmolovskii, Calculus of variations and optimal control. In D. G. Babbitt & J. E. Kister (Eds.), Featured reviews in mathematical reviews, 1997–1999 (pp. E63–E64). Providence, RI: American Mathematical Society.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ireland, K., & Rosen, M. (1990). A classical introduction to modern number theory (2nd ed.). New York: Springer.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Janusz, G. J. (1996). Algebraic number fields (2nd ed.). Providence, RI: American Mathematical Society.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kazdan, J. L. (1981). Another proof of Bianchi’s identity in Riemannian geometry. Proceedings of the American Mathematical Society, 81, 341–342.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kedlaya, K. S. (2008). From quadratic reciprocity to class field theory. In T. Gowers, J. Barrow-Green, & I. Leader (Eds.), The princeton companion to mathematics (pp. 39–42). Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kelp, C. (2016). Towards a knowledge-based account of understanding. In S. R. Grimm, C. Baumberger, & S. Ammon (Eds.), Explaining understanding: New perspectives from epistemology and philosophy of science (pp. 251–271). London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Khalifa, K. (2013). The role of explanation in understanding. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 64, 161–187.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kitcher, P. (1989). Explanatory unification and the causal structure of the world. In P. Kitcher & W. Salmon (Eds.), Scientific explanation (Minnesota studies in the philosophy of science) (Vol. XIII, pp. 410–505). Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Knuuttila, T., & Merz, M. (2009). Understanding by modeling: An objectual approach. In H. W. De Regt, S. Leonelli, & K. Eigner (Eds.), Scientific understanding: Philosophical perspectives (pp. 146–168). Pittsburgh, PA: University of Pittsburgh Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Koch, H. (1991). Introduction to classical mathematics I: From the quadratic reciprocity law to the uniformization theorem (J. Stillwell, Trans.). Dordrecht: Springer.

  • Lange, M. (2009). Why proofs by mathematical induction are generally not explanatory. Analysis, 69, 203–211.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lange, M. (2014). Aspects of mathematical explanation: Symmetry, unity, and salience. Philosophical Review, 123, 485–531.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lange, M. (2015). Depth and explanation in mathematics. Philosophia Mathematica, 23, 196–214.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lange, M. (2016). Because without cause: Non-causal explanations in science and mathematics. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Lauenbacher, R. C., & Pengelley, D. J. (1994). Eisenstein’s misunderstood geometric proof of the quadratic reciprocity theorem. College Mathematics Journal, 25, 29–34.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Legendre, A.-M. (1830). Théorie des nombres (3rd ed., Vol. 1). Paris: Duprat.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lemmermeyer, F. (2000). Reciprocity laws: From Euler to Eisenstein. Berlin: Springer.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Lemmermeyer, F. (2019). “Proofs of the quadratic reciprocity law.” Online at http://www.rzuser.uni-heidelberg.de/~hb3/rchrono.html. Accessed 18 June 2019.

  • Mancosu, P. (2008). Mathematical explanation: Why it matters. In P. Mancosu (Ed.), The philosophy of mathematical practice (pp. 134–150). New York: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Manin, Y., & Panchishkin, A. (2005). Introduction to modern number theory: Fundamental problems, ideas and theories (2nd ed.). Springer: Berlin.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • McLarty, C. (2007). The rising sea: Grothendieck on simplicity and generality. In J. J. Gray & K. H. Parshall (Eds.), Episodes in the history of modern algebra (1800–1950). Providence, RI: American Mathematical Society.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nadler, S. B. (2010). A proof of Darboux’s theorem. American Mathematical Monthly, 117, 174–175.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Narins, B. (Ed.). (2001). World of mathematics (Vol. 1). New York: Gale Group.

    Google Scholar 

  • Neukirch, J. (1999). Algebraic number theory (N. Schappacher, Trans.). Berlin: Springer.

  • Pincock, C. (2015). The unsolvability of the quintic: A case study in abstract mathematical explanation. Philosophers’ Imprint, 15(3), 1–19.

    Google Scholar 

  • Raatikainen, P. (2018). “Gödel’s incompleteness theorems.” In E. N. Zalta (Ed.), The stanford encyclopedia of philosophy (Fall 2018 Edition). https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2018/entries/goedel-incompleteness/.

  • Raman-Sundström, M. (2016). The notion of fit as a mathematical value. In B. Larvor (Ed.), Mathematical cultures: The London meetings 2012–2014 (pp. 271–286). Cham: Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Raman-Sundström, M., & Öhman, L.-D. (2016). Mathematical fit: A case study. Philosophia Mathematica, 26, 184–210.

    Google Scholar 

  • Resnik, M. D., & Kushner, D. (1987). Explanation, independence and realism in mathematics. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 38, 141–158.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rogawski, J. (2000). The nonabelian reciprocity law for local fields. Notices of the AMS, 47, 35–41.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rousseau, G. (1991). On the quadratic reciprocity law. Journal of the Australian Mathematical Society (Series A), 51, 423–425.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rowe, D. E. (1988). Gauss, Dirichlet, and the law of biquadratic reciprocity. Mathematical Intelligencer, 10, 13–26.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Samuel, P. (1970). Algebraic theory of numbers (A. J. Silberger, Trans.). Paris: Hermann.

  • Severini, T. A. (2005). Elements of distribution theory. New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Shanks, D. (1978). Solved and unsolved problems in number theory (2nd ed.). New York: Chelsea Publishing Company.

    Google Scholar 

  • Smith, D. E. (1959). A source book in mathematics (Vol. 1). New York: Dover.

    Google Scholar 

  • Smith, H. J. S. (1894). The collected mathematical papers of Henry John Stephen Smith, (Vol. I), ed. J.W.L. Glaisher. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

  • Stanley, R. P. (2012). Enumerative Combinatorics (2nd ed., Vol. I). New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Steiner, M. (1978). Mathematical explanation. Philosophical Studies, 34, 135–151.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stillwell, J. (2015). What does ‘depth’ mean in mathematics? Philosophia Mathematica, 23, 215–232.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Swan, R. G. (1963). An application of graph theory to algebra. Proceedings of the American Mathematical Society, 14, 367–373.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tangedal, B. A. (2000). Eisenstein’s lemma and quadratic reciprocity for Jacobi symbols. Mathematics Magazine, 73, 130–134.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tappenden, J. (2005). Proof style and understanding in mathematics I: Visualization, unification and axiom choice. In P. Mancosu, K. Jørgensen, & S. Pedersen (Eds.), Visualization, explanation and reasoning styles in mathematics. Berlin: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tappenden, J. (2008). Mathematical concepts and definitions. In P. Mancosu (Ed.), The philosophy of mathematical practice (pp. 256–275). New York: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Trout, J. D. (2002). Scientific explanation and the sense of understanding. Philosophy of Science, 69, 212–233.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Turri, J. (2015). Understanding and the norm of explanation. Philosophia, 43, 1171–1175.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Urquhart, A. (2015). Mathematical depth. Philosophia Mathematica, 23, 233–241.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Waskan, J., Harmon, I., Horne, Z., Spino, J., & Clevenger, J. (2014). Explanatory anti-psychologism overturned by lay and scientific case classifications. Synthese, 191, 1013–1035.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Weber, E., & Verhoeven, L. (2002). Explanatory proofs in mathematics. Logique at Analyse, 179–180, 299–307.

    Google Scholar 

  • Weyl, H. (1968). Algebraic theory of numbers. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wilkenfeld, D. A. (2014). Functional explaining: A new approach to the philosophy of explanation. Synthese, 191, 3367–3391.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Yap, A. (2011). Gauss’ quadratic reciprocity theorem and mathematical fruitfulness. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science, 42, 410–415.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Zagier, D. (1990). A one-sentence proof that every prime \(p\equiv 1\) (mod \(4\)) is a sum of two squares. American Mathematical Monthly, 97, 144.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

An earlier version of this paper was my MS thesis in mathematics at the University of Illinois at Chicago. I’m grateful to my advisor, Ramin Takloo-Bighash, and my other committee members, Nathan Jones and Jamie Tappenden, for their help and support. Thanks especially to Ramin, who introduced me to quadratic reciprocity and whose faith, advice and good cheer were invaluable over the many months I worked on this project. Thanks to Dick Gross, Jordan Ellenberg and Keith Conrad for correspondence with Ramin and I about proofs of QR. Many thanks to Marc Lange for his characteristically perceptive and generous comments and for his ongoing support. Many thanks as well to Kenny Easwaran and the Texas A&M philosophy and math departments for their hospitality. As usual, Daniel Sutherland and Lauren Woomer gave me helpful feedback. Finally, thanks to the 2019 Midwest Philosophy of Mathematics Workshop participants—including John Baldwin, Paddy Blanchette, Bernd Buldt, Curtis Franks, Doug Marshall, Rebecca Morris, Daniel Nolan, Patrick Ryan, and Susan Vineberg—for their comments, discussion and encouragement.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to William D’Alessandro.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

D’Alessandro, W. Proving quadratic reciprocity: explanation, disagreement, transparency and depth. Synthese 198, 8621–8664 (2021). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-020-02591-6

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-020-02591-6

Keywords

Navigation